1 Introduction

The Paris Agreement, negotiated by 196 parties at the 2015 United Nations Climate Change Conference, aims to limit global warming to well below 2 °C compared to pre-industrial levels (UN 2015). Although there is thus broad consensus on the international goal of climate policy, a continuation of current policies would result in global warming of about 3 °C above pre-industrial levels (UN 2023).Footnote 1 Consequently, the Paris Agreement with its nationally determined contributions does not constitute an effective international environmental agreement in terms of the international political narrative. On the other hand, some world regions have introduced rather high carbon prices despite facing negative social costs of carbon (see Table 1). Although these carbon prices are still well below the global social cost of carbon (418/tCO2 from Ricke et al. 2018), this behaviour can hardly be explained with perfect selfishness.Footnote 2

Table 1 Largest carbon pricing schemes representing \(22\%\) of global \(\hbox {CO}_2\) emissions

Instead, it may reflect the important effects of altruistic values on environmental behaviour found in the psychological literature (see, e.g., Dietz et al. 2005; Steg 2016; Lades et al. 2021).Footnote 3 In particular, there is evidence that climate policy negotiators have social preferences regarding burden-sharing rules: If climate policy negotiators from rich countries were perfectly selfish, they would support the grandfathering rule, i.e. equal percentage reduction of emissions, and oppose the egalitarian rule, i.e. equal per capita emissions. However, gross domestic product per capita is not positively [negatively] correlated with support for the grandfathering [egalitarian] rule (Lange et al. 2007; Meulemann and Ziegler 2015). Furthermore, climate policy negotiators from industrialized countries state that the egalitarian rule should be the most important burden-sharing rule in international climate agreements (Kesternich et al. 2021). These results suggest that climate policy negotiators are not driven by perfect selfishness.Footnote 4

This paper analyses the formation of climate coalitions with altruistic preferences. In particular, each country values, to some extent, every other country’s welfare when deciding on its coalition membership at the first stage of the game and emissions policy at the second stage of the game. In order to be able to compare our results with the standard literature (Carraro and Siniscalco 1993; Barrett 1994), we apply the canonical model of self-enforcing international environmental agreements with identical countries, concave utility from own emissions and convex costs from global emissions. Without altruistic preferences, the standard (Nash or Stackelberg) game with linear-quadratic emissions benefits and linear marginal emissions damages predicts either small or ineffective climate coalitions.Footnote 5 Beyond the linear-quadratic case, Barrett (2013) and Nkuiya et al. (2015) show that climate thresholds can stabilise the grand coalition, Nkuiya (2020) finds that climate coalitions can be large and effective with isoelastic emissions benefits in the Stackelberg game, and Eckert and Nkuiya (2022) show that convex marginal emissions damages can stabilise large coalitions up to the grand coalition in the Nash game. With general functional forms, the second stage of the Nash game and the Stackelberg game have been analysed in detail by Bayramoglu et al. (2018) and Finus et al. (2021a, 2021b), respectively. Finally, Finus et al. (2023) show that the stable coalition is always weakly larger in the Stackelberg game than in the Nash game.Footnote 6

We distinguish between the coalition countries taking the fringe countries’ emissions as given (Nash game) and taking the reaction of the fringe countries’ emissions into account (Stackelberg game) when choosing their own emissions. In both cases, altruism reduces each fringe country’s emissions and raises global material welfare, i.e. global welfare in the absence of altruistic preferences. Furthermore, we get the typical results that global emissions decrease and each fringe country’s emissions and material welfare increase with the coalition size in the Nash game and above a critical coalition size in the Stackelberg game. By contrast, the effect of altruism on the equilibrium coalition size depends crucially on the game structure.

In the Nash game with linear-quadratic emissions benefits and quadratic emissions damages, altruism weakly reduces the coalition size, and climate coalitions consist of no more than two countries. The direct effect of altruism, namely smaller global emissions and larger global material welfare for a larger coalition size, makes it worthwhile for all other countries if some country joins the coalition. However, the indirect effect of altruism, namely smaller global emissions and larger global material welfare for a given coalition size, makes it less costly for all other countries if some country does not join the coalition. This indirect effect outweighs the direct effect for small coalition sizes and explains the small climate coalition in equilibrium.

In the Stackelberg game with linear-quadratic emissions benefits and quadratic emissions damages, altruism weakly raises the coalition size, and climate coalitions can consist of up to six countries. In this case, the coalition countries take advantage of the fringe countries’ altruism by becoming less ambitious in the fight against climate change, expecting the fringe countries to react by reducing their emissions more than they would without altruism. However, the coalition countries are not much more ambitious in the Stackelberg equilibrium than in the business-as-usual scenario without coalition formation.

These results suggest that altruism cannot stabilise large and effective climate coalitions. However, altruism narrows the gap between the individually optimal emissions and the socially optimal emissions, so altruism increases global welfare. Thus, altruism affecting the membership decision and the policy decision appears to be more of a substitute than a complement for large climate coalitions.

