Skip to main content
Log in

The Re-distributive Role of Child Benefits Revisited

  • Published:
International Tax and Public Finance Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we reexamine the commonly invoked argument that due to the existence of a negative correlation between earning ability and family size, the latter can be used as a “tagging” device, justifying subsidizing children (via provision of child allowances) to enhance egalitarian objectives. Employing a benchmark setting where the quality–quantity paradigm holds, we show that the case for subsidizing children is far from being a forgone conclusion. We demonstrate that the desirability of subsidizing children crucially hinges on whether benefits are means-tested or are offered on a universal basis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In some countries, such as Israel and most European countries (the notable exception is Italy), child benefits are provided on a universal basis; namely, child benefits do not depend on household’s income (but usually vary with the number of children). In other countries, such as the US and Australia, child benefits are means-tested. In some countries, there are means-tested child benefits on top of universal benefits. In this paper, we draw attention to the importance of distinguishing between a universal and a means-tested system, in analyzing re-distributive policy implications of child benefits.

  2. For evidence of the existence of a quality–quantity trade-off see, e.g., Hanushek (1992).

  3. As differences in earning ability are assumed to be the single source of heterogeneity in the economy, we refrain from introducing horizontal equity considerations into the analysis.

  4. Notice that both \(e\) and \(\alpha \) are measured per capita; hence, there are no economies of scale embodied in the consumption of children. For given levels of child-related consumption, \(e\), and time of attention, \(\alpha \), the cost of provision is increasing in the number of children.

  5. The variable \(e\) is henceforth interpreted as the level of parental provision of child-related consumption goods, such as education (Becker 1991), but may well take additional plausible interpretations, such as the maximized lifetime utility of each child (Becker and Barro 1988). An alternative interpretation of the utility form given in Eq. (1) is that g(\(l\), \(n\),\( e\), \(\alpha ) = \hbox {s}[l, n, x(e,\alpha )]\), where \(x\) denotes the domestic production function of “quality” (child-related consumption) employing parental time as well as market goods such as private tutoring and day-care services as inputs [see Cigno (2001)].

  6. By continuity considerations, provided that the utility function is separable between parental consumption, \(c\), and its other arguments \((l,n,e\hbox { and }\alpha )\), accommodating moderate income effects will not change the qualitative nature of our results.

  7. We acknowledge that parents have less than perfect control over the number of children (by proper choice of intercourse frequency, the use of contraceptives, etc.). For a recent paper that allows households to control only the probability distribution of the number of children, see Cigno and Luporini (2011). For models assuming exogenous fertility see, for instance, Cremer et al. (2003).

  8. Higher skilled households will partially mitigate this by replacing their own time inputs with relatively cheaper outsourced day-care/tutoring services (via choosing to increase \(e\) and decrease \(\alpha \)). We will further discuss this point below.

  9. We will henceforth assume that the second-order conditions are always satisfied, thus employ first-order conditions only to characterize the individual incentive constraints when formulating the government problem. This latter assumption will ensure no “bunching” in the optimal solution of the government problem [see Ebert (1992), for a rigorous treatment of “bunching” in the context of optimal non-linear labor income tax in the continuum case].

  10. Notice that to obtain our qualitative results, all we need is a negative correlation between quantity (number of children) and ability (of parents). Our qualitative results would remain unchanged even if quality were fixed at some exogenous level. In our setting, quality is endogenously determined by the households and quantity and quality are negatively related in the benchmark (no-tax) case, in line with the quality–quantity paradigm.

  11. In a previous version of the paper, we have examined the simpler case where \(\alpha \) is a fixed parameter (rather than being endogenously determined, as we assume). In this case, the negative correlation between the skill level and family size is satisfied with the additively separable functional form, without imposing additional assumptions [see Moav (2005) for a similar setting].

  12. With a bounded skill distribution, the standard efficiency at the top property continues to hold; namely, the marginal tax on children is zero for the top-earning household.

