Skip to main content
Log in

Right Reason Accounts of the Norm of Assertion

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A growing number of philosophers are defending what can be understood as Right Reason Accounts of the norm of assertion. According to these accounts, an agent’s asserting that p is epistemically permissible only if that agent asserts that p for a right (normative) reason, i.e., a reason that at least contributes to making it epistemically permissible to assert that p. In this paper, I argue that Right Reason Accounts do not allow for the possibility of asserting epistemically permissibly only for the wrong reason(s). However, it is a commonplace in all normative domains (e.g., morality, prudence, and aesthetics) that an agent can—at least sometimes—φ rightly (or permissibly) only for the wrong reason(s).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Weiner (2005) and Whiting (2013).

  2. Bach & Harnish (1979).

  3. Douven (2006), Lackey (2008), McKinnon (2015), and Willard-Kyle (2020).

  4. Kvanvig (2009, 2011).

  5. Unger (1975), Slote (2010), Williamson (2000), DeRose (2002), Sosa (2010), Turri (2011), Kelp and Simion (2019), and Simion (2016, 2018).

  6. Stanley (2008) and Petersen (2019).

  7. Lackey (2008), Turri (2011), Pelling (2013), McKinnon (2015), Gerken (2017), and Hughes (2019).

  8. I thank an anonymous referee for this journal for suggesting that I be clear that the right reason is undefeated.

  9. Turri (2011) introduces talk of “simple” versions of the norm of assertion.

  10. For example: Williamson (2000), Turri (2011), Littlejohn (2012, 157), McKinnon (2015), Kelp and Simion (2019), Simion (2018).

  11. McHugh (2012, 9).

  12. I am not suggesting that these domains (e.g., morality, prudence, and aesthetics) are only prescriptive, just that they provide or are partly constituted by prescriptive norms.

  13. Darwall (2016, 20; 2017,5) endorses a version of this view concerning morality.

  14. Scanlon (2008) defends a relationship-modification view about moral blame while Boult (2020) defends such a view about epistemic blame.

  15. Strawson (1962/2008).

  16. For such an account, see: Kauppinen (2018). For other defenses of specifically epistemic notions of blame, see: Brown (2020), Boult (2020), and Lewis (2021).

  17. Davidson (1980a, 3) and Arpaly and Schroeder, 2013, Chapter 3).

  18. For more on the distinction between kinds of reasons, see: Alvarez (2010, Chapter 2). Many think that motivating reasons are a subset of explanatory reasons. For my purposes, I will understand “explanatory reasons” as referring to non-motivating explanatory reasons.

  19. For example, see: Sylvan (2016, 377) and Bondy and Carter, 2019, 2).

  20. McKinnon (2015) talks about “proper basing” (52) while Gerken (2017) talks about “appropriate basing” (157).

  21. For my purposes, I can remain neutral on the exact ontology of the “reason for which” relation. Many proponents of RRT accounts (e.g., Turri, Pelling, and McKinnon) have in mind a causal account of the basing relation and, of course, a mainstream view of acting for a reason is likewise a causal view. For example, see Davidson (1980a and (1980b) and Arpaly and Schroeder, 2013, Ch. 3).

  22. Lackey (2008), 125.

  23. Turri (2011), 41.

  24. See: Davidson (1980b) and Arpaly and Schroeder, 2013, Ch. 3).

  25. Pelling (2013, 294).

  26. Pelling (2013, 300).

  27. Pelling (2013, 298-299).

  28. McKinnon (2015), 52.

  29. McKinnon (2015, 52).

  30. Gerken (2017, 157).

  31. Hughes (2019, 173, 181).

  32. McKinnon (2015, Ch. 4). McKinnon explicitly notes that both her and Lackey’s and Turri’s accounts require asserting for the right reason (64, fn. 21).