The economic literature has developed and tested several theories for imperfect selfishness. In the case of altruistic preferences (Becker 1974), one can distinguish between pure altruism, i.e. utility from others’ utility values (Becker 1981), paternalistic altruism, i.e. utility from others’ consumption bundles (Pollak 1988), and impure altruism, i.e. utility or warm glow from giving others (Andreoni 1990). Alger and Weibull (2010) show that pure altruism used in this paper is evolutionary stable, and Andreoni et al. (2010) summarize the significant evidence for altruism in economic experiments. Other theories comprise reciprocal fairness (Rabin 1993), inequality aversion (Fehr and Schmidt 1999; Bolton and Ockenfels 2000) and Kantian behaviour (Alger and Weibull 2013; Roemer 2015).

These theories have also been applied in the literature on self-enforcing international environmental agreements. Buchholz et al. (2018) and Nyborg (2018) analyse the effects of reciprocal fairness when countries decide on their membership in the coalition and on their emissions. They find that reciprocal fairness can stabilise the grand coalition, but it can also stabilise an interior coalition that is either weakly larger (Nyborg 2018) or even weakly smaller (Buchholz et al. 2018) than the interior coalition without reciprocal fairness. Lange and Vogt (2003) incorporate inequality aversion à la Bolton and Ockenfels (2000) into the canonical model of self-enforcing international environmental agreements and find that sufficiently large inequality aversion can stabilise the grand coalition. By contrast, Vogt (2016) applies inequality aversion à la Fehr and Schmidt (1999) and finds no stable coalition without transfers in his numerical model with heterogeneous countries. Recently, Eichner and Pethig (2022) and Ulph and Ulph (2023) analysed the effects of Kantian or moral behaviour when countries decide on their membership in the coalition and on their emissions. They find that membership moralism expands the climate coalition, and emissions moralism can expand the climate coalition only in the presence of membership moralism.

Closest to our paper is van der Pol et al. (2012), who analyse the effects of altruism affecting the membership decision but not the policy decision. They find that this kind of partial altruism expands the climate coalition. We extend their model into different directions. First, we consider altruism on both stages of the game. Second, we analyse not only the Nash game but also the Stackelberg game. Third, while they solve their model numerically with heterogeneous countries, we solve our model analytically with homogeneous countries. Forth, we replicate their results analytically to discuss the differences from our results.Footnote 7

Finally, we perform two model extensions. First, we analyse the effects of community altruism, that is, we distinguish between in-group altruism and out-group altruism. In this case, altruism can stabilise large coalitions up to the grand coalition. Second, we analyse the effects of altruism with linear climate damages and asymmetric countries. In this case, altruism can stabilise small coalitions but destabilises large coalitions.

The remainder of the paper is organized as follows: Sect. 2 introduces the model, and characterises the social optimum and the business-as-usual scenario. Section 3 analyses the effects of altruism on the Nash game of coalition formation. This section also includes a comparison with the model of van der Pol et al. (2012). Section 4 analyses the effects of altruism on the Stackelberg game of coalition formation with the coalition countries as Stackelberg leaders and the fringe countries as Stackelberg followers. Section 5 discusses which realms of decision making might be influenced by social preferences. Section 6 performs our two model extensions. Section 7 concludes.

2 Model

Consider a model with \(n\ge 3\) identical countries.Footnote 8 Each county \(i\in N\) derives consumption benefits \(B(e_i)\) from its emissions \(e_i\), where \(B(0)\ge 0\), \(B'>0\) and \(B''<0\), and faces climate damages \(D(e)\) from global emissions \(e:=\sum _{i\in N}e_i\), where \(D(0)=0\), \(D'>0\) and \(D''>0\). Then, each country’s material welfare function is \(W_i=B(e_i)-D(e)\). Furthermore, each country is altruistic such that it values its own material welfare by 1 and every other country’s material welfare by \(\alpha \in [0,1]\).Footnote 9 Thus, the altruism parameter \(\alpha =0\) implies perfectly selfish countries, while \(\alpha =1\) implies perfectly altruistic countries. Then, each country’s moral welfare is

$$\begin{aligned} V_i=W_i+\alpha \sum _{j\in N\backslash i} W_j=(1-\alpha )W_i+\alpha W, \end{aligned}$$
(1)

where \(W:=\sum _{i\in N}W_i\) is global material welfare, and the global moral welfare is

$$\begin{aligned} V:=\sum _{i\in N}V_i=\sum _{i\in N}\left[ W_i+\alpha \sum _{j\in N\backslash i} W_j\right] =[1+\alpha (n-1)]W. \end{aligned}$$
(2)

Consequently, the socially optimal emissions (SO) are independent of the altruism parameter \(\alpha\), while the individually optimal emissions, i.e. the business-as-usual emissions (BAU), are not (Daube 2019, Results 4 and 5). In particular, the socially optimal values and the individually optimal values coincide for \(\alpha =1\). In Appendix A.1, we prove that global emissions decrease and global material welfare increases with the altruism parameter in the individually optimal solution. Consequently, the relative global emissions \(e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}/e^{{\textrm{SO}}}\) decrease and the relative global material and moral welfare \(W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}/W^{{\textrm{SO}}}=V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}/V^{{\textrm{SO}}}\) increase with the altruism parameter.