  13. This is essentially the rationale underlying the common use of equivalence scales.

  14. Note that conditioning transfers on family size serves as a second-best “tagging” device because fertility is an endogenous variable in our setting, which responds to financial incentives offered by the government [for recent empirical attempts to estimate the effect of financial incentives on fertility, see Cohen, Dehejia and Romanov (2007) and Laroque and Salanie (2012)].

  15. It is important to emphasize that, in equilibrium, high-ability households will choose to spend more hours in the labor market and raise a lower number of children, relative to low-ability households. However, our argument suggests that if they mimic the low-ability households (an out-of-equilibrium strategy which will not be incentive compatible by construction of our optimal policy rule), then by choosing the same level of income, they will find it relatively cheaper to raise children.

  16. Cigno (2001) and Balestrino and Cigno (2002) demonstrate the “tagging” role played by child benefits.

  17. This observation was first made by Cigno (1986).

  18. Our key assumption, which we find plausible, is that nurturing cannot be entirely outsourced. Hence, to some extent, raising children always requires some parental investment of time (the opportunity cost of which varies across households with different earning abilities).

  19. We will examine, in particular, the desirability of providing a marginal child subsidy, when the labor income tax is set at the optimum. The reason we choose to analyze also the case with an arbitrarily given income tax schedule is in order to highlight the relationship between the shape of the income tax schedule and the desirable properties of the child benefit system. In addition, the exercise may also have some practical implications, as reforms in the child benefit schedule often takes place without being accompanied by adjustments to the income tax schedule (see e.g., a comprehensive child benefit reform that took place in Israel in 2003).

  20. One may argue that, in practice, most income tax systems exhibit marginal tax rate progressivity; namely, the statutory marginal tax rate is rising with (gross) income. However, when the bulk of welfare (transfer) programs are means-tested, the effective marginal tax rate at low levels of gross income is relatively high. Therefore, the integrated tax-transfer system exhibits marginal tax regressivity at the lower end of the income distribution; namely, the effective marginal tax rate is decreasing with (gross) income. Clearly, the marginal tax rates derived in our context are the effective rather than the statutory ones.

  21. Notice the difference between the labor supply elasticity used in condition (14) and the standard elasticity estimated by the voluminous empirical literature, as it takes into account additional factors such as fertility and time dedicated to nurturing children who are related to labor supply decisions. We expect that the magnitude of our extended new notion of labor supply elasticity to be greater than the elasticity provided by the empirical literature (which is fairly small in most studies). We are unable to quantify this magnitude due to lack of empirical evidence.

  22. Notice that over the income-range where the tax rate is optimally set to be flat, the marginal child subsidy is unambiguously negative (that is, a marginal tax). This is in contrast to the general case, where, with an arbitrary flat-rate system in place, we have shown the result to be ambiguous.

References

  • Akerlof, G. (1978). The Economics of Tagging as Applied to the Optimal Income Tax Welfare Programs, and Manpower Planning. American Economic Review, 68, 8–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, A., & Stiglitz, J. (1976). The Design of Tax Structure: Direct versus Indirect Taxation. Journal of Public Economics, 6, 55–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balestrino, A., Cigno, A., & Pettini, A. (2002). Endogenous Fertility and the Design of Family Taxation. International Tax and Public Finance, 9, 175–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balestrino, A., Cigno, A., & Pettini, A. (2003). Doing Wonders with an Egg: Optimal Re-distribution When Households Differ in Market and Non-Market Abilities. Journal of Public Economic Theory, 5, 479–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. (1960). An Economic Analysis of Fertility. In Demographic and Economic Change in Developed Countries, National Bureau of Economic Research Series, Number 11, Princeton (pp. 209–231). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Becker, G. (1991). A Treatise on the Family ( \(2^{nd}\) enlarged edition) (enlarged ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Becker, G., & Barro, R. (1988). A Re-formulation of the Economic Theory of Fertility. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 103, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G., & Lewis, G. (1973). On the Interaction between the Quantity and Quality of Children. Journal of Political Economy, 81, 279–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blundell, R., MaCurdy, T., & Meghir, C. (2007). Labor supply models: Unobserved heterogeneity, nonparticipation and dynamics. In J. J. Heckman & E. E. Leamer (Eds.). Handbook of Econometrics (1st ed.). volume 6, chapter 69 Salt Lake:Elsevier.

