Skip to main content
Log in

Colors, Perceptual Variation, and Science

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

“It was one of those days when some particular quality in the light

and not merely the brilliance of the sun makes colours glow and sing…”

Patrick O’Brian, The Ionian Mission

Abstract

Arguments from perceptual variation challenge the view that colors are objective properties of objects, properties that objects have independent of how they are perceived. This paper attempts, first, to diagnose one central reason why arguments from perceptual variation seem especially challenging for objectivists about color. Second, we offer a response to this challenge, claiming that once we focus on determinate colors rather than the determinables they determine, a response to arguments from perceptual variation becomes apparent. Third, our nominal opponents are relationalist (like Cohen in The red and the real: an essay on color ontology, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2009) and we will argue that the main argument for rejecting objectivism commits the relationalist to a position that is more radical than the one he would wish to endorse. Fourth, we suggest that insight into which properties could be relational may be found by looking to our best scientific theories.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10
Fig. 11

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We credit Mark Eli Kalderon (2007, 2008, 2011a, 2011b) with the following insight; Kalderon credits Myles Burnyeat (1979); Burnyeat credits Heraclitus.

  2. Particularly, color (like length, temporal duration, shape, etc.) will be a frame-dependent property.

  3. See Jacobs (1981) and Lazareva et al. (2012).

  4. See Burnyeat (1979) for an interesting history of the various ways in which things go.

  5. The position we take here has been greatly influenced by Kalderon (2011a).

  6. What we have in mind here about colors is akin to what J.L. Austin (1962) has in mind when he reminds us that straight sticks appear differently when in the water; otherwise, they wouldn’t appear to be in the water. They have a bent look; which is not to say that they look bent.

  7. Mark Johnston (1992) argues that the nature of colors is revealed to us by color experiences. There is considerable debate about just what that revelation comes to and whether it is true.

  8. We set aside further ambiguities concerning “same color.” Two objects might be the same color for all humans, but not for some creature that is sensitive to light outside our visual range. In what follows, we limit our discussion to those (ultimately determinate) colors determinate of (those more determinable) human colors.

  9. Unique blue, then, is not an ultimately determinate shade. Two objects might match under some lighting condition, and, under that lighting condition, both appear to be blue with no green or red in it; but when we see them under different lighting, their differences become manifest. And surely, intuitively, the difference we see is a color difference. Indeed, with Joshua Gert (2006), we doubt that there is a fact of the matter about which objects are unique blue, and we agree with Gert that this should not lead us to doubt that there are colors. Our agreement is only superficial, however. Gert’s claim is that something might be blue, although it has no determinate color. Our claim is that anything that is colored has a determinate color, although there may be no fact of the matter as to which determinable color it has. Compare: the water has whatever determinate temperature it has, but there may not be a fact of the matter as to whether it is slightly warm or merely tepid.

  10. As an analysis, this is circular. We would have analyzed two things having the same color by appeal to their matching in color. But we do not intend this as an analysis, as we’ll try to make clearer in the end. In any case, an understanding of what it is for objects to appear the same or different with respect to color is assumed by proponents of arguments from perceptual variation. If one doesn’t understand perceptual variation, then one doesn’t understand the argument to which we are responding to in this paper. And if one can’t understand that argument, then we can’t understand why anyone would be worried.

  11. Aristotle, p. 936 (Nicomachean Ethics, Bk 1, Ch. 2, 194b, lines 13–14).

  12. See Watkins (2002, 2005, and forthcoming(a)). Also see Keith Allen (2016, especially pp. 115–130).

  13. To be clear, and following Cohen (2009, 9), “it is essential that we limit the scope of relationalism to those theories that construe colors in terms of relations to subjects (possibly inter alia)” [our emphasis].

  14. Cohen (2009, 9), for instance, notes that the point of contention between relational and non-relational accounts of color can be expressed in terms paradigm examples of non-relational properties: “the question is whether being red is more like being the sister of b (i.e., a relation that yields relational properties when relevant parameters are filled in) or being cubical (i.e., a non-relational property for which there are no parameters in need of filling).” Our point here is that if the argument from perceptual variation ought to convince us that color is a relational property, then most (if not all) paradigm examples of non-relational properties will be demoted to relational properties.

