Skip to main content
Log in

Public Charades, or How the Enactivist Can Tell Apart Pretense from Non-pretense

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Enactive approaches to cognition argue that cognition, including pretense, comes about through the dynamical interaction of agent and environment. Applied to cognition, these approaches cast cognition as an activity an agent performs interacting in specific ways with her environment. This view is now under significant pressure: in a series of recent publications, Peter Langland-Hassan has proposed a number of arguments which purportedly should lead us to conclude that enactive approaches are unable to account for pretense without paying a way too severe theoretical price. In this paper, we will defend enactive approaches to pretense, arguing that they can in fact explain pretense without incurring in the negative theoretical consequences Peter Langland-Hassan fears. To this effect, we start by exposing Langland-Hassan’s challenge (§2), to then highlight its core assumptions and demonstrate their falsity (§3). Having done so, we argue that none of the theoretical consequences Langland-Hassan fears follow (§4), and in fact enactive approaches to cognition may be explanatorily superior to the one Langland-Hassan favors (§5). A brief conclusion will then follow (§6).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

Not applicable.

Code Availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. We will be using “enactive approaches”, “enactivism” and the like as collective names to refer to anti-representational 4E approaches. For more information on those, see (Gallagher, 2023; Ward et al., 2017).

  2. Langland-Hassan refers here to Angelique Lillard’s (1993, 1998) psychological experiments, which featured showing children a troll called ‘Moe’.

  3. Other representational recipes involve, i.e., recourse to imagining counterfactual scenarios such as being a bird in flight (Picciuto & Carruthers, 2016; van Leeuwen, 2011), or to a specialized cognitive architecture that allows for making inferences about birds (Nichols & Stich, 2003; for an overview, see Rucińska and Weichold (2022a). Our answer will stay neutral on this matter—its success will thus be independent from the success of any representationalist recipe.

  4. And that we will show to be highly problematic in Sect. 5.

  5. We’d like to thank the anonymous reviewer for this useful phrasing.

  6. One may fear our proposed definition is too demanding: couldn't the cases offered by Langland-Hassan pose a problem for enactivists, even if S and S* weren't complete kinematic duplicates – for example, if they behave only very similarly (but not identically), or if they act in slightly different environments? The answer is negative: if such differences – no matter how minuscule – are present in the examples, then the enactivist is free to appeal to those to tell apart pretense from other types of behavior. And notice that it would not be an ad hoc move: for the enactivist, cognitive phenomena are forms of agent-environment interaction: change interaction (or the environment) and the cognitive phenomenon will change too.

  7. Our argument has been largely inspired by Hurley’s (1998) attack on the “duplication assumption”.

  8. We prefer the (fairly ancient) nomenclature of “corollary discharge” rather than the more novel terminology based on pairs of (inverse and forward) models (e.g. Pickering & Clark, 2014), as the latter comes with a cognitivist and representationalist gloss that we prefer to avoid. For a way to replace it with an alternative, enactivism-friendly conceptualization (see Facchin, 2021).

  9. Notice that, at least when it comes to fine grained, “purely kinematic” aspects of movement, this view is widespread and well-accepted even among representationalists (Bongard & Pfeiffer, 2007; Clark, 1997).

  10. Many thanks to Shaun Gallagher for having suggested this scenario, and to one reviewer for indicating how to use it.

  11. Another way to frame the problem is this: enactivists want to explain various types of psychological phenomena in our world. What may happen in other possible worlds—especially distant ones—does not matter for their theorizing.

  12. A tree trunk, for example, affords different actions to a tired wanderer (e.g., leaning against it to rest), a bird-watcher (e.g., climbing on it) and an ant (e.g., searching for food). Of course, this isn’t to deny that the “material” features of the affordances do not matter: a tree trunk won’t afford flying or cooking, even to the world’s best pilot or chef. But the affective state of the person, or the context they are in, also influence what affordances are picked out. Both of the agential and environmental aspects will be important in understanding how affordances allow us to tell apart pretense games from other games.

  13. We write ‘seem to’, as we are not convinced that such ‘stepping away from the canonical affordances’ is required. As the context modulates which affordance calls forth our action, it is likely that in the context of play (e.g., playing a ‘calling game’), the object (the banana) immediately affords the alternative sense (pretend ‘telephoning’), without first affording eating that needs to be suppressed (Picciuto & Carruthers, 2016). For an elaboration of this argument, see Rucińska (2017).

  14. We suspect he would extend the complaint to canonical affordances of pretense-affording props (as opposed to other-games affording props).

  15. Does this mean that affordances are unanalyzable black boxes? No, it doesn't. Affordances can be qualitatively modeled (e.g. Jiang & Mark, 1994; Lopresti-Goodman et al., 2011; Warren, 1984), and their presence can be explained pointing to a variety of factors, including the physical properties of the environment and the objects therein, the embodiment of the agent and her skills.

