Skip to main content
Log in

Is an Electron a Charge Cloud? A Reexamination of Schrödinger’s Charge Density Hypothesis

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article re-examines Schrödinger’s charge density hypothesis, according to which the charge of an electron is distributed in the whole space, and the charge density in each position is proportional to the modulus squared of the wave function of the electron there. It is shown that the charge distribution of a quantum system can be measured by protective measurements as expectation values of certain observables, and the results as predicted by quantum mechanics confirm Schrödinger’s original hypothesis. Moreover, the physical origin of the charge distribution is also investigated. It is argued that the charge distribution of a quantum system is effective, that is, it is formed by the ergodic motion of a localized particle with the charge of the system.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that Born’s interpretation and Schrödinger’s charge density hypothesis can be reconciled (see later analysis and Gao 2017).

  2. Another protection scheme is to introduce a protective potential such that the measured wave function of a quantum system is a nondegenerate energy eigenstate of the Hamiltonian of the system with finite gap to neighboring energy eigenstates (Aharonov and Vaidman 1993). By this scheme, the measurement of an observable is required to be weak and adiabatic.

  3. Note that after the measurement the pointer wavepacket does not spread, and the width of the wavepacket is the same as the initial width. This ensures that the pointer shift can represent a valid measurement result.

  4. Similarly, we can protectively measure another observable \(B ={\hbar \over {2mi}}(A\nabla + \nabla A)\). The measurements will give the electric flux density \(j_Q(x,t) ={\hbar Q\over {2mi}}(\psi ^* \nabla \psi - \psi \nabla \psi ^* )\) everywhere in space. Moreover, we can also protectively measure the charge density (and electric flux density) of a many-body system, and the density turns out to be the same as that given by Schrödinger. For example, a protective measurement of \(A_1+A_2\) in a two-particle state \(\psi (x_1,x_2,t)\) yields \(\langle A_1+A_2\rangle = Q_1\int _{V}\int _{-\infty }^{+\infty }|\psi (x_1,x_2,t)|^2 {\hbox {d}}x_2{\hbox {d}}x_1+Q_2\int _{V}\int _{-\infty }^{+\infty }|\psi (x_1,x_2,t)|^2 {\hbox {d}}x_1{\hbox {d}}x_2\). When \(v \rightarrow 0\) we can find the charge density is \(\rho _Q(x,t)=Q_1\int _{-\infty }^{+\infty }|\psi (x,x_2,t)|^2 {\hbox {d}}x_2+Q_2\int _{-\infty }^{+\infty }|\psi (x_1,x,t)|^2{\hbox {d}}x_1\).

  5. Note that in Nelson’s stochastic mechanics, the particle, which is assumed to undergo Brownian motion, moves only within a region bounded by the nodes (Nelson 1966). Obviously this sort of motion is not ergodic and cannot generate the right charge distribution. This conclusion also holds true for the motion of particles in Bohm’s theory (Bohm 1952), as well as in some variants of stochastic mechanics and Bohm’s theory (Bell 1986; Vink 1993).

  6. Moreover, these two parts will be also entangled and their wave function be defined in a six-dimensional configuration space.

  7. It is a fundamental assumption in physics that a physical entity being at an instant has no interactions with itself being at another instant, while two distinct physical entities may have interactions with each other.

  8. Note that this argument does not assume that real charges which exist at the same time are classical charges and they have classical interaction. By contrast, the Schrödinger–Newton equation, which was proposed by Diósi (1984) and Penrose (1998), treats the mass distribution of a quantum system as classical.

  9. Besides, for normalized wave functions, the probability current density must also be equal to the formed charge flux density divided by the charge of the particle.

  10. This result may have implications for the ontological meaning of the wave function. For further discussion see Gao (2017).

References

  • Aharonov, Y., Anandan, J., & Vaidman, L. (1993). Meaning of the wave function. Physical Review A, 47, 4616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aharonov, Y., & Vaidman, L. (1993). Measurement of the Schrödinger wave of a single particle. Physics Letters A, 178, 38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bacciagaluppi, G., & Valentini, A. (2009). Quantum theory at the crossroads: Reconsidering the 1927 Solvay conference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barut, A. O. (1988). Quantum-electrodynamics based on self-energy. Physica Scripta, T21, 18–21.

