Skip to main content
Log in

Medical Error and Moral Luck

  • Published:
HEC Forum Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper addresses the concept of moral luck. Moral luck is discussed in the context of medical error, especially an error of omission that occurs frequently, but only rarely has adverse consequences. As an example, a failure to compare the label on a syringe with the drug chart results in the wrong medication being administered and the patient dies. However, this error may have previously occurred many times with no tragic consequences. Discussions on moral luck can highlight conflicting intuitions. Should perpetrators receive a harsher punishment because of an adverse outcome, or should they be dealt with in the same way as colleagues who have acted similarly, but with no adverse effects? An additional element to the discussion, specifically with medical errors, is that according to the evidence currently available, punishing individual practitioners does not seem to be effective in preventing future errors. The following discussion, using relevant philosophical and empirical evidence, posits a possible solution for the moral luck conundrum in the context of medical error: namely, making a distinction between the duty to make amends and assigning blame. Blame should be assigned on the basis of actual behavior, while the duty to make amends is dependent on the outcome.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See http://www.smd.qmul.ac.uk/risk/yearfive/casestudies/wayne-jowett.html for a discussion of an actual case. The actual case will also be mentioned later in this essay.

  2. The idea of luck is sometimes equated with something happening against the odds, such as winning the lottery. In the moral luck discussion, luck has a broader interpretation (Enoch and Marmor 2007).

  3. Nagel (1976) mentioned in footnote 10 that the Nobel prize is not awarded to people who turn out to be wrong, no matter how brilliant their reasoning.

  4. Williams’ (1976) key example in his original article is the artist Gauguin who leaves his family and becomes a successful painter but could not know when he decided to leave his family that he was going to become successful. This is not a typical moral luck example, more an example of decision making under uncertainty and it is not clear what it is supposed to show (Enoch 2010).

  5. Nagel (1976) identified four kinds of moral luck, namely resultant or consequential luck (focusing on outcome), constitutive luck (focusing on an individual’s characteristics), causal luck (focusing on circumstances which influence actions, relating to the compatibilism/incompatibilism debate), and circumstantial luck (the types of situations that one faces). With medical errors, consequential luck is most important, and only this form of moral luck will be discussed in the paper.

  6. Wolf uses the words ‘truck driver’. Williams and Nagel use the words ‘lorry driver’.

  7. Wolf does not address the issue of limits to the duty to amend. According to her, one should offer to pay if one’s child accidentally broke an expensive vase, but if one is on benefits and this action will leave no money for food, one can wonder whether the offer is appropriate. In the context of medical errors, it will be an insurance company paying, so this issue will not arise under normal circumstances.

  8. See for example http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/health/3133198.stm or http://www.theguardian.com/uk/2003/sep/25/ukcrime.comment.