  15. It will not do, for example, in the context of the Special Theory of relativity (to be discussed below) and from your frame of reference, to maintain that “the object is truly 1 m long because I measured it” when another observer holds that, from her reference frame, the object is of a different length. Thus, it isn’t the case that an appeal to empirical observation and measurement can break the symmetry between color properties and the type of paradigmatic non-relational and objective properties (such as length) that we have been discussing.

  16. As an anonymous reviewer notes, Cohen (2009) has a sophisticated theory of the semantics of color terms that attempts to address this kind of objection.

  17. Not to say that science determines metaphysics. At best, metaphysics is constrained but underdetermined by science. Moreover, what a scientific theory actually tells us about what the world is a highly controversial and complicated matter, quantum mechanics being a case in point. Still, looking to our best scientific theories is essential for the purposes of ascertaining the nature of, say, color properties.

  18. See Hyman (2005) for an interesting discussion of the ontology of colors that is also grounded in Einstein’s special relativity theory and suggests a notion of frames of reference (viz., our system of color concepts) that is relevant for evaluating the relationality/objectivity of colors. Our own discussion, however, emphasizes the observer/frame dependence of color properties (or their appearance) due to the relativistic Doppler effect and gravitational redshift.

  19. You are no doubt familiar with the (non-relativistic) Doppler effect as it manifests in sound, viz., an ambulance siren will sound differently depending on whether the ambulance is driving toward you (shorter sound waves, higher frequency) or away from you (longer sound waves, lower frequency). However, in the context of classical physics in which the classical Doppler effect manifests, there can be a preferred (absolute) reference frame as Newton maintained, so that it follows that the Doppler effect is epistemic in character. In the STR there is no preferred reference frame so that, on a standard interpretation of the theory, the relativistic Doppler effect takes on a metaphysical character.

  20. The relativistic Doppler effect, which can be derived in the context of the special theory of relativity, is different from a similar effect found in the context of the general theory of relativity. Namely, light is redshifted or blueshifted in the presence of gravity depending on whether it is going up or down, respectively, in a gravitational field. The gravitational redshift of light was experimentally confirmed by Pound and Rebka (1959).

  21. How did Einstein discover the STR and its consequences? The story is complex, but Einstein’s key clue was to notice that there is an asymmetry between the ways that classical electromagnetism describes certain states of the world that is not inherent in the observable phenomena—a difference with no difference, so to speak. For further details see, for instance, Norton (2014).

  22. Leibniz, of course, would and did disagree.

  23. As an anonymous reviewer notes, one may worry that our suggested strategy does not generalize well. Humor, for instance, is often taken to be paradigmatic example of a mind-dependent property. However, it seems dubious that scientific theory allows us to settle whether or not this is true, and certainly this doesn't seem like a question that special relativity theory has a bearing on. In reply, we admit that there may be some properties for which little to no ontological insight can be gained by appealing to our best and current scientific theory, let alone relativity theory. Afterall, our suggestion is that insights into, say, which properties are relational may be found by looking to our best scientific theories. However, it doesn’t follow that future science won’t have consequences for such properties. Nor does it follow that arguments from perceptual variation suddenly gain purchase.

  24. See Watkins (2005 and forthcoming(a)) and Kalderon (2007).

  25. Hardin (1992, p. 371) claims that the unique hues (and phenomenal structure more generally) are the “central reason” for rejecting any objectivist theory of color.

  26. See Watkins (2002, 2005), as well as Shoemaker (2007).

  27. We take this to be Burnyeat’s (1979) position, which he attributes to Heraclitus.

  28. We also suspect that once we have a way to identify the determinate colors, those colors that presumably realize the more determinable colors, plausible responses to arguments from perceptual variation concerning determinable colors will be more apparent. Showing that would require another paper, but for hints at how it might go see Watkins (forthcoming(b)), Shoemaker (2007), Kalderon (2007), and Allen (2017, especially chapter 3).