In the further course of the paper we analyse the two-stage game of self-enforcing environmental agreements. At the first stage of the game, countries decide on their membership in the coalition. Thereby, internal [external] stability implies that no country will leave [join] the coalition if this reduces its moral welfare (D’Aspremont et al. 1983). At the second stage of the game, there is a coalition of m countries, and countries decide on their emissions. Thereby, each fringe country maximizes its moral welfare (1), and each coalition country \(i\in M\) maximizes the sum of the coalition countries’ moral welfare

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i\in M}V_i&=\sum _{i\in M}\left[ W_i+\alpha \sum _{j\in N\backslash i} W_j\right] =(1-\alpha )\sum _{i\in M}W_i+\alpha m W. \end{aligned}$$
(3)

Comparing (1) and (3), each fringe country’s policy weights its own material welfare by \(1-\alpha\) and global material welfare by \(\alpha\), while each coalition country’s policy weights the coalition’s material welfare by \(1-\alpha\) and global material welfare by \(\alpha m\). In the following we distinguish between two game concepts. In Sect. 3, we analyse the Nash game, and in Sect. 4, we analyse the Stackelberg game with the coalition countries as Stackelberg leaders and the fringe countries as Stackelberg followers. The respective game is then solved by backward induction.

3 Nash Game

At the second stage of the Nash game, each fringe country \(i=f\) maximizes its moral welfare (1) over its emissions \(e_f\), taking the other countries’ emissions as given, which yields

$$\begin{aligned} B'(e_f)=[1+\alpha (n-1)]D'(e)\le nD'(e). \end{aligned}$$
(4)

Each fringe country equates marginal emissions benefits to its own marginal emissions damages \(D'(e)\), plus all other countries’ marginal emissions damages weighted by the altruism parameter \(\alpha (n-1)D'(e)\).

Furthermore, each coalition country \(i=c\) maximizes the sum of the coalition countries’ moral welfare (3) over its emissions \(e_c\), taking the other countries’ emissions as given, which yieldsFootnote 10

$$\begin{aligned} B'(e_c)&=\frac{1+\alpha (n-1)}{1+\alpha (m-1)}mD'(e)\le nD'(e). \end{aligned}$$
(5)

For \(\alpha =0\), each coalition country equates marginal emissions benefits to the coalition countries’ marginal emissions damages \(mD'(e)\). For \(\alpha >0\), altruism implies that each coalition country accounts for all other countries’ marginal emissions damages via \(1+\alpha (n-1)\), but it also implies that all other coalition countries account for each coalition country’s marginal emissions benefits via \(1+\alpha (m-1)\). Note that \(B'(e_f)=B'(e_c)=nD'(e)\) for \(\alpha =1\), so the Nash equilibrium and the social optimum then coincide. In the following we focus on \(\alpha \in [0,1)\).

Differentiating (4) and (5) yields the slopes of the aggregate reaction functions

$$\begin{aligned} R'_f:=\frac{{\textrm{d}}(n-m)e_f}{{\textrm{d}}me_c}&=-\frac{(n-m)[1+\alpha (n-1)]D''(e)}{(n-m)[1+\alpha (n-1)]D''(e)-B''(e_f)}\in (-1,0), \end{aligned}$$
(6)
$$\begin{aligned} R'_c:=\frac{{\textrm{d}}me_c}{{\textrm{d}}(n-m)e_f}&=-\frac{m^2[1+\alpha (n-1)]D''(e)}{m^2[1+\alpha (n-1)]D''(e)-[1+\alpha (m-1)]B''(e_c)}\in (-1,0). \end{aligned}$$
(7)

Consequently, emissions are strategic substitutes, and the slopes of the aggregate reaction functions ceteris paribus increase in absolute terms with the altruism parameter. Intuitively, altruism implies that countries react more sensitive to other countries’ emissions changes. Furthermore, we infer

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{B'(e_c)}{B'(e_f)}&=\frac{m}{1+\alpha (m-1)}\in (1,m]. \end{aligned}$$
(8)

Consequently, each fringe country’s emissions are greater than each coalition country’s emissions. In Appendix A.2.1, we proveFootnote 11

Proposition 1

(Comparison of Nash equilibrium and BAU)

  • \(e_c<e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i<e_f\) and \(e<e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\),

  • \(V_f>V_c\),

  • \(W_f>W_c,W_i^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\).

(8) implies that the coalition countries are ceteris paribus more ambitious in the fight against climate change than at BAU. This results in smaller coalition country’s emissions and global emissions, which raises the free-rider incentives and leads to greater fringe country’s emissions. Each fringe country’s emissions being greater than each coalition country’s emissions implies \(V_f>V_c\) and \(W_f>W_c\). Finally, global emissions being smaller and each fringe country’s emissions being greater than at BAU implies \(W_f>W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) and, thus, \(V_f>V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) if \(W_c\ge W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) or if \(\alpha\) is sufficiently small.

To prepare the analysis of the first stage of the Nash game, we prove in Appendix A.2.2Footnote 12

Lemma 1

(Effects of coalition size and altruism on emissions and welfare)

  • \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e_f}{{\textrm{d}}m}>0\), \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e}{{\textrm{d}}m}<0\) and \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}W_f}{{\textrm{d}}m}>0\),

  • \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e_f}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }<0\), \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }<0\) and \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}W}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }>0\).

