Skip to main content
Log in

Stance Pluralism, Scientology, and the Problem of Relativism

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Inspired by Bas van Fraassen’s Stance Empiricism, Anjan Chakravartty has developed a pluralistic account of what he calls epistemic stances towards scientific ontology. In this paper, I examine whether Chakravartty’s stance pluralism can exclude epistemic stances that licence pseudo-scientific practices like those found in Scientology. I argue that it cannot. Chakravartty’s stance pluralism is therefore prone to a form of debilitating relativism. Consequently, we need (1) some ground or constraint in relation to which epistemic stances can be ranked by degrees, and (2) some way to demarcate science from pseudo-science so that we know what epistemic stances are about. Regarding (1), I argue that empirical detectability can serve as the ground in relation to which epistemic stances are ranked by degrees. Regarding (2), I argue for ranking sciences on a continuum according to established institutional criteria, rather than attempting to draw a strict demarcation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See the 2011 special issue of Synthese (volume 178, issue 1) edited by Darrell Rowbottom and Octavio Bueno for the status of the contemporary debate.

  2. Scientology originally took the form of what Hubbard called Dianetics (as outlined in his (1950) book Dianetics: The modern science of mental health). Once Dianetics began to take on overtly religious tones, it morphed into what we now know as Scientology.

  3. The question of whether Scientology is largely a money-making pyramid scheme rather than a sincere philanthropic religion is often discussed (see e.g. Miller, 1988; Wright, 2013). I will however not engage with this debate since our concern is with the empirical, rather than financial, practices contained in Scientology.

  4. See Bigliardi (2016) for a detailed study of the E-meter, its role in Scientology, and its relationship to conventional science and technology.

  5. These claims rely on us having a level of trust in Scientologists’ sincerity. In other words, we will have to believe that Scientologists are (on the whole) well-meaning, but misguided pseudo-scientists, rather than charlatans. I do not see how we can make judgements to the contrary without insights into their deep psychological motives (see Hansson, 2017; Dawes, 2018 for more on this issue).

  6. Stathis Psillos (2021) argues likewise that creationism is not obviously self-defeating. Matthew Slater (2021) suggests the same for climate change denial and flat-Earthism.

  7. Chakravartty declines to offer examples of pathological epistemic stances. He does nonetheless state that an epistemic stance is pathological if its “associated epistemic policies are transparently flawed” (Chakravartty, 2017, p. 230). PSES seems to fit this definition.

  8. The National Academies of Science reports the reliability of polygraph testing as being between 81% and 91% (National Research Council, 2003). Lewis and Cuppari (2009) argue for the empirical legitimacy of polygraphy. Ekman (1996) and Cacioppo et al. (2000) disagree.

  9. Kyle Stanford notes likewise that creationism enjoys “‘some’ degree of representational accuracy”; the theory is not “wrong or misleading about everything” (2003, p. 567; see also Mahner, 2007, pp. 518–519). According to van Fraassen, there is no clear demarcation between science and religion (2002, pp. 153–155).

  10. See Hansson (2020) for a thorough discussion of pseudo-technology and its relation to pseudo-science.

  11. Probability theory may offer one way to formalise such a ranking schema. Jared Henderson (2021) has suggested that we can make sense of “partial verification” in terms of probability. Since probability comes in degrees, a claim is more or less verified depending on how probable it is made by the available evidence. In terms of our discussion, we can think of the ontological claims that form part of the content of an epistemic stance as being made more or less probable by the degree to which they are verifiable by detection. The more probable an epistemic stance’s ontological claims are, the more legitimate it will be, and the more our confidence in it should increase.

  12. See Hansson (2021) and for a thorough discussion of the demarcation problem. See Hirvonen and Karisto (2022) for a history.

  13. An anonymous reviewer pointed out that many English speakers mistakenly use the term ‘bona fide’ to mean something like ‘legitimate’, when it, in fact, means ‘in good faith’. The context of the Ladyman and Ross quote suggests that they intend the former. For consistency, I will follow Ladyman and Ross in using the mistaken sense of the term.

  14. As before, if ranking disciplines proves controversial, x-phi studies could empirically establish degrees of scientificity by surveying institutional norms.

  15. If graphed, this continuum should form a bell curve shape. Legitimate sciences cluster in the centre and pseudo-sciences reside in the long tail of the distribution. See also Mahner (2007) and Boudry (2017) for similar ranking schemas.

