Skip to main content
Log in

Scientific Mind and Objective World: Thomas Kuhn Between Naturalism and Apriorism

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Correction to this article was published on 08 October 2020

This article has been updated

Abstract

Kuhn’s account of scientific change is characterized by an internal tension between a naturalist vein, which is compatible with the revolutionary perspective on the historical development of science, and an aprioristic or Kantian vein which wants to secure that science is not an irrational enterprise. Kuhn himself never achieved to resolve the tension or even to deal with the terms of the problem. Michael Friedman, quite recently, provided an account which aspires to reconcile the revolutionary and the aprioristic elements of the Kuhnian historiography by placing the latter in the neo-Kantian philosophical framework. In this paper, I suggest that Friedman manages to provide a convincing description of the structuration of scientific knowledge and, further, to present science as a rational enterprise. I argue that despite these virtues Friedman’s account faces a major problem with regard to the context of transcendental idealism which he is not willing to abandon. I also argue that discarding transcendental idealism in the way the philosophical perspective of John McDowell does, we can dispose of the flaws of Friedman’s account while retaining its virtues.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. For instance, in one of first reviews of The Structure we can read: ‘Kuhn is well aware of the relativism implied by his view, and his common sense and feeling for history make him struggle mightily to soften the dismal conclusion’ (Shapere 1964, p. 392). For a more recent assessment of the accusation of relativism see Bird (2012a, §4.5).

  2. He used to refer to his historiographical account as a form of Kantianism ‘with moveable categories’ (Kuhn 2000b: 264) and as a form of ‘Post-Darwinian Kantianism’ (Kuhn 2000a: 104). Furthermore see Kuhn (1993: 331).

  3. See for instance Shapin (2015) and Brad Way (2015) with respect to the first strand and Nersessian (2003) and Andersen (2012) with respect to the second.

  4. In this passage, Lakatos refers to the title of Kuhn’s contribution (‘Logic of Discovery or Psychology of research?’. But he also stresses (Ibid fn 2) that the same conception is already implicit in Structure. See also Popper’s (1970: 55–56) contribution to the volume.

  5. See Kuhn (2000c: 110, 2000e).

  6. Massimi (2015) detects the same tension between the ‘Kantian reading of Kuhn’ and the Quinean-naturalistic vein of his work. However, my argumentation for resolving the tension in question takes an entirely different course than hers.

  7. See also Quine (1981b).

  8. Note that it is not self-evident that naturalism cannot coincide with a priori. Of course, naturalism cannot coincide with some notions of a priori but not all philosophers take theses notions for granted. For a comprehensive discussion of the issue see Warenski (2009).

  9. According to the notorious quote from The Structure, ‘the proponents of competing paradigms practice their trades in different worlds’ (Kuhn 1962/1990: 150).

  10. Disciplinary matrix and lexicon are terms which stand for paradigms in Kuhn’s later work.

  11. Friedman (2010, p. 498; 2011, p. 431) stresses that ‘[u]nlike many philosophical responses to Kuhn […] [his] approach, like Kuhn's, is essentially historical’. In other words, he insists that we should not return to a traditional cumulative approach of scientific change.

  12. For Reichenbach’s explicit revision of the Kantian a priori see Reichenbach (1965), Friedman (2002: 174–175) and Friedman (2001: 30–31). For Carnap’s implicit elaboration of a notion of a dynamical a priori see Carnap (1950/1956), Friedman (2001: 31–33; 2002: 175–176).

  13. It is not the nature or the logical structure of the constitutive principles that makes them immune to the empirical tests; rather it is their structural position in the particular system of knowledge that provides their empirical incontestability. Friedman argues that, in another framework where those same principles have a different (non-constitutive) structural position, they can and do face the ‘tribunal of experience’ (Friedman 2001, pp. 85–92). He also provides examples from the actual history of science (Friedman 2001: 35–39; 2002: 177–180).

  14. They are constitutive because they fulfill the conditions of possibility for the formulation and empirical application of the empirical laws, and relativised because they are subject to revision and change.

  15. ‘The present conception of scientific rationality is consistent with such “anti-realist” conceptions of scientific truth, but it is in no way committed to them. Perhaps the best way to put the point […] is that the present conception of scientific rationality does not involve a parallel conception of scientific truth—either “realist” or “anti-realist”’ (Friedman 2001, p. 68, n. 83).