From the first bullet of the lemma, we get the typical results that each fringe country’s emissions increase but global emissions decrease with the coalition size, so free-rider incentives tend to increase as the coalition gets larger. The resulting higher consumption benefits and lower climate damages imply that each fringe country’s material welfare increases with the coalition size and, thus, that \(V_f\) increases with the coalition size if \(W_c\) increases with the coalition size or if \(\alpha\) is sufficiently small.

The second bullet of the lemma reveals that each fringe country’s emissions and global emissions decrease with the altruism parameter and that global material welfare increases with the altruism parameter. Consequently, the relative global emissions \(e/e^{{\textrm{SO}}}\) decrease and the relative global material and moral welfare \(W/W^{{\textrm{SO}}}=V/V^{{\textrm{SO}}}\) increase with the altruism parameter. Finally, we prove in Appendix A.2.2 that the slope of the fringe countries’ aggregate reaction function increases in absolute terms with the altruism parameter for \(D'''\le 0\) and \(B'''=0\). This slope corresponds to the leakage rate to the fringe countries \(|R'_f|\), and the higher this leakage rate, the greater ceteris paribus the free-rider incentives in the Nash game (Carraro and Siniscalco 1993).

Now we turn to the first stage of the Nash game. First note that \(V_f(m)>V_c(m)\) from Proposition 1 implies that if a coalition is externally unstable, i.e. \(V_c(m+1)\ge V_f(m)\), then the corresponding expansion of the coalition is accompanied by a Pareto improvement, i.e. \(V_f(m+1)>V_c(m+1)\ge V_f(m)>V_c(m)\). For the detailed stability analysis, we use the following specification with linear-quadratic emissions benefits and quadratic emissions damages

$$\begin{aligned} B(e_i)=ae_i-\frac{b}{2}e_i^2,\quad D(e)=\frac{d}{2}e^2,\quad \text {with }a,b,d>0. \end{aligned}$$
(9)

We constrain the parameter space to ensure non-negative emissions for all \(m\in [2,n]\), which gives an upper bound for d. In particular, we formulate the following

Assumption 1

\(d\le {\bar{d}}:=\dfrac{4b}{(n-1)^2}\).

This assumption is necessary and sufficient for non-negative emissions for all \(m\in [2,n]\) with \(\alpha =0\).Footnote 13 In Appendix A.2.3, we then prove

Proposition 2

(Stability of coalitions with policy altruism) Consider the specification (9) and suppose altruism affects the membership decision and the policy decision.

  • Either the coalition \(m=2\) is stable or no coalition is stable.

  • The coalition \(m\hspace{-0.11em}=\hspace{-0.11em}2\) is [not] stable for \(\alpha \hspace{-0.11em}=\hspace{-0.11em}0\), \(n\hspace{-0.11em}\ge \hspace{-0.11em}12\) and \(d\hspace{-0.11em}\le \hspace{-0.11em}{\bar{d}}\) \([\alpha \hspace{-0.11em}=\hspace{-0.11em}0\), \(n\hspace{-0.11em}<\hspace{-0.11em}12\) and \(d\hspace{-0.11em}=\hspace{-0.11em}{\bar{d}}]\).

  • The coalition size weakly decreases with \(\alpha\).

From the first bullet of the proposition, we get the pessimistic result that at best a coalition of two countries is stable. The result from the second bullet of the proposition that \(m=2\) is stable for \(\alpha =0\) when there is a sufficiently large number of countries may seem counterintuitive. In fact, there are two countervailing effects of n on the internal stability condition. On the one hand, the condition for \(m=2\) to be stable becomes stricter as n increases for given parameter values abd and \(\alpha\), since the number of fringe countries increases with n, which raises marginal climate damages, reduces each coalition country’s emissions and, thus, the benefits of remaining in the coalition. On the other hand, the condition for \(m=2\) to be stable also becomes stricter as d increases, since each coalition [fringe] country’s emissions decrease [increase] with the damage parameter, which reflects Barrett’s (1994) paradox of cooperation. These considerations imply that the upper bound for d to ensure non-negative emissions decreases with n, i.e. \(\partial {\bar{d}}/\partial n<0\), which relaxes the internal stability condition. This indirect effect of n on the internal stability condition outweighs the direct effect for \(m=2\) and \(\alpha =0\), which explains why the coalition \(m=2\) is stable for \(\alpha =0\) and \(n\ge 12\). By contrast, the coalition \(m=2\) is not stable for \(\alpha =0\) and \(n<12\) when d is sufficiently large, i.e. when \(d={\bar{d}}\).Footnote 14

Fig. 1
figure 1

Each coalition country’s minimal emissions (left-hand side figure) and the internal stability condition for \(m=2\) (right-hand side figure) dependent on \(\alpha\) with \(n=100,a=100,b=1\) and \(d=1/10{,}000\)

We use a numerical example to demonstrate that there are economies in which \(m=2\) is not stable for \(\alpha >0\) and \(n\ge 12\). Figure 1 depicts each coalition country’s minimal emissionsFootnote 15 (left-hand side figure) and the internal stability condition for \(m=2\) (right-hand side figure) dependent on \(\alpha\). In the numerical example, each coalition country’s emissions are positive for all \(m\in [2,n]\). Furthermore, \(m=2\) becomes unstable for \(\alpha \ge 0.334\). Thus, there are economies in which \(m=2\) is not stable for \(\alpha >0\) and \(n\ge 12\).

