Skip to main content
Log in

Theorizing About Theories and Mathematical Existence

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Suppes proposes an analysis of the structure and identity of empirical theories with his model-theoretical approach and undertakes effective reconstructions of theories in diverse disciplinary fields. Here the authors analyse the results of these examinations under the optics of questions concerning the assumed ontological commitments, and for how they satisfy economic and other criteria.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. According to the structuralist position, theoricity must always be relativized, but not to a language (theoretical in contrast to an observational), but to a scientific theory. The exact denotation is, therefore, not “theoretical” but “T-theoretical” (Stegmüller 1979, p. 10). A concept t is called theoretical relative to theory T (or just T-theoretical) iff every determination of t in any application of T, presupposes the existence of a least one actual model of T. The distinction between T-theoretical and T-non-theoretical concepts form the basis of differentiation between potential models and partial potential models of a theory T. Potential models are those structures which exemplify all the concepts of the theory T. If we omit all theoretical terms from a potential model we are left with a partial potential model, i.e., a structure consisting of all and only the non-theoretical concepts of the theory

  2. According to the semantic view: (1) Scientific theories are to be conceived primarily not as linguistic entities (sets of statements) but as certain nonlinguistic conceptual structures called partial or potential models, state spaces or configuration spaces. (2) The appropriate tool for the formal description of scientific theories is not logic but mathematics. An empirical theory T can be identified with its class of models M(T), the models being structured sets. Then, the class of models M(T) of an empirical theory T is used to express “the empirical claim” or the “theoretical hypothesis” of T, to wit the assertion that a certain class I(T) of real (or empirical) systems is a subclass of M(T) or, in more refined versions of the semantic view, that the elements of I(T) can be extended in a certain way to elements of M(T). This is only a rough outline of the semantic view of empirical theories (Mormann 1991).

References

  • Balzer, W. (1996). Theoretical terms: Recent developments. In W. Balzer & C. U. Moulines (Eds.), Structuralist theory of science. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chihara, C. S. (1973). Ontology and the vicious-circle principle. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diederich, W. (1996). Structuralism within the model-theoretical approach. In W. Balzer & C. U. Moulines (Eds.), Structuralist theory of science. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and other enigmas. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Estany, A. (1993). Introducción a la filosofía de la ciencia. Barcelona: Critica. (in Spanish).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mormann, T. (1991). Husserl’s philosophy of science and the semantic approach. Philosophy of Sceince, 58(1), 61–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulines, U. (1998). Esbozo de ontoepistemosemántica. Theoria, I3(1), 141–159. (in Spanish).

    Google Scholar 

  • Nescolarde-Selva, J. A., Usó-Doménech, J. L., & Gash, H. (2017). What are ideological systems? Systems, 5, 21. https://doi.org/10.3390/systems5010021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, A. (1996). The metaphysics of properties. Mind, 105(417), 1–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1951). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies, 2(1), 11–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1983). Ontology and ldeology revisited. The Journal of Phüosophy, 80(9), 4–502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1986). Teorías y cosas. México: UNAM. (in Spanish).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sneed, J. D. (1971). The logical structure of mathematical physics. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1981). The evolution of rationality. Synthese, 48, 95–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller, W. (1979). The structuralist view of theories: A possible analogue of the Bourbaki programme in physical science. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, F. (1989). The semantic conception of’ theories and scientific realism. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Usó-Doménech, J. L., Nescolarde-Selva, J. A., & Gash, H. (2018). Universe of discourse and existence. Mathematics, 6, 272. https://doi.org/10.3390/math6110272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1970). On the extension of Beth’s semantics of physical theories. Philosophy of Science, 37, 325–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1971). Semántica formal y lógica. México: UNAM, 1987. (in Spanish).

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. A. Nescolarde-Selva.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Usó-Doménech, J.L., Nescolarde-Selva, J.A. & Gash, H. Theorizing About Theories and Mathematical Existence. Found Sci 25, 587–595 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-020-09648-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-020-09648-2

Keywords

Navigation