Skip to main content
Log in

Situationism, Manipulation, and Objective Self-Awareness

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Among those taking the implications of situationism seriously, some have suggested exploiting our tendency to be shaped by our environments toward desirable ends. The key insight here is that if experimental studies produce reliable, probabilistic predictions about the effects of situational variables on behavior—for example, how people react to the presence or absence of various sounds, objects, and their placement—then we should deploy those variables that promote prosocial behavior, while avoiding or limiting those that tend toward antisocial behavior. Put another way, some have suggested that we tweak situations to nudge or influence others toward good behavior. A question arises: Isn’t this manipulative? In this paper, I describe some existing proposals in the literature and consider the manipulation worry. Drawing on classical Confucian ethics, I argue that, when all is considered, it is chimerical to think we can refrain from influencing or manipulating others. We must rather accept that influence (whether intended or not) is part of social existence. Once we accept this, the only remaining question is how to influence others. I suggest that this should make us conceive ourselves in an objective fashion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Mengzi sometimes deviates from this pattern. See, e.g. Mengzi 2A2 (Van Norden 2008).

  2. Alfano agrees that a proper understanding of situationism yields both that situations affect persons and that persons affect situations, yet he finds my development of this theme “leaves much to be desired.” “Though [Sarkissian] is doubtless right that ‘not only do situations affect our own behavior, but we too return the favor,’ he provides no warrant for the further, blithely optimistic, claim that ‘we influence the situations we find ourselves in as much as they influence us’ (emphasis mine). The fact that there is a two-way street running between situations and persons does not entail that the traffic is equal in both directions” (Alfano 2013b, 253). Alfano interprets the latter quotation as suggesting something very strong—namely, that the impact of persons and situations is always equivalent. Taken out of its original context, such a reading is understandable. However, this does not reflect my considered view. In that article, I emphasize the potential for the impact to be equal in both directions. This leaves it open whether, to what extent, and how often influences flow one way or the other.

  3. Alfano claims that invoking de as capable of influencing others is question-begging because, “like any other global trait, de may not be common or even commonly acquirable. Answering the situationist challenge to virtue ethics by baldly asserting the existence of a virtue that gives one power over situations is clearly question-begging. I prefer to focus on ways in which situations can be rigged in advance, before one is called on to act in accordance with some virtue or other” (Alfano 2013b, 254). These criticisms reveal a potential misunderstanding of how the Confucians understand de. First, de is something each person has without even trying to acquire it. The way that a person characteristically impacts or influences others constitutes that person’s de. Confucians were preoccupied by the de of noble persons (or, for our purposes, moral exemplars). They noted that the noble person’s de would characteristically put others at ease. Through their appearance, countenance, demeanor—that is, through their very presence—such persons would harmonize with others. The de of a noble person stems as much from his or her scrutable self as it does from inner character. And minding one’s self-presentation is the kind of thing that can be done in advance of interacting with others through practice and habituation (DePaulo 1992). Finally, rather than “baldly asserting” the efficacy of de, I support it with experimental evidence (Sarkissian 2010, 9–10).

  4. In the original text, Fingarette’s transliterations observe the outdated Wage-Giles system (hence he uses jen for ren). Pinyin has been used here for consistency.

  5. Many thanks to Joseph Bendana, Jonathan Kwan, Nancy Snow, and especially to two anonymous referees for their comments on previous drafts, which led to important revisions and clarifications. Unfortunately, I was unable to incorporate all of their suggestions in the present paper.

References

  • Alfano M (2013a) Character as moral fiction. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alfano M (2013b) Identifying and defending the hard core of virtue ethics. J Philos Res 38:233–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brink DO (2013) Situationism, responsibility, and fair opportunity. Soc Philos Policy 30(1–2):121–149

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DePaulo BM (1992) Nonverbal behavior and self-presentation. Psychol Bull 111(2):203–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris JM (2002) Lack of character: personality and moral behavior. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Doris JM (2014) Talking to our selves: reflection, ignorance, and agency. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Duval S, Wicklund RA (1972) A theory of objective self awareness. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fingarette H (1972) Confucius: the secular as sacred. Harper & Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM, Welch B (2010) Debate: to nudge or not to nudge. J Polit Philos 18(1):123–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heine SJ, Buchtel EE (2009) Personality: the universal and the culturally specific. Annu Rev Psychol 60:369–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutton EL (2006) Character, situationism, and early confucian thought. Philos Stud 127(1):37–58

  • Hutton EL (2014) Xunzi: the complete text. Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Levy N (2016) Talking to our selves: reflection, ignorance, and agency, by Doris, John M. Australas J Philos 94(3):605–608

  • Li C (2006) The Confucian ideal of harmony. Philo East West 56(4):583–603

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McTernan E (2014) How to make citizens behave: social psychology, liberal virtues, and social norms. J Polit Philos 22(1):84–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merritt M (2000) Virtue ethics and situationist personality psychology. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 3(4):365–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller RL, Brickman P, Bolen D (1975) Attribution versus persuasion as a means for modifying behavior. J Pers Soc Psychol 31(3):430–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mower DS (2013) Situationism and Confucian virtue ethics. Ethical Theory Moral Pract 16(1):113–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T (1979) Mortal Questions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nahmias E (2007) Autonomous agency and social psychology. In: Marraffa M, De Caro M, Ferretti F (eds) Cartographies of the mind. Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht, pp 169–185

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Raz J (1986) The morality of freedom. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkissian H (2010) Minor tweaks, major payoffs: the problems and promise of situationism in moral philosophy. Philos Imprint 10(9):1–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Selinger E, Whyte K (2011) Is there a right way to nudge? The practice and ethics of choice architecture. Sociol Compass 5(10):923–935

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slingerland E (2011) The situationist critique and early Confucian virtue ethics. Ethics 121(2):390–419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2003) Libertarian paternalism. Am Econ Rev 93(2):175–179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2008) Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Norden B (2008) Mengzi: with selections from traditional commentaries. Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas M (2013) Situationism and moral responsibility: free will in fragments. In: Julian CAK, Vierkant T (eds) Decomposing the will. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 325–349

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson TM (2012) Nudging and manipulation. Pol Stud 61(2):341–355

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hagop Sarkissian.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sarkissian, H. Situationism, Manipulation, and Objective Self-Awareness. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 20, 489–503 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-017-9814-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-017-9814-1

Keywords

Navigation