The third bullet of Proposition 2 and Fig. 1 show that altruism does not stabilise larger coalitions, but even destabilises small coalitions. This is in stark contrast to the numerical analysis of van der Pol et al. (2012), who find that the coalition size increases with the altruism parameter and that the grand coalition becomes stable for \(\alpha \ge 0.401\) (without community altruism and transfers). The major difference between their model and our model is that we assume altruistic preferences at both stages of the game, while they assume altruistic preferences only at the first stage of the game. At the second stage of the game, they assume that each fringe country maximizes its material welfare, while each coalition country maximizes the sum of the coalition countries’ material welfare.Footnote 16 This does not alter the qualitative results at the second stage of the game, i.e. Proposition 1 and the first bullet of Lemma 1 also hold for \(\alpha =0\). However, it alters the qualitative effects of altruism on the internal stability condition. In both models, this internal stability condition reads

$$\begin{aligned} V_c(m)-V_f(m-1)&=(1-\alpha )W_c(m)+\alpha W(m)\nonumber \\&\quad -\left[ (1-\alpha )W_f(m-1)+\alpha W(m-1)\right] \ge 0. \end{aligned}$$
(10)

In van der Pol et al. (2012), where the policy is independent of \(\alpha\), altruism stabilises coalitions if and only if

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \left[ V_c(m)-V_f(m-1)\right] }{\partial \alpha }&=\left[ (m-1)W_c(m)+(n-m)W_f(m)\right] \nonumber \\&\quad -\left[ (m-1)W_c(m-1)+(n-m)W_f(m-1)\right] >0. \end{aligned}$$
(11)

This direct effect of altruism is positive if and only if the total material welfare of the other countries decreases when a country leaves the coalition. Then, altruism can induce a country to stay in the coalition even though its own material welfare would increase if it left the coalition. In Appendix A.2.4, we prove that the direct effect is positive for \(m=2\) (and for \(m\in [2,n]\) with specification (9)), regardless of whether or not altruistic preferences are assumed at the second stage of the game. However, the magnitude of the direct effect differs between the models. Furthermore, in our model, where the policy depends on \(\alpha\), altruism stabilises coalitions if and only if

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{{\textrm{d}}\left[ V_c(m)-V_f(m-1)\right] }{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }=\frac{\partial \left[ V_c(m)-V_f(m-1)\right] }{\partial \alpha }\nonumber \\&\quad +(1-\alpha )\frac{{\textrm{d}}W_c(m)}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }+\alpha \frac{{\textrm{d}}W(m)}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }-\left[ (1-\alpha )\frac{{\textrm{d}}W_f(m-1)}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }+\alpha \frac{{\textrm{d}}W(m-1)}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }\right] >0.\hspace{-2.5mm} \end{aligned}$$
(12)

The second line of (12) represents the indirect effect of altruism. It is positive if and only if the policy effect of altruism on a country’s moral welfare is greater inside than outside the coalition. In Appendix A.2.4, we prove that the policy effect inside the coalition is positive, i.e. \((1-\alpha )\frac{{\textrm{d}}W_c(m)}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }+\alpha \frac{{\textrm{d}}W(m)}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }>0\), but that the policy effect outside the coalition is also positive for \(m=2\) (and for \(m\in [2,n-2]\) with specification (9)), i.e. \((1-\alpha )\frac{{\textrm{d}}W_f(m-1)}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }+\alpha \frac{{\textrm{d}}W(m-1)}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }>0\). Proposition 2 reveals that the latter effect is so strong that altruism raises the free-rider incentives. In other words, the policy effect of altruism is more important for small coalitions than for large coalitions, and so important that the negative indirect effect of altruism outweighs the positive direct effect.

In order to check whether the different results of van der Pol et al. (2012) indeed stem from the different assumption concerning altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game, and not from some other minor differences between the models, we analyse the first stage of the game without altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game. In Appendix A.2.5, we then prove

Proposition 3

(Stability of coalitions without policy altruism) Consider specification (9) and suppose altruism affects the membership decision but not the policy decision.

  • Either some unique coalition is stable or no coalition is stable.

  • The coalition \(m\hspace{-0.11em}=\hspace{-0.11em}2\) is [not] stable for \(\alpha \hspace{-0.11em}=\hspace{-0.11em}0\), \(n\hspace{-0.11em}\ge \hspace{-0.11em}12\) and \(d\hspace{-0.11em}\le \hspace{-0.11em}{\bar{d}}\) \([\alpha \hspace{-0.11em}=\hspace{-0.11em}0\), \(n\hspace{-0.11em}<\hspace{-0.11em}12\) and \(d\hspace{-0.11em}=\hspace{-0.11em}{\bar{d}}]\).

  • The coalition size weakly increases with \(\alpha\).

  • The grand coalition is [not] stable for \(\alpha \ge 4/7\) and \(d\le {\bar{d}}\) \([\alpha \le 3/7\) and \(n\ge 12]\).