  33. McKinnon (2015, 55).

  34. Lackey (2008, 126), Turri (2011, 40-41), and Hughes (2019, 174).

  35. For example, Williamson, 2000, 47, 255-56), Sutton (2005, 2005), Littlejohn (2013, 310).

  36. For example, Turri (2010, 313) and Littlejohn (2012, 8).

  37. For example, Alston (1989, 108), Pollock & Cruz (1999, 356), and Korcz (2000, 46).

  38. Williamson (2000, 255-256) and Turri (2011, 44).

  39. Benton (2012, 86-87), Greco (2015), Turri (2016), and Kelp and Simion (2019), Simion, 2016, 3042; 2018, 479). See also: Millikan (2004) and Graham (2010)).

  40. Infrequently, a single fact can constitute a right reason and a wrong reason. For example, the fact that an action will result in the death of innocent civilians counts against performing the action, but that same fact might also lead an evil empire to surrender and thus count in favor of performing the action. Thus, the fact that one’s action will result in the death of innocent civilians counts both for and against that action. Even though such cases exist, I will only rely on cases in which a wrong reason to φ is not also a right reason to φ. Moreover, the commonplace that one can φ permissibly for the wrong reason(s) is meant to apply to wrong reasons that are not also right reasons.

  41. To be clear, I’m not arguing that this is a decisive reason for rejecting Right Reason Accounts. However, it certainly provides a strong reason against these views.

  42. Mill (1871/2015, 131-132), Moore (1912/2005, 94-98), Sidgwick (1962, 204). Generally, consequentialists deny the relevance of the motives to moral permissibility.

  43. Broad (1928, 297), Ross (1930, 4-6; 1939, Chapter 6); Thomson (1999, 517); Kamm (2007, 138), and Scanlon (2008, Chapters 1-3).

  44. Aristotle NE 1105b.

  45. Timmons (2002).

  46. Kant G. 4:397.

  47. The claim that the fact that p is an objective reason to believe that p, see: Sylvan & Sosa (2018, 569).

  48. Schroeder (2018) and Whiting (2020) endorse the view that truth makes for objectively epistemically permissible belief while one’s evidence makes for subjectively epistemically permissible belief.

  49. This distinction comes from Firth (1978) who distinguished between “propositional warrant” and “doxastic warrant.”

  50. While the exact difference between these domains is controversial, philosophers indicate that the authoritative normative domains are “robustly” normative (McPherson (2011) or normatively “authoritative” (Wodak (2019) while formal ones are not.

  51. Martin (1983, 13).

  52. Gardner (2007, 147).

  53. Austin (1961, 226), Austin (1962, 15), Searle (1969, 60), and Searle & Vanderveken (1985, 18–19).

  54. Others defend the view that sincerity is a matter of having certain beliefs about what mental states one has when makes the relevant utterances (e.g., Ridge 2006). But, again, the view is not that one must perform some speech act on the basis of this belief, simply that one must have it at the time of utterance. Moreover, domains such as the promissory or assertoric are not the kind of authoritative demands that I am focused on. This is because, in part, they do not have distinctive blaming responses for unexcused violations of their norms. Moreover, the way that Austin speaks about insincere utterances suggests that he is talking about evaluative and not prescriptive standards. For example, he characterizes insincere utterances as “hollow” (1961, 226; 1962, 16, 18). Insofar as he is not just using a synonym for insincere, we might interpret him as meaning that these utterances lack a certain value.

  55. Sverdlik (1996, 339; 2011, 16), Gorr (1999, 582), Slote (2001), Tadros (2011, 140), Wedgwood (2011), and Liao (2012).

  56. McMahan (2009), Tadros (2011), Wedgwood (2011), and Liao (2012).

  57. Sverdlik (1996, 343).

  58. I thank an anonymous referee for this journal for helping me see the importance of being clear about the generality of my objection.