  • Borg, M. (1989). The income-fertility relationship: Effect of the net price of a child. Demography, 26, 301–310.

  • Bradshaw, J., Finch, N. (2002). “A Comparison of Child Benefit Packages in 22 Countries”, Department for Work and Pensions Research Report No.174, Corporate Document Services: Leeds.

  • Cigno, A. (1986). Fertility and the Tax-benefit system: A reconsideration of the theory of family taxation. Economic Journal, 96, 1035–1051.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cigno, A. (2001). Comparative advantage, observability, and the optimal tax treatment of families with children. International Tax and Public Finance, 8, 455–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cigno, A. (2011). Agency in family policy: A survey. CESifo Economic Studies, 57, 305–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cigno, A., & Luporini, A. (2011). Optimal family policy in the presence of Moral Hazard when the quantity and quality of children are stochastic. CESifo Economic Studies, 57, 349–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, A., Dehejia, R., & Romanov, D. (2013). Financial incentives and fertility. Review of Economics and Statistics, 95, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cremer, H., Dellis, A., & Pestieau, P. (2003). Family size and optimal income taxation. Journal of Population Economics, 16, 37–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, P. (1998). Optimal income taxation: An example with a U-shaped pattern of optimal marginal tax rates. American Economic Review, 88, 83–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, P., & Saez, E. (2011). The case for a progressive tax: From basic research to policy recommendations. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 25, 165–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Docquier, F. (2004). Income distribution, non-convexities and the fertility-income relationship. Economica, 71, 261–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, U. (1992). A reexamination of the optimal nonlinear income tax. Journal of Public Economics, 49, 47–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanushek, E. (1992). The trade-off between child quantity and quality. Journal of Political Economy, 100, 84–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hotz, V. J., Klerman, J. A., & Willis, R. J. (1997). The Economics of Fertility in Developed Countries. In M. R. Rosenzweig & O. Stark (Eds.), Handbook of Population and Family Economics. Salt Lake: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, L., Tertilt, M. (2013). “An Economic History of Fertility in the U.S.: 1826–1960”. The Handbook of Family Economics, Peter Rupert, (Ed.). forthcoming.

  • Laroque, G., Salanie, B. (2013). “Identifying the Response of Fertility to Financial Incentives”. forthcoming Journal of Applied Econometrics.

  • Mirrlees, J. (1971). An exploration in the theory of optimum income taxation. Review of Economic Studies, 38, 175–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moav, O. (2005). Cheap children and the persistence of poverty. Economic Journal, 115, 88–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piketty, T., & Saez, E. (2013). A theory of optimal inheritance taxation. Econometrica, 81(1851–1886), 09.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saez, E. (2001). Using elasticities to derive optimal income tax rates. Review of Economic Studies, 68, 205–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saez, E. (2002). Optimal income transfer programs: Intensive versus extensive labor supply responses. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117, 1039–1073.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salanie, B. (2003). The Economics of Taxation. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strulik, H., & Sikandar, S. (2002). Tracing the income-fertility nexus: Nonparametric estimates for a panel of countries. Economics Bulletin, 15, 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Efraim Sadka.

Additional information

The authors wish to thank the editor and two anonymous referees for helpful comments. The usual disclaimer applies. The first author wishes to dedicate the paper to his late and much loved father who succumbed to cancer shortly after this project was initiated.

Appendices

Appendix A: the additively separable case

We show that in the absence of taxes (\(z_n =0\hbox { and }z_y =1)\) when the utility in (1) is taking an additively separable form, \(g(l,n,e,\alpha )=\psi (l)+v(n)+u(e)+\Phi (\alpha )\) and, in addition, satisfies the property that \(-\alpha \cdot \Phi ^{\prime \prime }(\alpha )/\Phi ^{\prime }(\alpha )>1\), then \(\partial [y(w)/w]/\partial w>0\) and \(\partial n(w)/\partial w<0\).