The first bullet of the proposition reveals that there is at most one stable coalition size. The second bullet of Proposition 3 mirrors the second bullet of Proposition 2, since the models with and without altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game coincide for \(\alpha =0\). The rest of Proposition 3 confirms the numerical result of van der Pol et al. (2012) that considering altruism only at the first stage of the game stabilises coalitions. In particular, the grand coalition becomes stable when the altruism parameter is greater than a critical value, which lies between 3/7 and 4/7 for \(n\ge 12\) and \(d\le {\bar{d}}\).

Fig. 2
figure 2

Global emissions (left-hand side figure) and global material welfare (right-hand side figure) with (solid curves) and without (dashed curves) altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game dependent on \(\alpha\) with \(n=100,a=100,b=1\) and \(d=1/10{,}000\)

Furthermore, in Appendix A.2.5 we prove that global material and moral welfare increase with the coalition size without altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game. While altruism affecting the membership decision only is beneficial for global welfare and for the climate (\(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e}{{\textrm{d}}m}<0\) from Lemma 1) because it expands the climate coalition, altruism affecting the membership decision and the policy decision is beneficial for global welfare and for the climate (\(\frac{{\textrm{d}}W}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }>0\) and \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }<0\) from Lemma 1) because it tightens the climate policy. If the same coalition is stable in both models, e.g. for \(\alpha \rightarrow 0\) such that \(m=2\), then global welfare is larger and global emissions are smaller with than without altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game. By contrast, if the grand coalition is stable without altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game, e.g. for \(\alpha \ge 4/7\), then global welfare is larger and global emissions are smaller without than with altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game. Figure 2 depicts these relationships for a numerical example.Footnote 17 With [without] altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game, \(m=2\) becomes unstable for \(\alpha >0.334\) [\(m=n\) becomes stable for \(\alpha >0.5\)]. Global emissions are smaller and global material welfare is larger with than without altruistic preferences at the second stage of the game if and only if \(\alpha <0.089\) and \(\alpha <0.135\), respectively. Then, the tighter climate policy outweighs the larger climate coalition, which then comprises no more than 30 and 40 out of 100 countries, respectively. Finally, the figure shows that the welfare difference is relatively small (\(<27{,}000\)) compared to the welfare difference between social optimum (250,000) and BAU without altruistic preferences (9800).

4 Stackelberg Game

At the second stage of the Stackelberg game, each fringe country \(i=f\) maximizes its moral welfare (1) over its emissions \(e_f\), taking the other countries’ emissions as given, which yields (4).

Furthermore, each coalition country \(i=c\) maximizes the sum of the coalition countries’ moral welfare (3) over its emissions \(e_c\), taking the other coalition countries’ emissions as given, but taking (4) into account, which yieldsFootnote 18

$$\begin{aligned} B'(e_c)=\frac{1+\alpha (n-1)}{1+\alpha (m-1)}mD'(e)\left[ 1+(1-\alpha )R'_f\right] \le nD'(e), \end{aligned}$$
(13)

where \(R'_f\in (-1,0)\) from (6). For \(\alpha =0\), each coalition country equates marginal emissions benefits to the coalition countries’ marginal emissions damages \(mD'(e)\), corrected for the leakage rate to the fringe countries \(\big |R'_f\big |\). For \(\alpha >0\), altruism implies that each coalition country accounts for all other countries’ marginal emissions damages via \(1+\alpha (n-1)\), but it also implies that all other coalition countries account for each coalition country’s marginal emissions benefits via \(1+\alpha (m-1)\). Furthermore, altruism implies that each coalition country accounts for all fringe countries’ marginal emissions benefits, which reduces the influence of the leakage rate to the fringe countries via \(1-\alpha\). Finally, altruism of the fringe countries implies that these countries react more sensitive to other countries’ emissions changes, such that the altruism parameter ceteris paribus increases the leakage rate to the fringe countries. Note that \(B'(e_f)=B'(e_c)=nD'(e)\) for \(\alpha =1\), so the Stackelberg equilibrium and the social optimum then coincide. In the following we focus on \(\alpha \in [0,1)\).

From (4) and (13), we infer

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{B'(e_c)}{B'(e_f)}=\frac{m}{1+\alpha (m-1)}\left[ 1+(1-\alpha )R'_f\right] =:\tilde{\theta }\in (0,m). \end{aligned}$$
(14)

Consequently, each fringe country’s emissions are greater [smaller] than each coalition country’s emissions for \(\tilde{\theta }>[<]1\). Furthermore, \(\tilde{\theta }=1\) implies that the Stackelberg equilibrium and the BAU coincide. In Appendix A.3.2, we proveFootnote 19

Proposition 4

(Comparison of Stackelberg equilibrium and BAU)

  • \(e_c\gtreqless e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\gtreqless e_f\) and \(e\gtreqless e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for \(\tilde{\theta }\lesseqgtr 1\),

  • \(V_c>V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i>V_f\) and \(V<V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for \(\tilde{\theta }<1\), \(V_c=V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i=V_f\) and \(V=V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for \(\tilde{\theta }=1\), \(V_f>V_c>V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) and \(V>V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for \(\tilde{\theta }>1\),

  • \(W_c>W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i>W_f\) and \(W<W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for \(\tilde{\theta }<1\), \(W_c=W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i=W_f\) and \(W=W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for \(\tilde{\theta }=1\), \(W_f>W_c,W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\)    and \(W>W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for \(\tilde{\theta }>1\).

