Skip to main content
Log in

Constructibility of the Universal Wave Function

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper focuses on a constructive treatment of the mathematical formalism of quantum theory and a possible role of constructivist philosophy in resolving the foundational problems of quantum mechanics, particularly, the controversy over the meaning of the wave function of the universe. As it is demonstrated in the paper, unless the number of the universe’s degrees of freedom is fundamentally upper bounded (owing to some unknown physical laws) or hypercomputation is physically realizable, the universal wave function is a non-constructive entity in the sense of constructive recursive mathematics. This means that even if such a function might exist, basic mathematical operations on it would be undefinable and subsequently the only content one would be able to deduce from this function would be pure symbolical.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Quantum formalism provides no indication as to how to exhibit, or calculate, macroscopic wave functions except the general form of the Schrödinger equation, which, to paraphrase Walter Huckel [2], has the good view but leads to misunderstanding, because it forces us to think that we have something that we do not have—i.e., a calculated wave function of any given physical system (i.e., of an arbitrary size and complexity).

  2. A constructive existence proof demonstrates the existence of a mathematical object by outlining a method (i.e., an algorithm) of “constructing” (that is, computing) this object [3].

  3. For example, most models in quantum cosmology—an application of quantum theory to the universe as a whole—are based on the approach of the Wheeler–DeWitt equation that combines mathematically the ideas of quantum mechanics and general relativity. This approach is first to restrict the full configuration space of three-geometries called “superspace” to a small number of variables (such as scale factor, inflaton field, etc.) and then to quantize them canonically; consequently, the resultant models are called “minisuperspace models”. More details can be found in [4] as well as in the review [5].

  4. However, while one can prove that any constructive function is a computable function (for instance, using Kleene’s realizability interpretation [9]), it is important to keep the distinction between the notions of constructivism and computability. As explained in [10], the notion of function in constructive mathematics is a primitive one, which cannot be explained in a satisfactory way in term of recursivity. Even so, unless it brings about a confusion, henceforward in this paper, we will use the adjectives “constructive”, “computable” and “recursive” interchangeably.

  5. If the spectrum of L is not bounded, then the domain of definition of L cannot be all of \(\mathcal {H}\), that is, \(\mathcal {D}(L) \ne \mathcal {H}\). Furthermore, if the spectrum of the operator L contains a continuous part, then the corresponding eigenvectors do not belong to \(\mathcal {H}\), but to a larger space.

  6. A general proof (not based on the computational representation of quantum mechanics), which demonstrates that the quantum world is in fact a “hostile environment” for many (if not all) varieties of constructivist mathematics, is given in the paper [19]. As it is argued there, from a thoroughgoing constructivist point of view, unbounded linear Hermitian operators in an infinite Hilbert space cannot be even recognizable as mathematical objects. Also, deserving of mentioning are the investigations [20, 21], which show that, due to the use of unbounded and thus discontinuous operators in an infinite Hilbert space, noncomputable and hence nonconstructive objects are unavoidable in the quantum theory. Even though it is still unclear whether or not at least some form(s) (albeit modified) of constructivist mathematics can be applied to develop a full counterpart of quantum formalism constructive in a sense, it is crucial to our investigation that such a counterpart cannot be recursive

  7. Suffice it to say that it is even unclear as to how to account for the probabilistic content of the wave function of the universe; see, for example, the discussion in [24].

  8. According to the commonly accepted paradigm, the observed universe evolved in a finite time from a dense singular state, before which classical space and time did not exist. However, as it is argued in the papers [25, 26], self-consistent, geodesically complete, and physically sensible steady-state (SS) eternally inflating universe, based on the flat slicing of de Sitter space, is also possible. In the SS, the universe always has and always will exist in a state statistically like its current one, and time has no beginning. Needless to say, the SS cosmology is appealing because it avoids an initial singularity, has no beginning of time, and does not require an initial condition for the universe.

  9. Putting it differently, because an essential feature of macroscopic assemblies of microscopic particles is that the state equations are size independent, one can naturally arrive at an idealization of an infinite universe as an infinite-volume limit of increasingly large finite systems with constant density.