References

  • Alspector-Kelly, M. (2004). Seeing the unobservable: Van Fraassen and the limits of experience. Synthese, 140(3), 331–353.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baghramian, M. (2019). I—The virtues of relativism. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 93(1), 247–269.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumann, P. (2011). Empiricism, stances, and the problem of voluntarism. Synthese, 178(1), 27–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behe, M. J. (1996). Darwin’s black box: The biochemical challenge to evolution. Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigliardi, S. (2016). New religious movements, technology, and science: The conceptualization of the E-meter in Scientology teachings. Zygon Journal of Religion and Science, 51(3), 661–683.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blancke, S., Boudry, M., & Braeckman, J. (2019). Reasonable irrationality: The role of reasons in the diffusion of pseudo-science. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 19(5), 432–449.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boucher, S. (2018). Stances and epistemology: Values, pragmatics, and rationality. Metaphilosophy, 49(4), 521–547.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M. (2017). Plus ultra. Why science does not have limits. In M. Pigliucci & M. Boudry (Eds.), Science unlimited? The challenges of scientism. (pp. 31–52). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Bryant, A. (2021). A thousand flowers on the road to epistemic anarchy: Comments on Chakravartty’s scientific ontology. Dialogue, 60(1), 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1983). Treatise on basic philosophy, vol. 6, epistemology and methodology II. Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Cacioppo, J. T., Berntson, G. G., Larsen, J. T., Poehlmann, K. M., & Ito, T. A. (2000). The psychophysiology of emotion. In R. Lewis & J. M. Haviland-Jones (Eds.), The Handbook of emotion (2nd ed., pp. 173–191). Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2004). Stance relativism: Empiricism versus metaphysics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 35(1), 173–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A Metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2017). Scientific ontology: Integrating naturalized metaphysics and voluntarist epistemology. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2021). Risk, reward, and scientific ontology: Reply to Bryant, Psillos, and Slater. Dialogue, 60(1), 43–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A., & van Fraassen, B. C. (2018). What is scientific realism? Spontaneous Generations, 9(1), 12–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2020). Relativism, perspectivism and pluralism. In M. Kusch (Ed.), The routledge handbook of philosophy of relativism (pp. 398–407). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1973). The problem of the criterion. Marquette University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Church of Scientology. (1969). Success beyond man’s wildest dreams. Advance! 7.

  • Church of Scientology. (2001). OT VIII: Truth revealed. Advance! 155.

  • Church of Scientology. (2010). Scientology: What is it? [Resource document.] https://www.cia.gov/library/readingroom/docs/CIA-RDP90-00806R000201000018-9.pdf. Accessed 21 December 2020.

  • Church of Scientology. (1998). What is Scientology? Bridge Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H., Bartlett, A., & Reyes-Galindo, L. (2017). Demarcating fringe science for policy. Perspectives on Science, 25(4), 411–438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawes, G. W. (2018). Identifying pseudo-science: A social process criterion. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 49(3), 283–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dericquebourg, R. (2010). Legitimizing belief through the authority of science: The case of the church of scientology. In J. R. Lewis & O. Hammer (Eds.), Handbook of religion and the authority of science (pp. 741–62). Leiden: Brill.

  • Ekman, P. (1996). Why don’t we catch liars? Social Research, 63(3), 801–817.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fahrbach, L. (2017). Scientific revolutions and the explosion of scientific evidence. Synthese, 194(12), 5039–5072.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez-Beanato, D. (2020). The multicriterial approach to the problem of demarcation. Journal for the General Philosophy of Science, 51(4), 375–390.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gell-Mann, M. (1994). The quark and the jaguar: Adventures in the simple and the complex. W. H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2021). Science and pseudo-science. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy E. N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2021/entries/pseudo-science/>.