  16. I have provided such an account in Dimitrakos (2016). For a critical assessment of Friedman’s account see also Korkut (2011), Ferrari (2012), Richardson (2010), Ryckman (2010) and Van Dyck (2009).

  17. In Kant’s original account these forms are space and time. I will say a few more things about this below.

  18. This is Jonathan Lear’s term. See Haddock (2011).

  19. See Sect. 6 below.

  20. ‘If intuition has to conform to the constitution of the objects, then I do not see how we can know anything of them a priori; but if the object (as an object C of the senses) conforms to the constitution of our faculty of intuition, then I can very well represent this possibility to myself’ (Kant 1781/1998, XVII, p. 110).

  21. ‘[A] priori principles cannot be falsified and new ones cannot be better able to meet the tribunal of experience’ (Richardson 2010: 283).

  22. Note that for Allison these forms need not necessarily be space and time. My argument also does not direct against any specific a priori form of sensibility. It directs against the very idea of the a priori forms of sensibility.

  23. One could argue that the forms of intuition could change under the influence of various psychological or sociological factors. However, this would lead straight to a version of social constructivism and thus it is not an option for Friedman.

  24. Since the Kantian absolute conception of a priori has become obsolete by the scientific evolution and since we refer to a sort of relativized but still constitutive a priori, we should admit the plurality of phenomenal worlds. See the ‘Plurality-of-Phenomenal-Worlds Thesis’ in Hoyningen-Huene (1993: 36–42).

  25. It would be more correct to say that this conception of empirical knowledge characterises the traditional pre-Kantian epistemological camps, either of an empiricist or of a traditional rationalist origin. Sellars attacks the empiricist because of his popularity among analytic philosophy of the twentieth century.

  26. For a further discussion of the issue see Halbig (2006, §2.2).

  27. In particular the ‘two-aspect’ view on transcendental idealism as opposed to the ‘two-worlds interpretation’ (Friedman 1996: 441, n. 17). For a complete exposition of the differences see Allison (2004).

  28. ‘Transcendental idealism […] is a doctrine of epistemological modesty, since it denies finite cognisers like ourselves any purchase on the God’s-eye view of things’ (Allison 2004: XVI).

  29. ‘Worldview […] would be the result of the supposed interaction between the two sides of the dualism. A scheme would be, not a worldview, but what is left when content is subtracted from a world view’ (McDowell 2009c: 119).

  30. This limit, as I argued above, comes from the acceptance of the transcendental idealism and the following scheme-content dualism.

  31. This is what McDowell (1996) calls ‘bald naturalism’.

  32. For a recent defence of this kind of naturalism see Turner (2010).

  33. At least in his seminal Epistemology Naturalized (Quine 1969).

  34. Since the Kantian absolute conception of a priori has become obsolete by the scientific evolution and since we refer to a sort of Relativized but still constitutive a priori, we should admit the plurality of phenomenal worlds. See the “Plurality-of-Phenomenal-Worlds Thesis” in Hoyningen-Huene (1993: 36–42).

  35. As Halbig (2006: 224) points out: ‘McDowell interprets his theory of experience in an utterly realistic way: What we take in through experience are facts […]; if we do not go wrong the content of the experience is nothing else but a fact as part of the fabric of reality’.

  36. For this categorization see Psillos (1999: xvii).

  37. This insight is inferred by his claim that his conception of scientific rationality is not committed to any particular realistic or anti-realistic theory of truth.

  38. “Rational reconstruction” conceived in the Lakatosian sense. See Lakatos (1978).

  39. Note that the notion of the expansion of the framework of possible experience includes the actual empirical corroboration of—at least a part of—expanded space. For this reason, we can talk of an empirical relief after the scientific revolution. In other words, the expansion of the empirical space of reasons satisfies the condition of acceptability described by Lakatos: ‘For the sophisticated falsificationist a theory is ‘acceptable’ or ‘scientific’ only if it has corroborated excess empirical content over its predecessor (or rival), that is, only if it leads to the discovery of novel facts. This condition can be analysed into two clauses: that the new theory has excess empirical content (“acceptability1) and that some of this excess content is verified (“acceptability2”)’ (Lakatos 1978: 31–32).

