Skip to main content
Log in

Generic Moral Grounding

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Moral theories often issue general principles that explain our moral judgments in terms of underlying moral considerations. But it is unclear whether the general principles have an explanatory role beyond the underlying moral considerations. In order to avoid the redundancy of their principles, two-level theories issue principles that appear to generalize beyond the considerations that ground them. In doing so, the principles appear to overgeneralize. The problem is conspicuous in the case of contractualism, which proposes that moral principles are grounded in generic reasons that operate in only a subset of the cases covered by the relevant principle. Arguments that motivate the use of generic reasons on the basis of guidance, institutional necessity, or fairness are unsatisfactory. But the generality of moral principles can be justified in terms of the idea of a generic interest, which is an interest that all occupants of a standpoint have in virtue of what occupants of the standpoint as such typically take an interest in. The notion of a generic interest therefore acknowledges a distinction between having and taking an interest, and its use in moral theory is a way of giving expression to the significance of autonomy. This is reminiscent of the idea of a normative power; but the idea of a generic interest is less expensive and makes better sense of the way in which autonomy features in our moral lives.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It has become commonplace to distinguish between the metaphysical grounding of some moral fact p (what makes p necessary) and its normative grounding (what makes it normatively necessary). See Leary (forthcoming), Bader (2017), and Fine (2012). I abstain from discussion of the relation between these two concepts, and by moral grounding refer to a kind of normative grounding.

  2. It is tempting to frame the project of moral theory in term of explanation, but work on the nature of moral explanation, such as Leibowitz (2011), Schroeder (2014), and Väyrynen (2009, 2013, 2019, forthcoming) suggests that notions such as explanation and justification must be treated with great caution in the moral domain. By making use of the notion of moral grounding I hope to distinguish my subject matter from several otherwise legitimate avenues of theorizing that are suggested by the idea of explaining or justifying moral facts. First among these is the metaethical pursuit which seeks to show the metaphysical underpinnings of the normativity of moral facts, and which may be understood as an attempt to explain how there could be any such facts. Second, there is the project of reconstructing practical reason in a manner that explains the priority that moral facts have amongst the other considerations that bear on what one should do. This project aims to justify the general force of moral requirements, but it may stop short of justifying particular moral requirements. Third, there is the project of showing that our moral judgments are epistemically well-grounded, a project which may well advance by showing that our capacity to make accurate moral judgments is not accidental in light of the kind of creature we are. The success of that project may rest on showing that we have epistemic access to the grounds of particular moral judgments, but the focus is on our epistemic access, rather than the grounds themselves.

  3. The qualifications in this principles are attempts to say what would save an instance of non-compliance with a particular promise from being an impermissible promise-breaking in the first place. Some may think that particular such instances—say those which are responses to unforeseen emergencies—are still promise-breakings, though they are excused for reasons that go to the culpability of the promise-breaker rather than permissibility of their action. But no doubt there are some qualifications to the impermissibility of not complying with one’s promise. Any reader who thinks my statement of a principle of impermissible promise-breaking has failed to come close to the correct qualifications may substitute their own principle for Promising.

  4. Berker (2018) specifies redundancy as the claim that moral principles are not explanation-serving—they could not have any role in explaining our moral judgments about particular cases. We could accept this (roughly Humean) conclusion, except that once we lose our sense that moral principles have an explanatory role, we might also lose confidence that they do a good job reflecting the generality of our patterns of moral judgment (for a different concern see Enoch 2019). That is because the intuitive plausibility of a principle like Promising rests not on the fact that it appears to be a good summary of our particular judgments, but rather on the fact that it appears to play an important role in our deliberation. Displacing it from this role, we may easily come to wonder whether its generality is an accurate summary. In what follows it will be plain that I am not much concerned about redundancy so long as we can vindicate the generality of our patterns of moral judgment.

  5. From a certain viewpoint, the problem may appear to be better described as one of underdetermination. If the Promising appropriately applies in cases X and Y, but our best theory grounds the principle in considerations that appear only in X, then its scope of application is underdetermined by the considerations we have supplied. Too bad for our theory, one might think; but too bad for the principle, whether we correct its scope or our explanation of its scope.

  6. A version of the first strategy, as an explicit response to redundancy, is found in Warnock (1971: 53–70). Presaging Raz, Warnock suggests that the force of a rule is ‘to exclude from practical consideration the particular merits of particular cases, by specifying in advance what is to be done, whatever the circumstances of the particular cases may be’ (65). But (as Warnock agrees) this will not solve the problem. While it may be important from a psychological point of view for deliberation to have the guardrails of exclusionary reasons, the agent who does properly consider all the merits of a particular case will surely come to the conclusion that he should not phi in a case whose merits support the rule. In such a case there is no need for the rule beyond convenience. Where the case’s particular merits do not support the rule, we may wonder why it is then covered by the rule. At this point we are confronted with the problem of overgeneralization.

  7. This claim is familiar from earlier ethical arguments e.g. Singer (1971).

  8. This objection, that contractualism is threatened by redundancy, was made early on by Thomson (1990, 188n5), but has since been made and dismissed by many commentators. For thorough discussion, see Suikannen (2005).

  9. For defense of the claim that G necessarily follows from F, see Trogdon (2013).

  10. The idea of generic reasons also plays a crucial role in Scanlon’s account of the importance of choice (1998: 248–67, especially at 263). My alternative suggestion in what follows is that the importance of choice in fact plays a more fundamental role in moral theory than the generality that the idea of generic reasons aims to capture.