We first turn to show that \(\partial n(w)/\partial w<0\). The \(w\)-household is seeking to maximize the utility in (1) subject to the budget constraint in (2). Formulating the household, first-order conditions (assuming no taxes in place) yields

$$\begin{aligned}&1-\psi ^{\prime }(1-y/w-n\cdot \alpha )/w=0\end{aligned}$$
(15)
$$\begin{aligned}&v^{\prime }(n)-\alpha \cdot \psi ^{\prime }(1-y/w-n\cdot \alpha )-e=0,\end{aligned}$$
(16)
$$\begin{aligned}&u^{\prime }(e)-n=0,\end{aligned}$$
(17)
$$\begin{aligned}&\Phi ^{\prime }(\alpha )-n\cdot \psi ^{\prime }(1-y/w-n\cdot \alpha )=0. \end{aligned}$$
(18)

Substituting from (15) into (16) and (18) yields

$$\begin{aligned} v^{\prime }(n)-\alpha \cdot w-e(n)=0, \end{aligned}$$
(16')
$$\begin{aligned} \Phi ^{\prime }(\alpha )-n\cdot w=0, \end{aligned}$$
(18')

where \(e(n)\) is given by the implicit solution to (17).

The system of two Eqs.  [(16’) and (18’)] implicitly defines the optimal solution for the number of children and the level of parental time invested per child, as a function of the wage rate [\(n(w)\) and \(\alpha (w)\)]. Fully differentiating the two first-order conditions in (16’) and (18’) with respect to \(w\) yields

$$\begin{aligned}&v^{\prime \prime }(n)\cdot n^{\prime }(w)-[\alpha +w\cdot \alpha ^{\prime }(w)]-e^{\prime }(n)\cdot n^{\prime }(w)=0,\end{aligned}$$
(19)
$$\begin{aligned}&\Phi ^{\prime \prime }(\alpha )\cdot \alpha ^{\prime }(w)- [n+w\cdot n^{\prime }(w)]=0. \end{aligned}$$
(20)

Applying Cramer’s Rule, one then obtains

$$\begin{aligned} n^{\prime }(w)=\frac{\alpha \cdot \Phi ^{\prime \prime } (\alpha )+n\cdot w}{[v^{\prime \prime }(n)-e^{\prime }(n)]\cdot \Phi ^{\prime \prime }(\alpha )-w^{2}}, \end{aligned}$$
(21)

where \([v^{\prime \prime }(n)-e{\prime }(n)]\cdot \Phi ^{\prime \prime }(\alpha )-w^{2}>0\), by the household’s optimization second-order conditions. Substituting for the term \(n\cdot w\) from (18’) into the numerator on the right-hand side of (21) implies that \(\partial n(w)/\partial w<0\) if-and-only-if \(\Phi ^{\prime }(\alpha ) +\alpha \cdot \Phi ^{\prime \prime }(\alpha )<0\Leftrightarrow -\alpha \cdot \Phi ^{\prime \prime }(\alpha )/\Phi ^{\prime }(\alpha )>1\). The latter follows from our assumption. This completes the first part of the proof.

We turn next to show that \(\partial [y(w)/w]/\partial w>0\). Fully differentiating the condition in (15) with respect to \(w\) yields

$$\begin{aligned} 1+\psi ^{\prime \prime }(1-y/w-n\cdot \alpha ) \cdot [\partial (y/w)/\partial w+\partial (n\cdot \alpha )/\partial w]=0. \end{aligned}$$
(22)

By the strict concavity of \(\psi \), it suffices to show that \(\partial (n\cdot \alpha )/\partial w < 0\) in order to establish that \(\partial [y(w)/w]/\partial w>0\).

Employing (16’) and (20) and re-arranging, one obtains

$$\begin{aligned} \partial (n\cdot \alpha )/\partial w=n^{\prime }(w)\cdot \alpha +\alpha ^{\prime }(w)\cdot n=\frac{n^{2}+n^{\prime }(w)\cdot [\Phi ^{\prime }(\alpha )+\alpha \cdot \Phi ^{\prime \prime }(\alpha )]}{\Phi ^{\prime \prime }(\alpha )}<0.\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(23)

The sign of the inequality follows from the concavity of \(\Phi \), the fact that \(n^{\prime }(w)<0\) by the first part of the proof and our assumption that \(-\alpha \cdot \Phi ^{\prime \prime }(\alpha )/ \Phi ^{\prime }(\alpha )>1\). This concludes the proof.