\(\tilde{\theta }>[<]1\) implies that the coalition countries are ceteris paribus more [less] ambitious in the fight against climate change than at BAU. This results in smaller [greater] coalition country’s emissions and global emissions, which raises [reduces] the free-rider incentives and leads to greater [smaller] fringe country’s emissions. The coalition could always choose \(\tilde{\theta }=1\), such that \(\tilde{\theta }\ne 1\) implies \(V_c>V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\). For \(\tilde{\theta }>[<]1\) global emissions being smaller [greater] and each fringe country’s emissions being greater [smaller] than at BAU implies \(V_f\gtreqless V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\Longleftrightarrow W_f\gtreqless W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\Longleftrightarrow \tilde{\theta }\gtreqless 1\). Furthermore, for \(\tilde{\theta }>[<]1\) global emissions being smaller [greater] than at BAU implies \(V\gtreqless V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\Longleftrightarrow W\gtreqless W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\Longleftrightarrow \tilde{\theta }\gtreqless 1\). Finally, for \(\tilde{\theta }>[<]1\) each fringe country’s emissions being greater [smaller] than each coalition country’s emissions implies \(V_f\gtreqless V_c\Longleftrightarrow W_f\gtreqless W_c\Longleftrightarrow\) \(\tilde{\theta }\gtreqless 1\).

The partial derivative of \(\tilde{\theta }\) with respect to m is positive, so the coalition countries tend to become more ambitious as the coalition gets larger. Then, the leakage rate to the fringe countries ceteris paribus becomes smaller, which tends to increase \(\tilde{\theta }\), see (6). Furthermore, the coalition countries’ marginal emissions damages then become greater, which outweighs the greater coalition countries’ marginal emissions benefits and increases \(\tilde{\theta }\), see (14). In Appendix A.3.3, we proveFootnote 20

Proposition 5

(Relation between coalition size and coalition’s ambition) Suppose \(B'''\ge 0\) and \(D'''\le 0\). Then, \(m\lesseqgtr {\tilde{m}}\Longleftrightarrow \tilde{\theta }\lesseqgtr 1\), where

$$\begin{aligned} {\tilde{m}}:=\frac{n[1+\alpha (n-1)]D''(e^{{\textrm{BAU}}})-B''(e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i)}{[1+\alpha (n-1)]D''(e^{{\textrm{BAU}}})-B''(e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i)}\in (1,n) \end{aligned}$$
(15)

and where \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}{\tilde{m}}}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }>0\) for \(B'''=0\) (sufficient).

Thus, the coalition countries are less [more] ambitious than the fringe countries in small [large] coalitions, in which the leakage effect outweighs [is outweighed by] the marginal emissions damage effect. The partial derivative of \({\tilde{m}}\) with respect to \(\alpha\) is positive, so the respective threshold coalition \({\tilde{m}}\) tends to get larger as countries become more altruistic. In other words, the coalition countries tend to become less ambitious in the fight against climate change compared to the fringe countries. On the one hand, the altruism parameter ceteris paribus increases the importance of all other coalition countries’ marginal emissions benefits for the optimal policy, and it increases the leakage rate to the fringe countries. On the other hand, it ceteris paribus increases the importance of all fringe countries’ marginal emissions benefits for the optimal policy. Proposition 5 reveals that the former effect outweighs the latter with linear-quadratic consumption benefits.

Since \(m\ge {\tilde{m}}\) will turn out to be the relevant coalition size and to prepare the analysis of the first stage of the Stackelberg game, we prove in Appendix A.3.4Footnote 21

Lemma 2

(Effects of coalition size and altruism on emissions and welfare for \(m\ge {\tilde{m}}\)) Suppose \(B'''\ge 0\) and \(D'''\le 0\).

  • \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e_f}{{\textrm{d}}m}>0\), \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e}{{\textrm{d}}m}<0\) and \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}V_c}{{\textrm{d}}m},\frac{{\textrm{d}}V_f}{{\textrm{d}}m},\frac{{\textrm{d}}W_f}{{\textrm{d}}m}>0\) and \(V(m)>V(m-1),W(m)>W(m-1)\),

  • \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e_f}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }<0\) and \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}W}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }>0\).