  10. No ratio of positive integers (capable of being calculated in a finite number of steps) can be the exact value of \(\pi \); see the proof in [27].

  11. A typical example of such a ‘limited’ consideration is the Hartle–Hawking state (i.e., the wave function of the universe) satisfying the Wheeler–DeWitt equation defined in mini-superspaces [28].

  12. If not, then it would be hard for the proposition of explicit physical finitism to answer the charge of arbitrariness: Certainly, no matter where the limit for the particular parameter would be drawn, it would be always ad hoc and so perpetually subject to shifting.

  13. It is interesting to note that the existence of the upper bound on the complexity of the universal wave function could also result in constructiveness of this function. Indeed, according to [30], the complexity of a quantum state \({\vert {\Psi } \rangle }_N\) on N qubits is defined as the minimum number of gates (i.e., elementary unitaries) necessary to produce \({\vert {\Psi } \rangle }_N\) from a simple reference state \(\vert {\Psi }_0 \rangle \). The complexity of \({\vert {\Psi } \rangle }_N\) in principle depends on all the details of the construction, but more importantly, it is proportional to the number of active degrees of freedom of the system, that is, the number of qubits N. So, if the complexity of the state vector describing the universe \({\vert {\Psi } \rangle }_N\) were to be limited it would imply the limitation on N and thus the computability of this vector. The problem is that it is unclear why the complexity of the quantum state of the universe should be bounded (and not grow to infinity).

  14. For details see the critical analysis [35] that examines the possibility of computation-like processes transcending the limits imposed by the Church–Turing thesis.

  15. Besides, as expected by most logicians, one can construct an undecidable sentence (i.e., such that neither it itself nor its negation is provable) whose physical meaning seems to be hardly questionable. This happens both in classical and in quantum mechanics (see for example investigations by Pitowski [38], Mundici [39] and Svozil [40]). So, the wave function of the entire universe might be uncomputable and yet full of physical meaning.

References

  1. Bishop, E.: Foundations of Constructive Mathematics. Springer, Heidelberg (1985)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Huckel, W.: Theoretical Principles of Organic Chemistry. Elsevier Van Nostrand, New York (1955)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Troelstra, A., Schwichtenberger, H.: Basic Proof Theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. Kiefer, C.: Quantum Gravity. Clarendon Press, Oxford (2004)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Kiefer, C.: Quantum gravity: general introduction and recent developments. Ann. Phys. 15, 129–148 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Bridges, D., Richman, F.: Varieties of Constructive Mathematics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1987)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Shanin, N.: Georg Cantor as the author of constructions playing fundamental roles in constructive mathematics. J. Math. Sci. 87(1), 3183–3201 (1997)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  8. Troelstra, A., van Dalen, D.: Constructivism in Mathematics. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam (1988)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Kleene, S.: Introduction to metamathematics. D. Van Nostrand, New York (1952)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Coquand, T.: Recursive Functions and Constructive Mathematics. In: Dubucs, J., Bourdeau, M. (eds.) Constructivity and Computability in Historical and Philosophical Perspective, Chap. 6. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, pp. 159–167. Springer, Dordrecht (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Hilbert, D., Bernays, P.: Grundlagen der Mathematik I - Foundations of Mathematics I. Part B. College Publications, London, First (in German and English) edition (2013)

  12. Jane, I.: The role of the absolute infinite in Cantor’s conception of set. Erkenntnis 42(3), 375–402 (1995)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Gieres, F.: Mathematical surprises and Dirac’s formalism in quantum mechanics. Rep. Prog. Phys. 63(12), 1893–1931 (2000)

