Skip to main content
Log in

A Matricial Vue of Classical Syllogistic and an Extension of the Rules of Valid Syllogism to Rules of Conclusive Syllogisms with Indefinite Terms

  • Published:
Journal of Logic, Language and Information Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One lists the distinct pairs of categorical premises (PCPs) formulable via only the positive terms, S,P,M, by constructing a six by six matrix obtained by pairing the six categorical P-premises, A(P,M), O(P,M), A(M,P*), O(M,P*), where P* ∈ {P,P′}, with the six, similar, categorical S-premises. One shows how five rules of valid syllogism (RofVS), select only 15 distinct PCPs that entail logical consequences (LCs) belonging to the set L+: = {A(P,S), O(P,S), A(S,P), E(S,P), O(S,P), I(S,P)}. The choice of admissible LCs can be regarded as a condition separated from the conditions (or axioms) contained in the RofVS: the usual eight (Boolean) PCPs that generate valid syllogisms are obtained when the only admissible LCs belong to the set L: = {A(S,P), E(S,P), O(S,P), I(S,P)} and no existential imports are addressed. A 64 PCP-matrix obtains when both PCPs and LCs may contain indefinite terms—the positive, S,P,M, terms, and their complementary sets, S′,P′, M′, in the universe of discourse, U, called the negative terms. Now one can accept eight LCs: A(S*,P*), I(S*,P*), where P* ∈ {P,P′}, S* ∈ {S,S′}, and there are 32 conclusive PCPs, entailing precise, “one partitioning subset of U” LCs. The four rules of conclusive syllogisms (RofCS) predict the less precise LCs, left after eliminating the middle term from the exact LCs. The RofCS also predict that the other 32 PCPs of the 64 PCP-matrix are non-conclusive. The RofVS and the RofCS are generalized, and arguments are given, for also accepting as valid syllogisms the conclusive syllogisms formulable via positive terms which entail the LCs A(P,S) and O(P,S).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Alvarez, E., & Correia, M. (2012). Syllogistic with Indefinite Terms. History and Philosophy of Logic, 33(4), 297–306. https://doi.org/10.1080/01445340.2012.680704

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez-Fontecilla, E. (2016). Canonical syllogistic moods in traditional Aristotelian logic. Logica Universalis, 10(4), 517–531. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-016-0156-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez-Fontecilla, E., & Tomas, L. (2019). Aristotelian logic axioms in propositional logic: The pouch method. History and Philosophy of Logic, 40(1), 12–21. https://doi.org/10.1080/01445340.2018.1442172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, L. (1986). Symbolic logic. Reprinted part I elementary, 1896. Fifth edition. Part II, advanced, never previously published. Edited, with annotations and an introduction by William Warren Bartley III. Reprinted edition. Clark son Potter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copi, I. M., Cohen, C., & McMahon, K. (2014). Introduction to logic (14th ed.). Pearson Education Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correia, M. (2017). The proto-exposition of aristotelian categorical logic. In J.-Y. Béziau & G. Basti (Eds.), The square of opposition: A cornerstone of thought. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Morgan, A. (1860). Syllabus of a proposed system of logic. Walton and Maberly.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, P. J. (2015). A concise introduction to logic (12th ed.). Cengage Learning.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jevons, W. S. (2019). The substitution of similars, the true principle of reasoning, derived from a modification of Aristotle’s dictum. Macmillan and Co., London (1869). Wentworth Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J. N. (1884). Studies and exercises in formal logic (4th ed.). Macmillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radulescu, D. C. (2021). Variation and pattern in the 3-term syllogisms and biliteral sorites of types Barbara, Darapti and Darii. Journal of Applied Logics, 9(7), 1953–1975.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stebbing, L. S. (1961). A Modern Introduction to Logic (1st ed.). Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Striker, G. (2009). Aristotle’s prior analytics book I. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, J. (1932). Negative terms in traditional logic: Distribution, immediate infer ence, and syllogism. The Monist, 42(1), 96–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dan Constantin Radulescu.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no conflict of interest to declare that are relevant to the content of this article.

Ethical Approval

The research for this article did not involve any Ethical approval from anybody; no Ethical approval is applicable for this article.

Informed Consent

The research for this article did not involve asking for an Informed consent from anybody—only the author did the research.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

To the memory of my beloved ones: Alexandra, Lidia, Constantin and Cristina.

Dan Constantin Radulescu—Retired.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Radulescu, D.C. A Matricial Vue of Classical Syllogistic and an Extension of the Rules of Valid Syllogism to Rules of Conclusive Syllogisms with Indefinite Terms. J of Log Lang and Inf 31, 465–491 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-022-09362-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-022-09362-1

Keywords

Navigation