  16. One of the three biblical Magi.

  17. Notice that Langland-Hassan puts his challenge in terms of best explanation. He’s not committed to the claim that an account of pretense must involve folk psychological attitudes (say, as a matter of conceptual necessity, see Langland-Hassan, 2022a, p. 1005).

  18. That is the case even if enactivists’ commitments to architectural details vary. For instance, radical enactivists’ (cf. Hutto & Myin, 2013, 2017) commitments to the cognitive architecture will be very minimal: they just commit to it being non-representational. In turn, autopoietic enactivists commit to a fairly specific and biologically inspired cognitive architecture based on autopoiesis (e.g. Di Paolo et al., 2016; Thompson, 2007).

  19. Notice that “reduction” does not indicate a relation holding between two theories, one of which is more fundamental than the other (cf. Nagel, 1961). Here, the reduction happens within the same theory (or at least the same linguistic framework), namely that of folk psychology.

References

  • Aizawa, K. (2017). Cognition and behavior. Synthese, 194(11), 4269–4288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1958). Pretending. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 32, 261–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, L. (2019). Enactivism, pragmatism… behaviorism? Philosophical Studies, 176(3), 807–818.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bongard, J., & Pfeiffer, R. (2007). How the Body Shapes the Way We Think. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bovet, S. (2007). Robots with Self-Developing Brains, Dissertation, University of Zurich https://www.zora.uzh.ch/id/eprint/163709/1/20080298_001884101.pdf. Accessed February 25, 2020.

  • Bruineberg, J., Chemero, A., & Rietveld, E. (2019). General ecological information supports engagement with affordances for ‘higher’ cognition. Synthese, 196(12), 5231–5251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1992). A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of the mind and the structure of science. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1989). Microcognition. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015). Predicting Peace: The end of the representation wars. In T. Metzinger & W. J. Windt (Eds.), Open Mind: 7(R). The MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, S. H., et al. (2001). A three-dimensional passive dynamic walking robot with two legs and knees. International Journal of Robotics Research, 20(7), 607–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costall, A. (2012). Canonical affordances in context. Avant, 2, 85–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Degenaar, J., & Myin, E. (2014). Representation-hunger reconsidered. Synthese, 191(15), 3639–3648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennet, D. (1987). The intentional stance. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., et al. (2016). Sensorimotor life. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A., Cuffari, E. C., & De Jaegher, H. (2018). Linguistic bodies: The continuity between life and language. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Facchin, M. (2021). Predictive processing and anti-representationalism. Synthese, 199(3), 11609–11642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finisguerra, A., et al. (2018). Dissociated representations of deceptive intentions and kinematic adaptations in the observer’s motor system. Cerebral Cortex, 28(1), 33–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, J. R., & Wing, A. M. (1997). The role of internal models in motion planning and control: evidence from grip force adjustments during movements of hand-hold objects. Journal of Neuroscience, 17(4), 1519–1528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, D. W., & Wolpert, D. M. (2011). Computational mechanism for sensorimotor control. Neuron, 72, 425–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2023). Embodied and enactive approaches to cognition. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gleason, T. R. (2013). Imaginary Relationships. In M. Taylor (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the development of imagination (pp. 251–271).

  • Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in Action. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (2022). Getting real about pretense: A radical enactivist proposal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 21(5), 1157–1175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism. The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, T. W. (2014). Emotion in languaging: Languaging as affective, adaptive, and flexible behavior in social interaction. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 720.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jiang, Y., & Mark, L. S. (1994). The effect of gap depth on the perception of whether a gap is crossable. Perception and Psychophysics, 56(6), 691–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, S. (1995). Dynamic patterns. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J. D., & Rietveld, E. (2018). Reconceiving representation-hungry cognition: An ecological-enactive proposal. Adaptive Behavior, 26(4), 147–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2018). What do predictive corders want? Synthese, 195(6), 2541–2557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2021). A Humean challenge to predictive coding. In D, Mendoça, M. Curado, S. Grouveia (Eds.), The philosophy and science of predictive processing (pp. 25–38). Bloomsbury Academics

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamb, M., & Chemero, A. (2018). Interacting in the open: When dynamical systems become extended and embodied. In A. Newen, L. de Bruin, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition (pp. 1147–1162). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2020). Explaining imagination. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2022a). Why pretense poses a problem for 4E cognition (and how to move forward). Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 21(5), 1003–1021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2022b). Secret charades: Reply to Hutto. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 21(5), 1183–1187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1987). Pretense and representation: The origins of “theory of mind.” Psychological Review, 94, 412–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lillard, A. (1993). Young children’s conceptualization of pretense: Action or mental representation state? Child Development, 64(2), 372–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lillard, A. (1998). Wanting to be it: Children’s understanding of intentions underlying pretense. Child Development, 69(4), 981–993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lopresti-Goodman, S. M., et al. (2011). Behavioral dynamics of the affordance «graspable». Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 73(6), 1948–1965.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ma, L., & Lillard, A. S. (2013). What makes an act a pretense one? Young children’s pretend-real judgments and explanations. Child Development Research.