Appendix B: proof of proposition 1

Assuming that the second-order conditions for the government optimization are satisfied, to determine whether taxing or subsidizing children at the margin would be optimal, it suffices to examine the sign of the derivative of the Hamiltonian [given in (10)] with respect to \(n\), starting from a system where the marginal child tax/subsidy is set to zero and the income tax is set at the optimum. A positive sign would imply that social welfare will rise by introducing a small marginal child subsidy (thereby increasing the number of children), whereas a negative sign would suggest taxing children at the margin would be desirable.

Formulating the first-order condition for the Hamiltonian in (10) with respect to \(U\) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial H}{\partial U}=G^{\prime }(U)\cdot f-\lambda \cdot f=-\mu ^{\prime }. \end{aligned}$$
(24)

The transversality conditions are given by

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (\underline{w})=\mu (\overline{w})=0, (\lim _{\overline{w} \rightarrow \infty } \mu (\overline{w})=0, \hbox {when the distribution of skills is unbounded).}\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(25)

Integrating condition (24), employing the transversality condition, \(\mu (\overline{w})=0\), yields

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (w)=\int \limits _w^{\overline{w}}{\left[ {G^{\prime } [U(t)]-\lambda }\right] dF(t)}. \end{aligned}$$
(26)

Employing the second transversality condition, \(\mu (\underline{w})=0\), yields

$$\begin{aligned} \lambda =\int \limits _{\underline{w}}^{\overline{w}} {G^{\prime }[U(t)]dF(t)}. \end{aligned}$$
(27)

Now define the function \(D\) by

$$\begin{aligned} D(w)=\frac{1}{1-F(w)}\int \limits _w^{\overline{w}} {G^{\prime }[U(t)]dF(t)}. \end{aligned}$$
(28)

In words, the function \(D\) measures the average social marginal utility of income over the interval \([w,\overline{w}]\). Moreover, employing (26)–(28) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (w)&= [1-F(w)]\cdot [D(w)-D(\underline{w})] < 0\end{aligned}$$
(29)
$$\begin{aligned} \lambda&= D(\underline{w}), \end{aligned}$$
(30)

where the negative sign of the expression on the right-hand side of (29) follows from the fact that \(D(w)\) [defined in (28)] is decreasing by virtue of the concavity of \(G\).

Setting the marginal child tax/subsidy to zero \((z_n =0)\) and differentiating the Hamiltonian with respect to \(n\) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \left. \begin{array}{l} \frac{\partial H}{\partial n}\\ \end{array}\right| _{z_n =0}=\lambda \cdot f\cdot h_1 (n,y/w)- \mu \cdot h_{12} (n,y/w)\cdot \frac{y}{w^{2}}<0. \end{aligned}$$
(31)

The negative sign follows from (i) the fact that \(h_1 (n,y/w)=0\), by virtue of the household’s first-order condition in (4), (ii) the fact that \(h_{12} (n,y/w)<0\) by virtue of the assumptions on the utility function ensuring a negative relationship between family size and labor supply, and (iii) the fact that \(\mu (w)<0\), by virtue of (29).

Appendix C: derivation of Eq. (11)

In this appendix, we derive the necessary and sufficient condition for the social desirability of providing a marginal child subsidy given in Eq. (11). As in the means-tested case (analyzed in appendix B), assuming that the second-order conditions for the government optimization are satisfied, to determine whether taxing or subsidizing children at the margin would be optimal it suffices to examine the sign of the derivative of the Hamiltonian [given in (10’)] with respect to \(n\), starting from a system where the marginal child tax/subsidy is set to zero and the income tax is set at the optimum.