  59. Raz (1999, 39).

  60. Raz (1999, 47).

  61. Raz (1999, 49).

  62. Raz (1999, 39).

  63. Sometimes a single consideration can provide a first-order reason for an action and second-order reason to exclude acting for certain other reasons. For example, Raz (1999) gives the example of a soldier being ordered by his commanding officer to commandeer a van. This order is a first-order reason to commandeer the vehicle. However, it is, according to Raz, a second-order reason to exclude any reasons against commandeering the vehicle (42).

  64. Ross (1930, 5; 1939, 115-116) and Scanlon (2008, 58-60).

  65. For a similar argument, see: Scanlon (2008, 58-60).

  66. Dancy (2000, 4).

  67. Davidson (1980a), Mele (1992), Smith (1987, 1994), and Lenman (1996).

  68. Of course, the “Koplik’s spots” need not figure in the literal content of Dave’s belief. Rather, he might just believe that they are “the spots that indicate measles” or something related.

  69. Whiting (2017, 405).

  70. For more on this point, see: Whiting (2017, 404).

  71. Lackey (2008, 107 and 131), Gerken (2017, 157); (De Rose 2002, 180);

  72. I have placed “epistemically” in parenthesis because it is controversial whether there are different flavors of fittingness (e.g., moral, prudential, aesthetic, epistemic, etc.).

  73. I thank an anonymous referee for this journal for suggesting that I offer some explanation of why so many epistemologists seemed to miss the fact that their views are incompatible with the possibility of asserting epistemically permissibly only for the wrong reason(s).

  74. Hughes (2019) is explicit that the norm of assertion, whatever it precisely amounts to, ought to match the conditions for knowledge. Lackey (2007, 126, fn. 33) claims that the proper basing condition of her account is meant to be analogous to whatever condition on knowledge rules out Gettier cases—i.e., cases of justified, but accidentally true, belief.

  75. Lackey, 2008, 126, fn. 33), Turri (2011, 42, fn. 12), Pelling, 2013, 295, 298, and 299-303), and McKinnon (2015, 59).

  76. For example, see: Markovits (2010) and Lord (2015).

  77. Benton (2012, 86–87), Greco (2015), Turri (2016), Kelp (2016), Kelp and Simion (2019), Simion, (2016, 3042; 2018, 479). See also: Millikan (2004) and Graham (2010)).

  78. For example, see: Markovits (2010).

  79. In fact, Lackey (2007) seems to acknowledge that asserters that satisfy her performed norm of assertion are praiseworthy qua asserters (112).

  80. See: Schroeder (2018) and Whiting (2020).

  81. Lackey, 2008, 118).

  82. Lackey, 2008, 118–124), Turri (2011, 43), and McKinnon (2015, 54). The primary/secondary propriety/impropriety distinction comes from DeRose (2002, 180).

  83. For example, Mill (1871/2015, 132), Thomson (1999, 517), and Scanlon (2008, 27–28).

  84. For example, see: Lewis (2021).

  85. Moreover, it is also not clear that the important work done by the right reason requirement cannot be done with other machinery. For example, as I just mentioned, appealing to epistemic blameworthiness can plausibly account for why it is intuitively epistemically defective to assert on the basis of a bad epistemic reason.

References

  • Alston, W. P. (1989). Epistemic Justification: Essays in the Theory of Knowledge. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez, M. (2010). Kinds of Reasons. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arpaly, N., & Schroeder, T. (2013). In Praise of Desire. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). How to Do Things with Words. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. (1961). Philosophical Papers. In:  Edited Urmson J.O. & G.J.

  • Bach, K., & Harnish, R. M. (1979). Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benton, Matthew A. (2012). Knowledge Norms: Assertion, Action, and Belief. Rutgers University. https://rucore.libraries.rutgers.edu/rutgers-lib/37370/PDF/1/

  • Bondy, P., & Carter, A. J. (2019). Introduction. In Adam J. Carter & Patrick Bondy (Eds.), Well-Founded Belief (pp. 1–11).