References

  • Alicke, M. D. (1992). Culpable causation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63(3), 368–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J. R., & Buckwalter, W. (2010). The epistemic side-effect effect. Mind & Language, 25(4), 474–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berlinger, N. (2003). Broken stories: Patients, families, and clinicians after medical error. Literature and Medicine, 22(2), 230–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blendon, R. J., DesRoches, C. M., Brodie, M., Benson, J., Rosen, A. B., Schneider, E., et al. (2002). Views of practicing physicians and the public on medical errors. New England Journal of Medicine, 347(24), 1933–1940.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clinton, H. R., & Obama, B. (2006). Making patient safety the centerpiece of medical liability reform. New England Journal of Medicine, 354(21), 2205–2208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Domsky, D. (2004). There is no door: Finally solving the problem of moral luck. Journal of Philosophy, 101(9), 445–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2010). Moral luck and the law. Philosophy Compass, 5(1), 42–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D., & Guttel, E. (2010). Cognitive biases and moral luck. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 7(3), 372–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D., & Marmor, A. (2007). The case against moral luck. Law and Philosophy, 26(4), 405–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A., & Cokely, E. T. (2011). Individual differences in theory-of-mind judgments: Order effects and side effects. Philosophical Psychology, 24(3), 343–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferner, R. E., & McDowell, S. E. (2006). Doctors charged with manslaughter in the course of medical practice, 1795–2005: A literature review. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 99(6), 309–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guerrero, A. A. (2007). Don’t know, don’t kill: Moral ignorance, culpability, and caution. Philosophical Studies, 136(1), 59–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayward, R. A., & Hofer, T. P. (2001). Estimating hospital deaths due to medical errors. JAMA, 286(4), 415–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubbeling, D. (2010). Criminal prosecution for medical manslaughter. Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, 103(6), 216–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, L. A., & Fogel, J. S. (2010). Ascribing intentions in clinical decision-making. Journal of Medical Ethics, 36(1), 2–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Juth, N., Tillberg, T., & Lynoe, N. (2011). Intentions in critical clinical settings: A study of medical students’ perceptions. Journal of Medical Ethics, 37(8), 483–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2013). The armchair and the trolley: An argument for experimental ethics. Philosophical Studies, 162(2), 421–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (1982). Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kay, N., Green, A., McDowell, S. E., & Ferner, R. E. (2008). Should doctors who make clinical errors be charged with manslaughter? A survey of medical professionals and members of the public. Medicine, Science and the Law, 48(4), 317–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khushf, G., Raymond, J., & Beaman, C. (2008). The Institute of Medicine’s reports on quality and safety: Paradoxes and tensions. HEC Forum, 20(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63(3), 190–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2010). Person as scientist, person as moralist. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(4), 315–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kohn, L. T., Corrigan, J. M., & Donaldson, M. S. (Eds.). (1999). To err is human: Building a safer health system. Washington: Institute of Medicine National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lench, H. C., Domsky, D., Smallman, R., & Darbor, K. E. (2014). Beliefs in moral luck: When and why blame hinges on luck. British Journal of Psychology, 106(1), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R. (2008). Knobe versus Machery: Testing the trade-off hypothesis. Mind & Language, 23(2), 247–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, T., & Aulisio, M. P. (2001). Medical practice, mistake prevention, and compensation. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 11(2), 135–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1976). Moral luck II. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 50, 137–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Ulatowski, J. (2007). Intuitions and individual differences: The Knobe effect revisited. Mind & Language, 22(4), 346–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickerson, R. S. (1998). Confirmation bias: A ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Review of General Psychology, 2(2), 175–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinillos, A. N., Smith, N., Nair, G. S., Marchetto, P., & Mun, C. (2011). Philosophy’s new challenge: Experiments and intentional action. Mind & Language, 26(1), 115–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Royzman, E., & Kumar, R. (2004). Is consequential luck morally inconsequential? Empirical psychology and the reassessment of moral luck. Ratio, 17(3), 329–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauer, H., & Bates, T. (2013). Chairmen, cocaine, and car crashes: The Knobe effect as an attribution error. Journal of Ethics, 17(4), 305–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, H. M. (2010). Subjective rightness. Social Philosophy and Policy, 27(2), 64–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Studdert, D. M., & Brennan, T. A. (2001). No-fault compensation for medical injuries. The prospect for error prevention. JAMA, 286(2), 217–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Studdert, D. M., Mello, M., Gawande, A. A., Gandhi, T. K., Kachalia, A., Yoon, C., et al. (2006). Claims, errors, and compensation payments in medical malpractice litigation. New England Journal of Medicine, 345(19), 2024–2033.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uttich, K., & Lombrozo, T. (2010). Norms inform mental state ascriptions: A rational explanation for the side-effect effect. Cognition, 116(1), 87–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Grunsven, P. R. (1997). Medical malpractice or criminal mistake? An analysis of past and current criminal prosecutions for clinical mistakes and fatal errors. DePaul Journal of Health Care Law, 2(1), 1–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. A. O. (1976). Moral luck I. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 50, 115–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (2001). The moral of moral luck. Philosophic Exchange, 31(1), 2–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zientek, D. M. (2010). Medical error, malpractice and complications: A moral geography. HEC Forum, 22(2), 145–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, M. J. (1997). Moral responsibility and ignorance. Ethics, 107(3), 410–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, M. J. (2002). Taking luck seriously. Journal of Philosophy, 99(11), 553–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dieneke Hubbeling.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hubbeling, D. Medical Error and Moral Luck. HEC Forum 28, 229–243 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-015-9295-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-015-9295-3

Keywords

Navigation