Formulating the necessary first-order condition for the Hamiltonian in (10’) with respect to the state variable \(U\), employing the transversality conditions and re-arranging (repeating the same steps as in appendix B, which are therefore omitted), one obtains

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (w)&= [1-F(w)]\cdot [D(w)-D(\underline{w})]<0\end{aligned}$$
(32)
$$\begin{aligned} \lambda&= D(\underline{w}), \end{aligned}$$
(33)

where \(D(w)=\frac{1}{1-F(w)}\int _w^{\overline{w}}{G^{\prime } [U(t)]dF(t)}\).

Notice that the conditions in (32) and (33) replicate the conditions in (29) and (30). The negative sign of the expression on the right-hand side of (32) follows from the fact that \(D(w)\) is decreasing by virtue of the concavity of \(G\).

Setting the marginal child tax/subsidy to zero (\(z_n =0)\) and differentiating the Hamiltonian with respect to \(n\) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \left. \begin{array}{l} \frac{\partial H}{\partial n}\\ \end{array}\right| _{z_n =0}&= \lambda \cdot f\cdot [y^{\prime }+h_1 +h_2 \cdot y^{\prime }/w]-\mu \cdot [h_{12} \cdot y/w^{2}+h_{22} \cdot y^{\prime }\cdot y/w^{3}\nonumber \\&+h_2 \cdot y^{\prime }/w^{2}], \end{aligned}$$
(34)

where we omit some of the arguments to abbreviate notation.

The household’s first-order conditions with respect to \(y\) and \(n\) (replicated for convenience), assuming that the marginal child tax/subsidy is set to zero, are given, respectively, by

$$\begin{aligned} a_y +h_2 /w&= 0,\end{aligned}$$
(35)
$$\begin{aligned} h_1&= 0. \end{aligned}$$
(36)

Fully differentiating the condition in (35) with respect to \(n\) yields

$$\begin{aligned} a_{yy} \cdot y^{\prime }+h_{12} /w+h_{22} \cdot y^{\prime }/w^{2}=0. \end{aligned}$$
(37)

Re-arranging yields

$$\begin{aligned} y^{\prime }=-\frac{h_{12} /w}{a_{yy} +h_{22} /w^{2}}<0, \end{aligned}$$
(38)

where the negative sign follows from the fact that \(h_{12} <0\), by our earlier assumptions regarding the household utility function, and the household second-order condition [differentiation of the first-order condition in (35) with respect to \(y\) implies that \(a_{yy} +h_{22} /w^{2}<0\)]. That is, an increase in the number of children (say in response to offering a marginal subsidy) results in a reduction in the labor supply, and consequently the gross level of income, as expected.

Substituting for \(\lambda \hbox { and }\mu \) from (32) and (33) into (34), employing the conditions in (32)–(35) and following some re-arrangements yield the following necessary and sufficient condition for the desirability of providing a marginal child subsidy:

$$\begin{aligned} \left. \begin{array}{l} \frac{\partial H}{\partial n}\\ \end{array}\right| _{b_n =0} >0\Leftrightarrow \left[ {(1\!-\!a_y )+\left[ {1\!-\!\frac{D(w)}{D(\underline{w})}}\right] \cdot \frac{1-F(w)}{f(w)\cdot w} \cdot \left[ {-a_{yy} \cdot y-a_y}\right] }\right] \cdot y^{\prime }>0.\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(39)

By virtue of (38), the condition in (39) holds if-and-only if the following condition [equivalent to the one given in Eq. (11)] is satisfied:

$$\begin{aligned} \left. {\begin{array}{l} \frac{\partial H}{\partial n}\\ \end{array}_{b_n =0}}\right| >0\Leftrightarrow \left[ {1-\frac{D(w)}{D(\underline{w})}}\right] \cdot \left[ {\frac{1-F(w)}{f(w)\cdot w}}\right] \cdot \left[ {a_{yy} \cdot y+a_y}\right] >(1-a_y).\qquad \quad \end{aligned}$$
(40)

Appendix D: the correlation between family size and earning ability and the properties of the income tax schedule

In this appendix, we state and prove the following claim:

Claim

\(n^{\prime }(w)>=<0\hbox { if-and-only-if }a_{yy} \cdot y+a_y < = >0\)