    Google Scholar 

  • Boult, C. (2020). There is a distinctively epistemic kind of blame. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 00, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C. D. (1928). Analysis of Some Ethical Concepts. Philosophy, 3(11), 285–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2020). Epistemically Blameworthy Belief. Philosophical Studies, 177, 3595–3614.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2000). Practical Reality. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2016). Taking Account of Character and Being an Accountable Person. In M. Timmons (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics (Vol. 6, pp. 12–36). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, Stephen. 2017. What Are Moral Reasons? The Amherst Lecture in Philosophy 12: 1–24. https://www.amherstlecture.org/darwall2017/. Accessed 01 Jan 2022

  • Davidson, Donald. (1980a). Actions, Reasons, and Causes. In Essays on Actions and Events, 3–19. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Davidson, Donald. (1980b). Freedom to Act. In Essays on Actions and Events, 63–81.

  • DeRose, K. (2002). Assertion, knowledge, and context. Philosophical Review, 111, 167–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2006). Assertion, Knowledge, and Rational Credibility. Philosophical Review, 115(4), 449–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Firth, Roderick. (1978). Are Epistemic Concepts Reducible to Ethical Concepts? In Alvin Goldman and Jaegwon Kim (eds.), Values and Morals, 215–229.

  • Gardner, John. (2007). Fletcher on Offences and Defences. In Offences and Defences, 141–153.

  • Gerken, M. (2017). On Folk Epistemology: How we think and talk about knowledge. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gorr, M. (1999). Motives and Rightness. Philosophia, 27(3–4), 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, P. J. (2010). Testimonial entitlement and the function of comprehension. In S. Epistemology (Ed.), Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, and Duncan Pritchard (pp. 148–174). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2015). Post-Gettier Epistemology. Veritas, 60(3), 421–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, N. (2019). Knowledgeable assertion in the image of knowledgeable belief. Inquiry, 62(2), 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (1999). On Virtue Ethics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. (2007). Intricate Ethics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2018). Epistemic Norms and Epistemic Accountability. Philosophers’ Imprint, 18(8), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2016). Assertion: a function first account. Noûs, 50(2), 411–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C., & Simion M. (2019). (Manuscript). Assertion: a function first account.

  • Korcz, K. A. (2000). The Causal-Doxastic Theory of the Basing Relation. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 30(4), 525–550.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korcz, Keith Allen. (2021). The Epistemic Basing Relation. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/basing-epistemic/. Accessed 12 Sep 2022

  • Kvanvig, J. (2009). Assertion, Knowledge, and Lotteries. In P. Greenough & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Williamson on Knowledge (pp. 140–160). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2011). Norms of Assertion. In J. Brown & H. Cappelen (Eds.), Assertion (pp. 233–250). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (2008). Learning from Words. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lenman, J. (1996). Belief, Desire and Motivation: An Essay on Quasi-Hydraulics. American Philosophical Quarterly, 33(3), 291–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, M. (2021). The Knowledge Norm of Assertion: Keep It Simple. Synthese, 199, 12963–12984.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S. M. (2012). Intentions and Moral Permissibility: The Case of Acting Permissibly with Bad Intentions. Law and Philosophy, 31(6), 703–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Littlejohn, C. (2012). Justification and the Truth-Connection. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Littlejohn, C. (2013). The Russellian Retreat. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary, 113(3), 293–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lord, Errol. (2015). Acting for the Right Reasons, Abilities, and Obligation. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics. (Vol. 10). Oxford University Press.

  • Markovits, J. (2010). Acting for the Right Reasons. Philosophical Review, 119, 201–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, J. (1983). Miss Manners’ Guide to Excruciatingly Correct Behavior. Warner Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • McHugh, C. (2012). The Truth Norm of Belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 93, 8–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinnon, R. (2015). The Norms of Assertion. Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (2009). Intention, Permissibility, Terrorism, and War. Philosophical Perspectives, 23, 345–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McPherson, T. (2011). Against Quietist Normative Realism. Philosophical Studies., 154(2), 223–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (1992). The Springs of Action. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. (1871/2015). On Liberty, Utilitarianism, and Other EssaysUtilitarianism. Edited by Mark Philp and Frederick Rosen.

