Skip to main content
Log in

Why the Concept of Moral Status Should be Abandoned

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The use of the concept of moral status is commonplace today in debates about the moral consideration of entities lacking certain special capacities, such as nonhuman animals. This concept has been typically used to defend the view that adult human beings have a status higher than all those entities. However, even those who disagree with this claim have often accepted the idea of moral status as if it were part of an undisputed received way of thinking in ethics. This paper argues that the use of this concept, however common, distorts our understanding of how to behave towards different individuals in different circumstances. When moral status is identified with the interest in living or the capacity for well-being, it becomes an arbitrary and irrelevant criterion. When it is used as a synonym of moral consideration or considerability, in a way that is compatible with the principle of equal consideration, it becomes trivial and confusing. When used, instead, to defend the unequal moral consideration of interests of equal weight, it has several implausible implications. In particular, the claim that unequal status is justified because of the value (either final or intrinsic, or instrumental) of cognitive capacities implausibly entails that our exercising those capacities should have priority over the promotion of our wellbeing. The idea of full moral status is also problematic as it implies the possibility of status monsters. In addition, its use is based in a misconceived way of what it would really entail to have a full status by virtue of having rational capacities. The paper concludes that we have strong reasons to abandon the concept of moral status altogether.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See for instance Sumner (1981); Clark (1977); Steiner (2008).

  2. See Sumner (1981); Steinbock (1992); McMahan (2002); Kamm (2007); DiSilvestro (2010); Morris (2011). The term ‘moral standing’ is sometimes used as a synonym for this.

  3. In some cases, an intermediate concept between the possession of these capacities and moral status is introduced. For example, it is argued that beings who possess the mentioned capacities are persons, and that this, in turn, grants them the possession of moral status (or of some special moral status). For the sake of simplicity, however, I will not examine the concept of personhood here and will just focus on moral status.

  4. See for instance Warren (1997).

  5. Hacker-Wright (2007); Hursthouse (2013). There are, however, many who claim that relations are also morally relevant and yet accept the standard view. Accordingly, they claim that our status determines partially, but not completely, how others should behave towards us. They can therefore claim that a relative should be treated better than a stranger, without necessarily arguing that their moral status would be different. See for instance Jaworska (2007); McMahan (2002).

  6. See McMahan (2002, espesially p. 208).

  7. Tooley (1983); Frey (1988).

  8. Bradley (2009); de Lazari-Radek and Singer (2014).

  9. See for instance Cavalieri (2001); Dunayer (2004).

  10. Vallentyne (2005, especially p. 423).

  11. Singer (2009).

  12. Sachs (2011).

  13. This has been argued for by Rachels (2004).

  14. DeGrazia (2008).

  15. Jaworska (2007).

  16. McMahan (2008); Kamm (2007, ch. 7).

  17. Kant (2002/1785); Carruthers (1992).

  18. Posner (2004), DeGrazia (2008, pp. 193–94).

  19. Kant (2002/1785). The most common objection against this claim is the argument from species overlap, see Horta (2014).

  20. McMahan (1996); Vallentyne (2005).

  21. This is so both if we understand the quality of experiences or preferences as trumping in value—as it has been assumed, not without controversy, that J.S. Mill held (1969, pp. 203–529)—or if we just understand quality as a feature of experiences that can make them better or worse without that meaning any kind of incommensurability.

  22. Nozick (1974, p. 41).

  23. This is also the case if instead of maximum moral status as such we consider the concept of equal maximum moral status. If instead of a single status monster there existed a group of individuals with the same capacities that the status monster has, then they would all have equally the maximum status that it would be possible for them to have. This would mean when their interests conflicted they would count the same, but for anyone else they would still be status monsters, their interests being more important than the aggregate interests of all other entities.

  24. See for instance Bostrom and Savulescu (2009).

  25. Buchanan (2009); Agar (2013). For a different view see Douglas (2013).

  26. See for instance McMahan (2002); Buchanan (2009).

References

  • Agar N (2013) Why is it possible to enhance moral status and why doing so is wrong? J Med Ethics 39:67–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bostrom N, Savulescu J (eds) (2009) Human enhancement. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley B (2009) Well-being and death. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan A (2009) Moral status and human enhancement. Philos Public Aff 37:346–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers P (1992) The animal issue: moral theory in practice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Cavalieri P (2001) The animal question: why nonhuman animals deserve human rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark SRL (1977) The moral status of animals. Claredon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • de Lazari-Radek K, Singer P (2014) The point of view of the universe: Sidgwick and contemporary ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia D (2008) Moral status as a matter of degree? South J Philos 46:181–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiSilvestro R (2010) Human capacities and moral status. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas T (2013) Human enhancement and supra-personal moral status. Philos Stud 162:473–497

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunayer J (2004) Speciesism. Ryce, Derwood

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey RG (1988) Moral standing, the value of lives, and speciesism. Between Species 4:191–201

    Google Scholar 

  • Horta O (2014) The scope of the argument from species overlap. J Appl Philos 31:142–154

  • Hacker-Wright J (2007) Moral status in virtue ethics. Philosophy 82:449–473

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse R (2013) Moral status. In: LaFollette H (ed) International encyclopedia of ethics. Wiley-Blackwell, Hoboken, pp 3422–3432

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaworska A (2007) Caring and full moral standing. Ethics 117:460–497

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamm FM (2007) Intricate ethics: rights, responsibilities, and permissible harm. Oxford University Press. New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (2002/1785) Groundwork of the metaphysic of morals. Oxford University, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (1996) Cognitive disability, misfortune, and justice. Philos Public Aff 25:3–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (2002) The ethics of killing: problems at the margins of life. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan J (2008) Challenges to human equality. J Ethics 12:81–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1969) Utilitarianism. In: Collected Works, vol. X, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

  • Morris CW (2011) The idea of moral standing. In: Beauchamp TL, Frey RG (eds) The Oxford handbook of animal ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 255–275

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1974) Anarchy, state and utopia. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner RA (2004) Animal rights: legal, philosophical and pragmatic perspectives. In: Sunstein C, Nussbaum M (eds) Animal rights: current debates and new directions. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 51–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels J (2004) Drawing lines. In: Sunstein C, Nussbaum M (eds) Animal rights: current debates and new directions. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 162–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Sachs B (2011) The status of moral status. Pac Philos Q 92:87–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer P (2009) Speciesism and moral status. Metaphilosophy 40:567–581

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock, B (1992) Life before birth: the moral and legal status of embryos and fetuses. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Steiner G (2008) Animals and the moral community: mental life, moral status, and kinship. Columbia University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sumner LW (1981) Abortion and moral theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley M (1983) Abortion and infanticide. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallentyne P (2005) Of mice and men: equality and animals. J Ethics 9:403–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren MA (1997) Moral status: obligations to persons and other living things: obligations to persons and other living things. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Oscar Horta.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Horta, O. Why the Concept of Moral Status Should be Abandoned. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 20, 899–910 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-017-9829-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-017-9829-7

Keywords

Navigation