Proof

We reproduce, for convenience, the \(w\)-household’s first-order conditions, given in Eqs. (4) and (5), assuming a universal system, namely \(z(y,n)=a(y)+b(n)\) and setting the marginal child subsidy to zero \((b_n = 0)\):

$$\begin{aligned} K(y,n,w)&{\,\equiv \,}&a_y +h_2 /w=0,\end{aligned}$$
(41)
$$\begin{aligned} H(y,n,w)&{\,\equiv \,}&h_1 =0. \end{aligned}$$
(42)

The systems of two Eqs. [(41) and (42)] provide an implicit solution for \(n(w)\) and \(y(w)\), the optimal choices of the \(w\)-household.

Fully differentiating the two conditions in (41) and (42) with respect to \(w\) yields

$$\begin{aligned}&\partial K/\partial y\cdot y^{\prime }(w)+\partial K/\partial n\cdot n^{\prime }(w)+\partial K/\partial w=0,\end{aligned}$$
(43)
$$\begin{aligned}&\partial H/\partial y\cdot y^{\prime }(w)+\partial H/\partial n\cdot n^{\prime }(w)+\partial H/\partial w=0. \end{aligned}$$
(44)

Employing Cramer’s Rule then yields

$$\begin{aligned} n^{\prime }(w)=\frac{-\partial K/\partial y\cdot \partial H/\partial w+\partial H/\partial y\cdot \partial K/\partial w}{\partial K/\partial y\cdot \partial H/\partial n-\partial H/\partial y\cdot \partial K/\partial n} \end{aligned}$$
(45)

By the second-order conditions of the household’s optimization, it follows that \(\partial K/\partial y\cdot \partial H/\partial n-\partial H/\partial y\cdot \partial K/\partial n >0\). Thus, it follows

$$\begin{aligned} Sign[n^{\prime }(w)]=Sign[-\partial K/\partial y\cdot \partial H/\partial w+\partial H/\partial y\cdot \partial K/\partial w]. \end{aligned}$$
(46)

Differentiating the household’s first-order conditions in (41) and (42) yields

$$\begin{aligned}&\partial H/\partial w=-h_{12} \cdot y/w^{2},\end{aligned}$$
(47)
$$\begin{aligned}&\partial H/\partial y=h_{12} /w,\end{aligned}$$
(48)
$$\begin{aligned}&\partial K/\partial y=a_{yy} +h_{22}/w^{2},\end{aligned}$$
(49)
$$\begin{aligned}&\partial K/\partial w=-h_{22} \cdot y/w^{3}-h_2/w^{2}. \end{aligned}$$
(50)

Substituting from (47)–(50) into the expression on the right-hand side of (46) and re-arranging yields

$$\begin{aligned} -\partial K/\partial y\cdot \partial H/\partial w+\partial H/\partial y\cdot \partial K/\partial w=\frac{h_{12} }{w^{2}}\cdot [a_{yy} \cdot y-h_2 /w]. \end{aligned}$$
(51)

The result follows by substituting \(a_y\) for the term \(-h_2/w\) by virtue of the first-order condition in (35) and by noting that \(h_{12} <0\) by our assumption regarding the utility function.

Appendix E: derivation of Eq. (13)

In this appendix, we derive the formula for the optimal marginal income tax given in Eq. (13). The Hamiltonian for the government program is given by

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{ll} H=&{}\left[ {G(U)+\lambda \cdot \left[ {y-U+h[n(y),y/w]-R}\right] } \right] \cdot f \\ &{}-\mu \cdot h_2 [n(y),y/w]\cdot y/w^{2}, \\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
(52)

where \(n(y)\) is implicitly given by the household’s first-order condition in (5).