  • Millikan, R. (2004). Varieties of Meaning. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1912/2005). Ethics. In: William H. S. (ed)

  • Pelling, C. (2013). Assertion and the Provision of Knowledge. The Philosophical Quarterly, 63(251), 293–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petersen, E. N. (2019). A case for a certainty norm of assertion. Synthese, 196(11), 4691–4710.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J., & Cruz, J. (1999). Contemporary Theories of Knowledge (2nd ed.). Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1999). Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ridge, M. (2006). Sincerity and Expressivism. Philosophical Studies, 131(2), 487–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1930). The Right and the Good. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1939). Foundations of Ethics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2008). Moral Dimensions: Permissibility, Meaning, Blame. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2018). Believing Well. In C. McHugh, J. Way, & D. Whiting (Eds.), Metaepistemology (pp. 196–212). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech Acts. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R., & Vanderveken, D. (1985). Foundations of Illocutionary Logic. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. (1962). The Methods of Ethics (7th ed.). Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simion, M. (2016). Assertion: Knowledge is Enough. Synthese, 193, 3041–3056.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simion, M. (2018). The Explanation Proffering Norm of Moral Assertion. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21, 477–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (2001). Morals from Motives. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slote, Michael. (2010). Assertion and belief. In Selected Essays, 94–102. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Smith, M. (1987). The Humean Theory of Motivation. Mind, 96(381), 36–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The Moral Problem. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2010). Value Matters in Epistemology. Journal of Philosophy, 107(4), 167–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2008). Knowledge and Certainty. Philosophical Issues, 18, 35–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1962/2008). Freedom and Resentment. In Freedom and Resentment and Other Essays, 1–28. New York: Routledge.

  • Sutton, J. (2005). Stick to What You Know. Noûs, 39(3), 359–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sverdlik, S. (1996). Motive and Rightness. Ethics, 106(2), 327–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sverdlik, S. (2011). Motive and Rightness. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sylvan, K. (2016). Epistemic Reasons II: Basing. Philosophy Compass, 11(7), 377–389. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sylvan, K., & Sosa, E. (2018). The Place of Reasons in Epistemology. In D. Star (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity (pp. 555–574). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, V. (2011). The Ends of Harm. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1999). Physician-Assisted Suicide: Two Moral Arguments. Ethics, 109(3), 497–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Timmons, M. (2002). Motive and Rightness in Kant’s Ethical System. In M. Timmons (Ed.), Kant’s “Metaphysics of Morals”: Interpretative Essays (pp. 255–288). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2010). On the Relationship between Propositional and Doxastic Justification. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80(2), 312–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2011). The Express Knowledge Account of Assertion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(1), 37–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2016). The point of assertion is to transmit knowledge. Analysis, 76(2), 130–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1975). Ignorance. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2011). Defending Double Effect. Ratio, 24(4), 384–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, M. (2005). Must We Know What We Say? Philosophical Review, 114, 227–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiting, D. (2013). Stick to the Facts: On the Norms of Assertion. Erkenntnis, 78, 847–867.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiting, D. (2017). Against Second-Order Reasons. Noûs, 51(2), 398–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiting, D. (2020). Epistemic Worth. Ergo, 7(3), 105–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Willard-Kyle, C. (2020). Being in a Position to Know is the Norm of Assertion. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 101(2), 328–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wodak, D. (2019). Mere formalities: Fictional normativity and normative authority. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 49(6), 828–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the Mind. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper benefitted from conversations with Errol Lord, Jaakko Hirvëla, Antti Kauppinen, Maria Lasonen-Aarnio, Michael Vazquez, and Yunjie Zhang.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Max Lewis.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lewis, M. Right Reason Accounts of the Norm of Assertion. Erkenn (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-024-00806-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-024-00806-7

Navigation