    Going beyond Scanlon’s applications, Kumar (2003, 2009, 2018) has noticed that generic reasons might be used to provide a contractualist response to venerable puzzles such as the non-identity problem and the non-consequentialist approach to problems involving risk and aggregation. I set aside whether my alternative can retain the distinctiveness of contractualism in these areas.

  11. In what follows I focus on the possibility that principles are rooted in our epistemic boundedness. Another possibility, but one which could be dealt with along similar lines, is that morality issues principles as a way of accommodating our tendency to overgeneralize—see Lerner and Leslie (2013).

  12. On the distinction between excuse and justification, see Austin (1956), Zimmerman (2004), and Williamson (forthcoming). Williamson is prepared to apply the distinction to the case of justified belief, and the statement in the text above could be read in this way too i.e. one may be sufficiently badly placed to understand what interests bear on one’s phi-ing such that one has an excuse, though no justification, for believing that it is right to phi. This would not detract from the fact that one also has an excuse for phi-ing.

  13. Note that you can take an interest in whether there is a swimming pool or not even if you do not hope that there is a swimming pool. You may hope that there is not, perhaps because you think it wastes water. But note that ‘taking an interest in whether x’ is best understood as ‘taking an interest in knowing whether x.’ Knowing that x is the case, you may now take an interest in x not obtaining.

  14. The threat seems to me to arise insofar as interests are presumptively universal. Suppose it serves my own autonomy that I have more than others, by providing me with opportunities for making others serve me and enjoying positional status. Still, morality does not respond to such an interest insofar as there is no reason for me to have it specially; and it does not respond to such an interest on behalf of everyone, since it makes no sense for each to have more than everyone else.

  15. I don’t mean to narrow the value of control to what Scanlon calls its ‘predictive’ or ‘instrumental’ value (1998: 251–53). Perhaps one reason that a promisee has a generic interest worth protecting is that, even where promissory assurance plays no actual role in their life, having the open possibility of relying upon the promisor’s assurance represents the independent fact that the promisee is vulnerable to the promisor’s actions, or stands in some other relation of power to the promisor. (Consider especially the dynamics of promises in intimate relationships described by Shiffrin 2008.) There is a non-instrumental connection between the promisee’s choice and their interest in the quality of their relationship with the promisor in such cases, though its importance stands in need of vindication.

References

  • Austin JL (1956) A plea for excuses. Proc Aristot Soc 57:1–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bader R (2017) The grounding argument against non-reductive moral realism. In: Shafer-Landau (ed) Oxford studies in Metaethics, vol 12. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Berker S (2018) The explanatory ambitions of moral principles. Noûs 53:904–936

  • Enoch D (2019) How principles ground. In: Shafer-Landau (ed) Oxford studies in Metaethics, vol 14. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine K (2012) Guide to ground. In: Correia, Schnieder (eds) Metaphysical grounding. Cambridge University press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kumar R (2003) Who can be wronged? Philos Public Aff 31(2):99–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kumar R (2009) Wronging future people: a contractualist proposal. In: Gosseries A, Meyers LH (eds) Intergenerational justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Kumar R (2018) Risking future generations. Ethical Theory & Moral Practice 21:245–257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leary S (forthcoming) Normativity. In: Raven MJ (ed) Routledge handbook of metaphysical grounding. Routledge, New York

  • Leibowitz UD (2011) Scientific explanation and moral explanation. Noûs 45(3):472–503

    Google Scholar 

  • Lerner A, Leslie SJ (2013) Generics, generalism, and reflective equilibrium. Philos Perspect 27:366–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owens D (2012) Shaping the normative landscape. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Owens D (2019) Property and authority. J Polit Philos 27(3):271–293

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1955) Two concepts of rules. Philos Rev 64(1):3–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1999) A theory of justice, Revised edn. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1972) Voluntary obligations and normative powers. Proc Aristot Soc 46:79–102

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon TM (1988) Levels of moral thinking. In: Seanor D, Fotion N (eds) Hare and critics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Scanlon TM (1998) What we owe to each other. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler S (2010) Valuing. In: Equality and tradition. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder M (2014) Explaining the reasons we share. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin SV (2008) Promising, intimate relationships, and conventionalism. Philos Rev 117:481–524

  • Singer MG (1971) Generalization in ethics. Russell & Russell, New York

  • Suikannen J (2005) Contractualist replies to the redundancy objections. Theoria 71(1):38–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson JJ (1990) The realm of rights. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Trogdon K (2013) Grounding: necessary or contingent. Pac Philos Q 94:265–285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen P (2009) A theory of hedged moral principles. In: Shafer-Landau (ed) Oxford studies in Metaethics, vol 4. Oxford University press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen P (2013) Grounding and normative explanation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 87:155–178

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen P (2019) Reasons why in normative explanation. Inquiry 62(6):607–623

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Väyrynen P (forthcoming) Normative explanation and justification. Noûs

  • Wallace RJ (1994) Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Warnock GJ (1971) The object of morality. Methuen & Co, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (forthcoming) justifications, excuses, and sceptical scenarios. In: Dutant, Dorsch (eds) The new evil demon. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Zimmerman MJ (2004) Another plea for excuses. Am Philos Q 41:259–266

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper was presented at the British Society for Ethical Theory Annual Conference 2019. I am grateful to the organizers, and to audience members for valuable comments. I also received valuable comments from members of the Penn Normative Philosophy Group, and two anonymous reviewers. I am especially indebted to Rahul Kumar, Errol Lord, Pekka Väyrynen, and Daniel Wodak for patient discussion of the issues. I regret that I was unable to accommodate all of the wise recommendations I received.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Julian Jonker.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jonker, J. Generic Moral Grounding. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 23, 23–38 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10074-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-020-10074-3

Keywords

Navigation