Formulating the necessary first-order conditions for the Hamiltonian in (52), omitting the arguments to abbreviate notation, yields

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial H}{\partial y}&= \lambda \cdot f\cdot \left[ {1+h_1 \cdot n^{\prime }+h_2 /w} \right] \nonumber \\&-\mu \cdot [(h_{12} \cdot n^{\prime }+h_{22} /w)\cdot y/w^{2}+h_2 /w^{2}]=0, \end{aligned}$$
(53)
$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial H}{\partial U}&= G^{\prime }(U)\cdot f-\lambda \cdot f=-\mu ^{\prime }. \end{aligned}$$
(54)

The transversality conditions are given by

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (\underline{w})=\mu (\overline{w})=0, (\lim _{\overline{w} \rightarrow \infty } \mu (\overline{w})=0, \hbox {when the distribution of skills is unbounded)}.\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(55)

Integrating condition (54), employing the transversality conditions and repeating the steps made in appendix B (which are hence omitted) yield

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (w)&= [1-F(w)]\cdot [D(w)-D(\underline{w})]<0,\end{aligned}$$
(56)
$$\begin{aligned} \lambda&= D(\underline{w}), \end{aligned}$$
(57)

where \(D(w)=\frac{1}{1-F(w)}\int \nolimits _w^{\overline{w}}{G^{\prime } [U(t)]dF(t)}\).

The negative sign of the expression on the right-hand side of (56) follows from the fact that \(D(w)\) is decreasing by virtue of the concavity of \(G\).

Substituting from (56) and (57) into (53), employing the household’s first-order conditions in (4)–(5) yields, after some re-arrangements, the following expression [which is identical to Eq. (13)]:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1-a_y}{a_y}=\left[ {1-\frac{D(w)}{D (\underline{w})}}\right] \cdot \frac{1-F(w)}{f(w)\cdot w}\cdot \left[ {1+\frac{1}{\varepsilon _L}}\right] , \end{aligned}$$
(58)

where

$$\begin{aligned} \varepsilon _L =-\frac{w\cdot a_y }{y\cdot (n^{\prime }\cdot h_{12} +h_{22} /w)}. \end{aligned}$$
(59)

It remains to show that \(\varepsilon _L\) denotes the labor supply elasticity.

To see this, let \(w_{net} {\,\equiv \,} w\cdot a_y\) denote the after-tax wage rate and let \(m {\,\equiv \,} y/w\) denote labor supply. Reproducing the household first-order conditions in (4)–(5) obtains

$$\begin{aligned} w_{net} +h_2 (n,m)&= 0,\end{aligned}$$
(60)
$$\begin{aligned} h_1 (n,m)&= 0. \end{aligned}$$
(61)

Fully differentiating the system of two equations given by (60) and (61) with respect to \(w_{net}\) yields

$$\begin{aligned}&1+h_{12} (n,m)\cdot \frac{\partial n}{\partial w_{net}} +h_{22} (n,m)\cdot \frac{\partial m}{\partial w_{net}}=0,\end{aligned}$$
(62)
$$\begin{aligned}&h_{11} (n,m)\cdot \frac{\partial n}{\partial w_{net}} +h_{12} (n,m)\cdot \frac{\partial m}{\partial w_{net}}=0. \end{aligned}$$
(63)

Employing cramer’s rule then yields

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial m}{\partial w_{net}}=\frac{-h_{11}}{h_{11} \cdot h_{22} -h_{12}^{2}}. \end{aligned}$$
(64)

The labor supply elasticity is given by

$$\begin{aligned} \varepsilon _L =\frac{\partial m}{\partial w_{net}} \cdot \frac{w_{net}}{m}=-\frac{h_{11}}{h_{11} \cdot h_{22} -h_{12}^{2}} \cdot \frac{w^{2}\cdot a_y}{y}. \end{aligned}$$
(65)

Differentiating the first-order condition in (5) with respect to \(y\) and re-arranging yields

$$\begin{aligned} n^{\prime }(y)=\frac{-h_{12}}{w\cdot h_{11}}. \end{aligned}$$
(66)

Substituting for \(n\)’ from (65) into (59) and re-arranging yields the expression in (65). This concludes the derivation of (13).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Blumkin, T., Margalioth, Y. & Sadka, E. The Re-distributive Role of Child Benefits Revisited. Int Tax Public Finance 22, 476–501 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10797-014-9327-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10797-014-9327-y

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation