Skip to main content
Log in

Categorical Monism, Laws, and the Inference Problem

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A well-known difficulty that affects all accounts of laws of nature according to which the latter are higher-order facts involving relations between universals (the so-called DTA accounts, from Dretske in Philosophy of Science 44:248–268, 1977; Tooley in Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7:667–698, 1977 and Armstrong (What is a Law of Nature?, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983)) is the Inference Problem: how can laws construed in that way determine the first-order regularities that we find in the actual world? Bird (Analysis 65:147–55, 2005) has argued that there is no solution to the Inference Problem which is consistent with both categorical monism (that is, the view that all natural properties are categorical) and basic tenets of Armstrong’s account of the laws of nature. This paper shows that, given Armstrong’s view about laws as first-order structural universals whose instantiation ‘produce’ nomic regularities and under specific plausible metaphysical assumptions concerning nomic relations which are consistent with a broadly construed DTA approach to laws, there is no extra difficulty regarding the Inference Problem in a categorical monistic context besides the ones that beset structural universals in general.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The inference is taken to be an entailment that strictly holds only for deterministic and exceptionless laws.

  2. In his (1989, 96), van Fraassen has also presented the so-called Identification Problem which, in rough terms, concerns the identification of a proper entity that can play the governing role of N.

  3. As I will mention in the sequel, this characterisation cannot be construed as implying that under any conception of structural universals the latter are literally composed by other simpler universals. Structural universals ‘involve’ their ‘constituents’ at least in the minimal sense that there are necessary connections between their instances and the instances of their ‘constituents’.

  4. Nevertheless, for a defence of indiscernible universals, see Rodriguez-Pereyra (2017).

  5. For a proposal of how this can be done, see Bennett (2013).

  6. In contrast to that move, Hawley (2010) proposes a pictorialist mereological account of structural universals (for a critique, see Azzano 2021).

  7. For a useful review of the main arguments, see Fisher (2018).

  8. For Armstrong, the fundamental ontological units are states of affairs. Universals are state-of-affairs types: that is, abstractions in which particulars have been ‘eliminated’ from states of affairs.

  9. Bolender explains: “Armstrong’s point is that a causal relation between particulars instantiates a structural property. For example, states of affairs of the form A-caused-B are particulars (thick particulars) instantiating structural properties of a temporal sort. It is the nature of a causal sequence to instantiate a special kind of structural property, one in which the structure unfolds through time just as a flag (with a design on it) or a molecule is an instantiation of a structural property in which the structure is extended through space. In some cases, these particular causal relations essentially involve structural extension through time and in some cases they do not, but they are in all cases structures.” (2006, 407).

  10. According to Lewis (1999, 89), we should reject the linguistic conception for all structural universals on the grounds that it cannot accommodate the possibility of infinite complexity in the world (that is, the possibility that there are no simples).

  11. Perhaps, however, one could provide an essentialist explanation of this fact. For further discussion, see Sect. 6.

  12. To avoid misunderstandings, Coates herself does not suggest that. Her suggestion is that it is the nomic necessitation relation N that may have as a matter of brute fact the necessary property of being such that if it relates F and G then R(F,G) (2021, 927). Furthermore, although that at this point we appeal to Coates’ view in the case of simple categorical properties, there is nothing regarding the view itself that would prohibit its application in the case of complex categorical properties.

  13. In the recent literature, the concept of metaphysical explanation is most often related to grounding. For the purposes of this paper, a less specific notion of metaphysical explanation is sufficient. According to this conception, an explanation is metaphysical if its explanans involves ‘pure’ metaphysical notions such as essences, relations of ontological dependency, etc. Given that, the metaphysical explanation can be seen as a family of kinds of explanation which includes (perhaps among others) the grounding explanation.

  14. For an akin proposal, where the entailment in question is the strict implication from laws to corresponding regularities, see Wilsch (2021). Hireche et al. (2021) propose that it is part of the nature of the nomic relation N that it gives rise to the corresponding regularities. In their words: “It is essential to N that, if F stands in the relation N to G, then everything which is F is G.” (2021, 10, 228). Note however that this proposal concerns the essence of N, not the essence of laws whose ‘constituent’ is N.

  15. The adicity of a first-order universal is the number of ‘slots’ that need to be filled by particulars in order for an instance of the universal to exist. Properties of objects are monadic universals (they have adicity 1), whereas relations among objects are polyadic universals (they have adicity greater than or equal to 2). The definition of adicity can be generalised for universals of any order n: the adicity of a universal of order n is the number of ‘slots’ that need to be filled by entities of order n-1 in order for an each instance of the universal to exist.

  16. For a discussion of this issue in the case of powerful qualities, see Livanios (2021).

  17. According to Bird, powers are fundamental natural properties that have dispositional essences.

  18. Coates scrutinizes the idea that the nomic necessitation relation N (not the law N(F, G) itself) can essentially be such that if it relates F and G, then R(F,G) and finds it wanting for the same reason: “Indeed, it is possible for N to be instantiated without F or G being instantiated at all, as well as for F or G to be instantiated without N being instantiated. Consequently, that N stands in an essential connection with F and G cannot be explained by N’s having F and G as constituents.” (2021, 926).

  19. The notion of the relata-specific first-order relation has been used by Weiland and Betti (2008) to account for the unity of first-order facts. Livanios (2012) has suggested that relata-specificity is an essential characteristic of external second-order nomic relations (see also Ioannidis et al. 2021).

  20. It is interesting to note that Armstrong himself allows the existence of more than one type of nomic relations (nomic necessitation, nomic probabilification and perhaps nomic exclusion) in order to accommodate all possible laws of nature. (In fact, under a specific interpretation of his account of probabilistic laws, the number of distinct nomic/causal relations is the same as the number of laws with different objective probabilities of being instantiated in favourable conditions, see Jacobs and Hartman 2017). He does not however hold that each fundamental law involves a distinct nomic relation.

  21. Bartels (2019) argues that these ‘laws’ are not counterexamples to the causal interpretation of laws of nature. For him, the lawful status belongs to types of interactions which are represented by specific Lagrangians and the equations of motion derived from them. Furthermore, the modal force that characterised laws is grounded in the contingent fact that their causal productivity is stable on the basis of their mutual independence. Constraint and composition ‘laws’, as well as the symmetry principles (both global and local), are not laws in Bartels’ sense.

  22. Armstrong’s view is not the only DTA account that has failed to provide an adequate and illuminating answer to the Identification Problem. Tooley (1987) suggested two ways to solve the problem (the account by stipulation and the speculative account) which are both problematic. The latter proposal has been severely criticised by Sider (1992) and Hildebrand (2013) and Tooley himself (1987, 127) admitted that the former is inadequate on the grounds that it gives no account of the intrinsic nature of nomic relations. (I would add that even if the proposed account were to offer an illuminating view about the nature of nomic relations, it would certainly give no metaphysically illuminating ‘solution’ to the Inference Problem given that the crucial entailment that raises the problem is included by definition in the functional role of any relation that according to Tooley would legitimately be called nomic.) According to Dretske (1977), laws are the relationships between properties or magnitudes that are asserted to exist by true law-like statements which are singular statements of fact. The nomic relation between properties F and G (symbolised as F − > G) is an extensional relation between those properties, with the terms “F-ness” and “G-ness” occupying transparent positions. Beyond that, however, no extra information is given regarding the nature of nomic relations. As Dretske himself admits: “I attach no special significance to the connective→. I use it here merely as a dummy connective or relation. The kind of connection asserted to exist between the universals in question will depend on the particular law in question, and it will vary depending on whether the law involves quantitative or merely qualitative expressions”.

  23. According to the composition-as-identity view for a structural universal, the latter is identical to the plurality of universals that compose it. In a weak version of the view, the relation of identity is replaced by another relation of ‘weak identity’ which is sufficiently similar to ‘strict’ identity in the sense that just as in the case of the latter, necessarily, when two properties are related by this identity-like relation they are co-extensional. For details, see Azzano (2021).

References

  • Armstrong, D.M. 1983. What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. 1988. Reply to van Fraassen. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (2): 224–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. 1993. The identification problem and the inference problem. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LIII (2): 421–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. 1997. A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. 2010. Sketch for a systematic metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Azzano, L. 2021. Structural properties, mereology, and modal magic. Synthese 198 (Suppl. 18): S4303–S4329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, S., and B. Smart. 2012. The ultimate argument against dispositional monist accounts of laws. Analysis 72 (4): 714–722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. 2018. Symmetric dependence. In Reality and its structure, ed. Ricki Bliss and Graham. Priest, 50–69. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartels, A. 2019. Explaining the modal force of natural laws. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 9: 6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. 2013. Having a part twice over. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (1): 83–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. 2005. The ultimate argument against Armstrong’s contingent necessitation view of laws. Analysis 65 (2): 147–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolender, J. 2006. Nomic universals and particular causal relations: Which are basic and which are derived? Philosophia 34 (4): 405–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. 1994. Laws of nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coates, A. 2021. Essence and the inference problem. Synthese 198: 915–931.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1977. Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science 44: 248–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1985. Review of “What is a law of nature?” by David Armstrong. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (1): 79–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fales, E. 1990. Causation and universals. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, A.R.J. 2018. Structural universals. Philosophy Compass 13 (10) e12518: 1-13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foster, J. 2004. The divine lawmaker. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glazier, M. 2017. Essentialist explanation. Philosophical Studies 174 (11): 2871–2889.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. 2010. Mereology, modality and magic. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88: 117–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrand, T. 2013. Tooley’s account of the necessary connection between law and regularity. Philosophical Studies 166 (1): 33–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hireche, S., N. Linnemann, R. Michels, and L. Vogt. 2021. The strong arm of the law: A unified account of necessary and contingent laws of nature. Synthese 199 (3–4): 10211–10252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ioannidis, S., V. Livanios, and S. Psillos. 2021. No laws and (thin) Powers in, no governing laws out. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 (6): 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, J., and R. Hartman. 2017. Armstrong on probabilistic laws of nature. Philosophical Papers 46 (3): 373–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalhat, J. 2008. Structural universals and the principle of uniqueness of composition. Grazer Philosophische Studien 76: 57–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1983. New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. 1999. Against structural universals. In Papers in metaphysics and epistemology, 78–107. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Livanios, V. 2012. Exploring the metaphysics of nomic relations. Acta Analytica 27: 247–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livanios, V. 2021. Challenging the identity theory of properties. Synthese 199: 5079–5105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pagès, J. 2002. The Dretske-Tooley-Armstrong theory of natural laws and the inference problem. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16: 227–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. 2017. Indiscernible universals. Inquiry 60 (6): 604–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, S. 2001. Alien individuals, alien universals, and Armstrong’s combinatorial theory of possibility. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 39 (4): 575–593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrenk, M. 2011. Interfering with Nomological Necessity. The Philosophical Quarterly 61: 577–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T.R. 1992. Tooley’s solution to the inference problem. Philosophical Studies 67 (3): 261–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, N. 2016. Metaphysical interdependence. In Reality making, ed. Mark Jago, 38–56. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tiles, M. 1985. Review of “What is a law of nature?” by David Armstrong. Philosophy 60 (234): 557–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. 1977. The nature of law. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 667–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. 1987. Causation: A realist approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. 1989. Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weiland, J.W., and A. Betti. 2008. Relata-specific relations: A response to Vallicella. Dialectica 62 (4): 509–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilsch, T. 2021. The governance of laws of nature: Guidance and production. Philosophical Studies 178: 909–933.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. 1987. Review of “What is a law of nature?” by David Armstrong. The Philosophical Review 96 (3): 435–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. 1985. Review of “What is a law of nature?” by David Armstrong. Ethics 95 (4): 949–951.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the 4th conference of East European Network for Philosophy of Science (Tartu 2022) and 6th Italian Conference in Analytic Ontology and Metaphysics (L’Aquila 2022). I would like to thank the participants of both conferences as well as the anonymous referees for their useful comments. This study was funded by A.G. Leventis Foundation (Grant number 912876).

Funding

This study was funded by A.G. Leventis Foundation (912876).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vassilis Livanios.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

Authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Livanios, V. Categorical Monism, Laws, and the Inference Problem. J Gen Philos Sci 54, 599–619 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-023-09638-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-023-09638-5

Keywords

Navigation