  • Markis, S., & Urgesi, C. (2015). Neural underpinnings of superior action prediction abilities in soccer players. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 10(3), 342–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, T. (1990). Passive dynamic walking. International Journal of Robotics Research, 9(2), 68–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McNamee, D., & Wolpert, D. M. (2019). Internal models in biological control. Annual Review of Control, Robotics, and Autonomous Systems, 2, 339–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, self and society. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merker, B. (2005). The liabilities of motility: A selection pressure for the transition to consciousness in animal evolution. Consciousness and Cognition, 14(1), 89–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. Problems in the logic of explanation. Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2003). Mindreading. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Picciuto, E., & Carruthers, P. (2016). Imagination and Pretense. In A. Kind (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of imagination. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, M. J., & Clark, A. (2014). Getting ahead: Forward models and their place in cognitive architecture. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 18(9), 451–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W., et al. (1991). Connectionism, eliminativism, and the future of folk psychology. In W. Ramsey, S. Stich, & D. Rumelhart (Eds.), Philosophy and connectionist theory (pp. 199–228). Rutledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation Reconsidered. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E., et al. (2018). Ecological-Enactive cognition as engaging with a field of relevant affordances: the skilled intentionality framework (SIF). In A. Newen, L. De Bruin, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition (pp. 41–70). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). A rich landscape of affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26(4), 325–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2016). What guides pretence? Towards the interactive and narrative approaches. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15, 116–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2017). The role of affordances in pretend play. In C. Durt, T. Fuchs, & C. Tewes (Eds.), Embodiment, enaction and culture: Investigating the constitution of the shared world (pp. 257–278). The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z. (2019). Social and Enactive Perspectives on Pretending. Avant. https://doi.org/10.6913/avant.2019.03.15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z., & Weichold, M. (2022a). Pretense and imagination from the perspective of 4E cognitive science: Introduction to the special issue. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 21(5), 989–1001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rucińska, Z., & Weichold, M. (2022b). The roles of language in pretend play: A praxeological enactivist approach. Journal of Applied Psycholinguistics, 22(2), 17–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, D. G., & Singer, J. L. (1990). The house of make-believe: Children’s play and the developing imagination. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sperry, R. W. (1950). Neural basis of the spontaneous optokinetic response produced by visual inversion. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 43(6), 482–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Szokolszky, A., & Read, C. (2022). Pretend play with objects: An ecological approach. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 21(5), 1043–1068.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, M. (1999). Imaginary companions and the children who create them. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tidoni, E., et al. (2013). Action simulation plays a critical role in deceptive action recognition. Journal of Neuroscience, 33(2), 611–623.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. (1992). Affordances and prospective control: An outline of the ontology. Ecological Psychology, 4, 173–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valenti, S. S., & Gold, J. M. (1991). Social affordances and interaction I: Introduction. Ecological Psychology, 3(2), 77–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Leeuwen, N. (2011). Imagination is where the action is. The Journal of Philosophy, 108(2), 55–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, D., Silverman, D., & Villalobos, M. (2017). Introduction: The varieties of enactivism. Topoi, 36, 365–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, W. H. (1984). Perceiving affordances: Visual guidance of stair climbing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 10(5), 683–703.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webb, B. (2004). Neural mechanisms for predictions: Do insects have forward models? Trends in Neurosciences, 27(5), 278–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webb, B. (2019). The minds of insects. In M. Colombo, E. Irvine, & M. Stapleton (Eds.), Andy Clark and His Critics (pp. 254–265). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weichold, M., & Rucińska, S. (2022). Pretense as alternative sense-making: A praxeological enactivist account. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 21(5), 1131–1156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D. M., & Flanagan, J. R. (2001). Motor prediction. Current Biology, 11(18), R729-732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ZipoliCaiani, S. (2021). Intensional biases in affordance perception: An explanatory issue for radical enactivism. Synthese, 198(17), 4183–4203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ZipoliCaiani, S. (2022). Intelligence involves intensionality: An explanatory issue for radical enactivism (again). Synthese, 200(2), 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors wish to thank the participants of the WIP meeting in Antwerp University, Belgium, and the participants of the conference 'New Work in the Theory of Mind', University of Bucharest, Romania, for the very stimulating discussions on the earlier versions of this paper.

Funding

MF’s research is founded by the FWO grant “Towards a globally non-representational theory of the mind” (grant number 1202824N); ZR’s research was funded by the FWO grant “Enactive Approaches to Pretending” (grant number 12J0419N) and “Understanding virtual reality through ongoing embodied imagining” (grant number 12J0423N).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

The authors contributed equally.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Facchin.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare no conflict of interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Facchin, M., Rucińska, Z. Public Charades, or How the Enactivist Can Tell Apart Pretense from Non-pretense. Erkenn (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-024-00787-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-024-00787-7

Navigation