  • Bell, J. S. (1986). Beables for quantum field theory. Physics Reports, 137, 49–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1952). A suggested interpretation of quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables, I and II. Physical Review, 85, 166–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Born, M. (1926). Quantenmechanik der Sto\(\beta\)vorgänge. Zeitschrift fur Physik, 38, 803; (English translation in Ludwig, G., eds., 1968, Wave Mechanics, Oxford: Pergamon Press p. 206).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diósi, L. (1984). Gravitation and the quantum-mechanical localization of macro-objects. Physics Letters A, 105, 199–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2013). Protective measurement: A paradigm shift in understanding quantum mechanics. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9627/.

  • Gao, S. (2014). Reality and meaning of the wave function. In S. Gao (Ed.), Protective measurement and quantum reality: Toward a new understanding of quantum mechanics (pp. 211–229). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2015a). How do electrons move in atoms? From the Bohr model to quantum mechanics. In F. Aaserud & H. Kragh (Eds.), One hundred years of the Bohr atom: Proceedings from a conference, scientia Danica. Series M: Mathematica et physica (Vol. 1, pp. 450–464). Copenhagen: Royal Danish Academy of Sciences and Letters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2015b). An argument for \(\psi\)-ontology in terms of protective measurements. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 52, 198–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gao, S. (2017). Meaning of the wave function. In search of the ontology of quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Janossy, L. (1962). Zum hydrodynamischen Modell der Quantenmechanik. Zeitschrifr fur Physik, 169, 79–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaynes, E. T. (1973). Survey of the present status of neoclassical radiation theory. In L. Mandel & E. Wolf (Eds.), Coherence and quantum optics (p. 35). New York: Plenum.

  • Madelung, E. (1926). Eine anschauliche Deutung der Gleichung von Schrdinger. Naturwissenschaften, 14, 1004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Madelung, E. (1927). Quantentheorie in hydrodynamischer form. Zeitschrift fur Physik, 40, 322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, E. (1966). Derivation of the Schrödinger equation from Newtonian mechanics. Physical Review, 150, 1079–1085.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1998). Quantum computation, entanglement and state reduction. Philosophical Transactions Royal Society of London Series A, 356, 1927.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1926a). Über das Verhältnis der Heisenberg–Born–Jordanschen Quantenmechanik zu der meinen. Annalen der Physik, 79, 734–756. (English translation: On the Relation between the Quantum Mechanics of Heisenberg, Born, and Jordan, and that of Schrödinger. Reprint in Schrödinger (1982). pp. 45–61).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1926b). Quantisierung als Eigenwertproblem (dritte Mitteilung: Störungstheorie, mit Anwendung auf den Starkeffekt der Balmerlinien). Annalen der Physik, 80, 437–490. (English translation: Quantisation as a Problem of Proper Values. Part III, Reprint in Schrödinger (1982). pp. 62–101).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1926c). Quantisierung als Eigenwertproblem (vierte Mitteilung). Annalen der Physik, 81, 109–139.(English translation: Quantisation as a Problem of Proper Values. Part IV, Reprint in Schrödinger (1982). pp. 102–123).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrödinger, E. (1928). La mecanique des ondes. In Electrons et Photons: Rapports et Discussions du Cinquieme Conseil de Physique, tenu a Bruxelles du 24 au 29 Octobre 1927. Institut International de Physique Solvav. ed. Paris: Gauthier-Villars. pp. 185–213. (English translation: Wave Mechanics, in Bacciagaluppi and Valentini (2009), pp. 406–424).

  • Schrödinger, E. (1982). Collected papers on wave mechanics. New York: Chelsea Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vink, J. C. (1993). Quantum mechanics in terms of discrete beables. Physical Review A, 48, 1808.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to two anonymous referees of this journal for their insightful comments, constructive criticisms and helpful suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shan Gao.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gao, S. Is an Electron a Charge Cloud? A Reexamination of Schrödinger’s Charge Density Hypothesis. Found Sci 23, 145–157 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-017-9521-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-017-9521-3

Keywords

Navigation