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  14. Halmos, P.: A Hilbert Space Problem Book, 2nd edn. Springer, New York (1982)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. Shivakumar, P., Sivakumar, K.: A review of infinite matrices and their applications. Linear Algebra Appl. 430, 976–998 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Bridges, D.: Can constructive mathematics be applied in physics? J. Philos. Log. 28, 439–453 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Bridges, D., Svozil, K.: Constructive mathematics in quantum physics. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 39(3), 503–515 (2000)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Richman, F., Bridges, D.: A constructive proof of Gleason’s theorem. J. Funct. Anal. 162, 287–312 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Hellman, G.: Constructive mathematics and quantum mechanics: unbounded operators and the spectral theorem. J. Philos. Log. 22, 221–248 (1993)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Myrvold, W.: Constructivism, Computability, and Physical Theories. Ph.D. thesis, Boston University, 1994

  21. Myrvold, W.: Computability in Quantum Mechanics. In: Stadler, F., Depauli Schimanovich, W., Koehler, E. (eds.) The Foundational Debate: Complexity and Constructivity in Mathematics and Physics, vol. 3, pp. 976–998. Springer, Netherlands (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  22. MacKenzie, R.: Path integral methods and applications, April 2000. Lectures given at Rencontres du Vietnam: VIth Vietnam School of Physics, Vung Tau. Vietnam, 27 Dec 1999–8 Jan 2000. arXiv:quant-ph/0004090

  23. Schmied, R.: Lecture script: Introduction to computational quantum mechanics, June 2015. The lecture script of a one-semester course taught at the University of Basel in the Fall semesters of 2012 and 2013. arXiv:1403.7050

  24. Hemmo, M., Pitowsky, I.: Quantum probability and many worlds. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 38, 333–350 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  25. Aguirre, A., Gratton, S.: Steady-State Eternal Inflation. Phys. Rev. D 65(8), 083507–083513 (2002)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  26. Guth, A.: Eternal inflation and its implications. J. Phys. A 40, 6811–6826 (2007)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  27. Arndt, J., Haenel, C.: Pi—Unleashed, 2nd edn. Springer, New York (2001)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  28. Hartle, J., Hawking, S.: Wave function of the Universe. Phys. Rev. D 28(12), 2960–2975 (1983)

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  29. Kiefer, C.: Conceptual problems in quantum gravity and quantum cosmology. ISRN Math. Phys. 2013:1–17, 2013. Article ID 509316

  30. Brown, A., Roberts, D., Susskind, L., Swingle, B., Zhao, Y.: Complexity, Action, and Black Holes (2015). arXiv:1512.04993

  31. da Costa, N., Doria, F.: Some thoughts on hypercomputation. Appl. Math. Comput. 178, 83–92 (2006)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  32. Stannett, M.: The case for hypercomputation. Appl. Math. Comput. 178, 8–24 (2006)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  33. Blum, L., Shub, M., Smale, S.: On a theory of computation and complexity over the real numbers: NP-completeness, recursive functions and universal machines. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 21(1), 1–46 (1989)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Bournez, O., Campagnolo, M., Grata, D., Hainry, E.: Polynomial differential equations compute all real computable functions on computable compact intervals. J. Complex. 23, 317–335 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  35. Davis, M.: Why there is no such discipline as hypercomputation. Appl. Math. Comput. 178, 4–7 (2006)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  36. Davis, M.: The Myth of Hypercomputation. In: Teuscher, C. (ed.) Alan Turing: Life and Legacy of a Great Thinker. Springer, Berlin (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Wallace, D.: Worlds in the Everett interpretation. Stud. Hist. Philos. Mod. Phys. 33, 637–661 (2001)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  38. Pitowsky, I.: Quantum Probability—Quantum Logic. Lecture Notes in Physics. Springer, Berlin (1989)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  39. Mundici, D.: Logic of infinite quantum systems. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 32, 1941–1955 (1993)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  40. Svozil, K.: Randomness and Undecidability in Physics. World Scientific, Singapore (1993)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  41. Saunders, S.: Time, quantum mechanics, and probability. Synthese 114, 373–408 (1998)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  42. Vaidman, L.: Quantum theory and determinism. Quantum Stud. 1(1), 5–38 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Arkady Bolotin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bolotin, A. Constructibility of the Universal Wave Function. Found Phys 46, 1253–1268 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-016-0018-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-016-0018-7

Keywords

Navigation