  40. For a further elaboration of this issue see Dimitrakos (2016).

References

  • Allison, H. E. (2004). Kant’s transcendental idealism: An interpretation and defense. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, H. (2012). Scientific concepts and conceptual change. In V. Kindi & Th Arabatzis (Eds.), Kuhn’s the structure of scientific revolutions revisited (pp. 179–204). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2012a). The structure of scientific revolutions and its significance: An essay review of the fiftieth anniversary edition. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63, 859–883.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2012b). Kuhn, naturalism, and the social study of science. In V. Kindi & Th Arabatzis (Eds.), Kuhn’s the structure of scientific revolutions revisited (pp. 205–230). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2014). The historical turn in the philosophy of science. In M. Curdis & S. Psillos (Eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of science (2nd ed., pp. 79–89). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1991). Knowledge and social imagery (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brad Way, K. (2015). Kuhn’s social epistemology and the sociology of science. In W. J. Devlin & A. Bokulich (Eds.), Kuhn’s structure of scientific revolutions-50 years on (Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science) (Vol. 311, pp. 167–184). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950/1956). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. In R. Carnap (Ed.), Meaning and necessity (2nd ed., pp. 205–221). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Davidson, D. (2001). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Subjective, intersubjective, objective (pp. 137–157). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dimitrakos, Th. (2016). Kuhnianism and Neo-Kantianism: On Friedman’s Account of Scientific. Change, 30(4), 361–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrari, M. (2012). Between Cassirer and Kuhn. Some remarks on Friedman’s relativized a priori. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 43(1), 18–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1996). Exorcising the philosophical tradition: Comments on John McDowell’s mind and world. The Philosophical Review, 105(4), 427–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1997). Philosophical naturalism. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 71(2), 7–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1998). Kantian Themes in the contemporary philosophy. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 72, 111–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2001). Dynamics of reason. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2002). Kant, Kuhn and the rationality of science. Philosophy of Science, 69, 171–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2010). A post-Kuhnian approach to the history and philosophy of science. The Monist, 93(4), 497–517.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2011). Extending the dynamics of reason. Erkenntnis (1975-), 75(3), 431–444.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fumerton, R. (1999). A priori philosophy after an a posteriori turn. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 23, 21–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gattei, S. (2008). Thomas Kuhn’s “linguistic turn” and the legacy of logical empiricism: Incommensurability, rationality and the search for truth. Great Britain: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guyer, P. (1987). Kant and the claims of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haddock, A. (2011). Davidson and idealism. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Naturalism and transcendental philosophy (pp. 26–41). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halbig, C. (2006). Varieties of nature in Hegel and McDowell. European Journal of Philosophy, 14(2), 222–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1993). Reconstructing scientific revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn’s philosophy of science (A.T. Levine, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Kant, I. (1781/1998). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Korkut, B. (2011). The real virtue of Friedman’s neo-Kantian philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science, 78(1), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962/1990). The structure of scientific revolutions (3rd ed. revised). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970a). Logic of discovery of psychology of reasearch. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 231–278). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970b). Reflections on my critics. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 1–24). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977a). Second thoughts on paradigms. In T. S. Kuhn (Ed.), The essential tension, selected studies in scientific tradition and change (pp. 293–319). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977b). Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. In T. S. Kuhn (Ed.), The essential tension, selected studies in scientific tradition and change (pp. 320–339). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1993). Afterwords. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes: Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science (pp. 311–342). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (2000a). Possible worlds in history of science. In J. Conant & J. Haugeland (Eds.), The road since structure (pp. 58–89). Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (2000b). The road since structure. In J. Conant & J. Haugeland (Eds.), The road since structure (pp. 90–104). Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (2000c). The trouble with the historical philosophy of science. In J. Conant & J. Haugeland (Eds.), The road since structure (pp. 105–122). Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (2000d). Rationality and theory choice. In J. Conant & J. Haugeland (Eds.), The road since structure (pp. 208–215). Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (2000e). A discussion with Thomas S. Kuhn. In J. Conant & J. Haugeland (Eds.), The road since structure (pp. 253–323). Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. In Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91–196). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). History of Science and its Rational Reconstructions (pp. 102–138). In J. Worrall & G. Currie (Eds.), The methodology of scientific research programmes: Philosophical papers (Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2004). Review essay on Dynamics of reason by Michael Friedman. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68(3), 702–712.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (1998). Kantian humility: Our ignorance of things in themselves. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2003). Kant on wheels. Social Epistemology, 17(2&3), 215–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macarthur, D., & DeCaro, M. (2004). The nature of naturalism. In M. DeCaro & D. Macarthur (Eds.), Naturalism in question (pp. 1–20). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macarthur, D., & DeCaro, M. (2010). Introduction: Science, naturalism and the problem of normativity. In M. DeCaro & D. Macarthur (Eds.), Naturalism and normativity (pp. 1–19). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massimi, M. (2015). Walking the line: Kuhn between realism and relativism. In W. J. Devlin & A. Bokulich (Eds.), Kuhn’s structure of scientific revolutions-50 years on (Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science) (Vol. 311, pp. 135–152). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • McArthur, D. (2005). Normative naturalism and the relativised a priori. Journal for the General Philosophy of Science, 36(2), 331–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998). ‘Two sorts of naturalism mind’, value and reality (pp. 167–197). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2003). Hegel and the myth of the given. In W. Welsch & K. Vieweg (Eds.), Das Interesse des Denkens. Hegel aus heutiger Sicht (pp. 75–88). München: Fink.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2009a). Sellars on perceptual experience. In J. McDowell (Ed.), Having the world in view: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars (pp. 23–43). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2009b). The logical form of an intuition. In J. McDowell (Ed.), Having the world in view: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars (pp. 23–43). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2009c). Hegel’s idealism as radicalization of Kant. In J. McDowell (Ed.), Having the world in view: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars (pp. 69–89). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2009d). Scheme-content dualism and empiricism. In J. McDowell (Ed.), The engaged intellect: Philosophical essays, (pp. 115–133). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuire, J. E. (1992). Scientific change: Perspectives and proposals. In M. Salmon, et al. (Eds.), Introduction to the philosophy of science (pp. 132–178). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian, N. J. (2003). Kuhn, conceptual change, and cognitive science. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Thomas Kuhn (pp. 178–211). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1970). Normal science and its dangers. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 51–58). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2009). Knowing the structure of nature: Essays on realism and explanation. Basingstoke: Palgrave-McMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S., & Christopoulou, D. (2009). The a priori: Between conventions and implicit definitions. In N. Kompa, C. Nimtz, & C. Suhm (Eds.), The a priori and its role in philosophy (pp. 205–220). Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1951/1961). Two dogmas of empiricism. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), From a logical point of view (2nd ed. revised, pp. 20–46). New York: Harper Torchbooks.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Epistemology naturalized. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 69–90). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1981a). Things and their place in theories. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), Theories and things (pp. 1–23). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1981b). Five milestones of empiricism. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), Theories and things (pp. 67–72). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1965). The theory of relativity and a priori knowledge. Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, A. (2010). Ernst Cassirer and Michael Friedman: Kantian or Hegelian dynamics of reason? In M. Domski & M. Dickson (Eds.), Discourse on a new method (pp. 279–294). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryckman, T. (2010). The “relativized a priori”: An appreciation and a critique. In M. Domski & M. Dickson (Eds.), Discourse on a new method (pp. 445–470). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956/1997). Empiricism and philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Shapere, D. (1964). The structure of scientific revolutions. Philosophical Review, 73, 383–394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S. (2015). Kuhn’s structure: A moment in modern naturalism. In W. J. Devlin & A. Bokulich (Eds.), Kuhn’s structure of scientific revolutions-50 years on (Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science) (Vol. 311, pp. 11–21). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J., & Sullivan, P. (2011). Introduction: Transcendental philosophy and naturalism. In J. Smith & P. Sullivan (Eds.), Naturalism and transcendental philosophy (pp. 1–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szalek, P. K. (2007). The notion of conceptualized experience in John McDowell’s mind and world. Forum Philosophicum, 12, 87–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, S. (2010). Explaining the normative. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Dyck, M. (2009). The dynamics of reason and the Kantian project. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 689–700.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warenski, L. (2009). Naturalism, fallibilism, and the a priori. Philosophical Studies, 142(3), 403–426.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to Evgenia Mylonaki for her comments on a draft version of this paper. I would also like to thank the two anonymous referees of this journal for their helpful remarks.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thodoris Dimitrakos.

Additional information

This research is implemented through IKY scholarships programme and co-financed by the European Union (European Social Fund - ESF) and Greek national funds through the action entitled “Reinforcement of Postdoctoral Researchers”, in the framework of the Operational Programme “Human Resources Development Program, Education and Lifelong Learning” of the National Strategic Reference Framework (NSRF) 2014–2020

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dimitrakos, T. Scientific Mind and Objective World: Thomas Kuhn Between Naturalism and Apriorism. Erkenn 85, 225–254 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0025-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0025-5

Navigation