  • Hansson, S. O. (2017). Science denial as a form of pseudo-science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 63(1), 39–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (2020). With all this pseudo-science, why so little pseudotechnology? Axiomathes, 30(6), 685–696.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harley, G. M., & Kieffer, J. (2009). The development and reality of auditing. In J. R. Lewis (Ed.), Scientology (pp. 183–205). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, J. (2021). Truth and gradability. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 50, 755–779. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-020-09584-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirvonen, I., & Karisto, J. (2022). Demarcation without Dogmas. Theoria, 88(3), 701–720.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2013). Systematicity: The nature of science. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubbard, L. R. (1950). Dianetics: The modern science of mental health. Bridge Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hubbard, L. R. (1975). The book introducing the E-meter. Bridge Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, M. (2020). Stances, voluntarism, relativism. In D. Finkelde & P. M. Livingston (Eds.), Idealism, relativism and realism: New essays on objectivity beyond the analytic-continental divide (pp. 131–153). De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, J. A., & Cuppari, M. (2009). The polygraph: The truth lies within. The Journal of Psychiatry and Law, 37(1), 85–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Discussion—Epistemic options. Philosophical Studies, 121(2), 147–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. (2013). Science and pseudo-science. How to demarcate after the (alleged) demise of the demarcation problem. In M. Pigliucci & M. Boudry (Eds.), Philosophy of pseudo-science: Reconsidering the demarcation problem (pp. 29–44). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Mahner, M. (2007). Demarcating science from non-science. In T. Kuipers (Ed.), Handbook of the philosophy of science: General philosophy of science—Focal issues (pp. 515–575). Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G. (1962). The ontological status of theoretical entities. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time (pp. 1–27). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R. (1988). Bare-faced messiah: The true story of L. Ron Hubbard. H. Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (2009). Unsimple truths: Science, complexity and policy. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2020). Hypothesis testing in scientific practice: An empirical study. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 33(1), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (2018). Beware of mad DOG realist. Spontaneous Generations, 9(1), 52–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • National Research Council, Committee to Review the Scientific Evidence on the Polygraph. (2003). The polygraph and lie detection. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.

  • Nickles, T. (2013). The problem of demarcation: History and future. In M. Pigliucci & M. Boudry (Eds.), Philosophy of pseudo-science: Reconsidering the demarcation problem (pp. 101–120). University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2021). Scientific ontology: Fact or stance? Dialogue, 60(1), 15–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60(1), 20–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reisch, G. A. (1998). Pluralism, logical empiricism, and the problem of pseudo-science. Philosophy of Science, 65(2), 333–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, M. W. (1988). Effects of membership in scientology on personality: An exploratory study. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion., 27(4), 630–636.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sankey, H. (2010). Witchcraft, relativism and the problem of the criterion. Erkenntnis, 72(1), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sankey, H. (2011). Epistemic relativism and the problem of the criterion. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 42(4), 562–570.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. (2021). Extending the ladder of stances: Comments on Chakravartty’s scientific ontology. Dialogue, 60(1), 33–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolin, L. (2006). The trouble with physics: The rise of string theory, the fall of a science, and what comes next. Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, P. K. (2003). Pyrrhic victories for scientific realism. The Journal of Philosophy, 100(11), 553–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steup, M. (2011). Empiricism, metaphysics, and voluntarism. Synthese, 178(1), 19–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Surovell, J. R. (2019). Stance empiricism and epistemic reason. Synthese, 196(1), 709–733.

    Google Scholar 

  • Targ, R., & Puthoff, H. E. (1977). Mind-reach: Scientists look at psychic ability. Delacorte Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. R. (1978). Why astrology is a pseudo-science. In: P. Asquith, & I. Hacking (Eds.), Proceedings of the philosophy of science association (pp. 223–234). East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.

  • Thagard, P. R. (1988). Computational philosophy of science. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urban, H. (2011). The church of scientology: A history of a new religion. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van der Merwe, R. (2019). Book review of Anjan Chakravartty: Scientific ontology: Integrating naturalized metaphysics and voluntarist epistemology. Empedocles: European Journal for the Philosophy of Communication, 10(1), 109–119.

  • Van der Merwe, R. (2020). Book review of K. Brad Wray: Resisting scientific realism. Journal for the General Philosophy of Science, 51(4), 637–641.

  • Van der Merwe, R. (forthcoming). Whewell’s hylomorphism as a metaphorical explanation for how mind and world merge. Journal for General Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-021-09595-x

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (2002). The empirical stance. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veigl, S. J. (2020). Notes on a complicated relationship: Scientific pluralism, epistemic relativism, and stances. Synthese, 199, 3485–3503. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02943-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willms, G. (2009). Scientology: ‘Modern religion’ or ‘religion of modernity’? In J. R. Lewis (Ed.), Scientology (pp. 245–265). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (2013). Going clear: Scientology, hollywood and the prison of belief. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

John Templeton Foundation Project ID: 61408, Increasing Complexity: The First Rule of Evolution?

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ragnar van der Merwe.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

The author declares that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

van der Merwe, R. Stance Pluralism, Scientology, and the Problem of Relativism. Found Sci (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-022-09882-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-022-09882-w

Keywords

Navigation