References

  • Aglioti, S., DeSouza, J. F. X., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). Size-contrast illusions deceive the eye but not the hand. Current Biology, 5, 679–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, K. (2017). A Naïve realist theory of colour. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1962). Sense and sensibilia. In G. Warnock (Ed.), Oxford University Press. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanation in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 611–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnyeat, M. (1979). Conflicting appearances. The Proceedings of the British Academy, 65, 69–111.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (2009). The red and the real: An essay on color ontology. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Galileo, G. (1632) Dialogue concerning the two chief world systems. In: S. Drake (trans.), Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967.

  • Gert, J. (2006). A realistic colour realism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84, 565–589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenfieldboyce, N. (2014). “The X’s are the same shade, so what does that say about color?” National Public Radio. https://www.npr.org/sections/health-shots/2014/11/10/361219912/if-the-same-shade-looks-both-yellow-and-gray-whats-color

  • Gregory, R. L., & Heard, P. (1979). Border lockin and the Café Wall illusion. Perception, 8, 365–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C. L. (1988). Color for philosophers. Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C. L. (1992). The virtues of illusion. Philosophical Studies, 68, 371–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C. L. (2003). A spectral reflectance doth not a color make. Journal of Philosophy, 100, 191–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D., & Kalderon, M. E. (2000). Color and the inverted spectrum. In S. Davis (Ed.), Color perception: Philosophical, psychological, artistic and computational perspectives, vancouver studies in cognitive science (pp. 187–214). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, J. (2005). What, if anything, are colours relative to? Philosophy, 80, 475–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, G. (1981). Comparative color vision. Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the colors. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalderon, M. E. (2007). Color pluralism. Philosophical Review, 116, 563–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalderon, M. E. (2008). Metamerism, constancy, and knowing which. Mind, 117, 935–971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalderon, M. E. (2011a). Color illusion. Nous, 45, 751–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalderon, M. E. (2011b). The multiply qualitative. Mind, 120, 239–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Everything must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lazareva, O., Shimizu, T., & Wasserman, E. (2012). How animals see the world: Comparative behavior, biology, and evolution of vision. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1726). Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica. In Mathematical principles of natural philosophy, London, 1687; Cambridge, 1713; London.

  • Ney, A. (2010). Are there fundamental intrinsic properties? In A. Hazlett (Ed.), New waves in metaphysics (pp. 219–239). Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (2014). Einstein’s special theory of relativity and the problems in the electrodynamics of moving bodies that led him to it. In M. Janssen & C. Lehner (Eds.), Cambridge companion to Einstein (pp. 72–102). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brian, P. (1981). The Ionian mission. W.W Norton and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pound, R. V., & Rebka, G. A., Jr. (1959). Gravitational red-shift in nuclear resonance. Physical Review Letters, 3(9), 439–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shams, L., Kamitani, Y., & Shimojo, S. (2002) Visual illusion induced by sound. Cognitive Brain Research, 14(1), 147–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2003). Content, character, and color. Philosophical Issues, 13, 253–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2006). On the way things appear. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 461–480). Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2007). Physical realization. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strother, L., Killebrew, K. W., & Caplovitz, G. P. (2015). The lemon illusion: Seeing curvature where there is none. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2015.00095

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, K. (2017). Curvature blindness illusion. i-Perception. https://doi.org/10.1177/2041669517742178journals.sagepub.com/home/ipe

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (2013). The silences of the senses. In C. Travis (Ed.), Perception: Essays after Frege (pp. 23–58). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, M. forthcoming (a). From blue to the blues: A Study in Objectivity.

  • Watkins, M., forthcoming (b). Color Objectivism Made Simple.

  • Watkins, M. (2002). Rediscovering colors: A study in Pollyanna realism. Dordrecht: Boston.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, M. (2005). Seeing red: The metaphysics of colour without the physics. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 83, 33–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elay Shech.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Watkins, M., Shech, E. Colors, Perceptual Variation, and Science. Erkenn 89, 1157–1181 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00574-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00574-2

Navigation