From the first bullet of the lemma, we get the typical results that each fringe country’s emissions increase but global emissions decrease with the coalition size, so free-rider incentives tend to increase as the coalition gets larger as in the Nash game. Contrary to the Nash game, the resulting lower climate damages ensure that not only each fringe country’s moral welfare but also each coalition country’s moral welfare increases with the coalition size. Furthermore, each fringe country’s material welfare increases with the coalition size because its consumption benefits increase and the climate damages decrease with the coalition size. Finally, Finus et al. (2021a, p. 18) prove that any Stackelberg game is superadditive, i.e. \(mV_c(m)\ge (m-1)V_c(m-1)+V_f(m-1)\), because \(e_c(m)\) maximizes the sum of m countries’ moral welfare, taking \(e_f(e_c(m))\) into account. Since each fringe country’s moral welfare increases with the coalition size, superadditivity implies that global material and moral welfare also increase with the coalition size.Footnote 22

The second bullet of the lemma reveals that each fringe country’s emissions decrease with the altruism parameter and that global material welfare increases with the altruism parameter as in the Nash game. Consequently, the relative global material and moral welfare \(W/W^{{\textrm{SO}}}=V/V^{{\textrm{SO}}}\) increase with the altruism parameter. Contrary to the Nash game, global emissions need not decrease with the altruism parameter. Finally, we prove in Appendix A.3.4 that the slope of the fringe countries’ aggregate reaction function and, thus, the leakage rate to the fringe countries \(|R'_f|\) increases in absolute terms with the altruism parameter for \(D'''\le 0\) and \(B'''=0\) as in the Nash game. The higher this leakage rate, the smaller ceteris paribus the coalition’s ambition and the greater ceteris paribus the coalition’s strategic advantage over the fringe in the Stackelberg game (Finus et al. 2021b).Footnote 23

Now we turn to the first stage of the Stackelberg game. First note that Proposition 4 implies that all coalitions with \(\tilde{\theta }\le 1\) are externally unstable because joining this coalition then increases the respective country’s moral welfare from \(V_f\le V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) to \(V_c>V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\). Consequently, global emissions are smaller and each country’s moral welfare is greater at the stable Stackelberg equilibrium than at BAU, and each fringe country’s welfare is greater than each coalition country’s welfare. Together with Proposition 5, this givesFootnote 24,Footnote 25

Lemma 3

(Instability of small coalitions) Suppose \(B'''\ge 0\) and \(D'''\le 0\). Then, all coalitions \(m\le {\tilde{m}}\) are externally unstable, and the coalition \(m=\left\lfloor {\tilde{m}}+1\right\rfloor \ge 2\) is internally stable.

The coalition \(m=\left\lfloor {\tilde{m}}+1\right\rfloor \ge 2\) is internally stable because leaving the coalition decreases the respective country’s moral welfare from \(V_c>V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) to \(V_f\le V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\). The lemma indicates that the coalition size increases with the threshold coalition \({\tilde{m}}\), which in turn tends to increase with the altruism parameter from Proposition 5. Via this mechanism, altruism could stabilise larger coalitions.

For the detailed stability analysis, we use specification (9). We constrain the parameter space to ensure non-negative emissions for all \(m\in [2,n]\), which gives an upper bound for d similar to the Nash game. In particular, we formulate the following

Assumption 2

\(d\le \bar{{\tilde{d}}}:=\dfrac{4b}{n(n-4)}\).

This assumption is necessary and sufficient for non-negative emissions for all \(m\in [2,n]\) with \(\alpha =0\).Footnote 26 In Appendix A.3.5, we then proveFootnote 27

Proposition 6 (Stability of coalitions)

Consider specification (9) with \(n\ge 7\) and \(d\le \bar{{\tilde{d}}}\).

  • Some unique coalition \(m\in ({\tilde{m}},{\tilde{m}}+2)\) is stable.

  • Some unique coalition \(m\in \{2,3\}\) is stable for \(\alpha =0\).

  • The coalition size weakly increases with \(\alpha\).

  • Some unique coalition \(m\in \{2,3,4,5,6\}\) is stable for \(\alpha >0\).

Contrary to the Nash game, Proposition 6 reveals that altruism stabilises larger coalitions. However, the coalition never comprises more than six countries. More importantly, the coalition is always smaller than \(m={\tilde{m}}+2\). Since the Stackelberg equilibrium and BAU coincide for \(m={\tilde{m}}\), the emissions-reducing and welfare-enhancing effects of the coalition size from Lemma 2 are negligible. In fact, the small coalitions stem from constraining the parameter space to ensure non-negative emissions for \(m\in [2,n]\), which gives an upper bound for d/b and, thus, for \({\tilde{m}}\). From Proposition 5, this upper bound increases with the altruism parameter, which is the driving force for larger coalitions with than without altruism.

Fig. 3
figure 3

Each coalition country’s minimal emissions (left-hand side figure) and the internal stability condition (right-hand side figure) for \(m=3\) (solid curve) and for \(m=4\) (dashed curve) dependent on \(\alpha\) with \(n=100,a=100,b=1\) and \(d=1/4500\)

Fig. 4
figure 4

Global emissions (left-hand side figure) and global material welfare (right-hand side figure) dependent on \(\alpha\) with \(n=100,a=100,b=1\) and \(d=1/4500\)

We use a numerical example to demonstrate there are economies in which the coalition is larger with than without altruism. Figure 3 depicts each coalition country’s minimal emissionsFootnote 28 (left-hand side figure) and the internal stability condition (right-hand side figure) for \(m=3\) (solid curve) and for \(m=4\) (dashed curve) dependent on \(\alpha\). In the numerical example, each coalition country’s emissions are positive for all \(m\in [2,n]\). Furthermore, \(m=3\) becomes stable for \(\alpha \ge 0.223\), and \(m=4\) becomes stable for \(\alpha \ge 0.839\). Thus, there are economies in which the coalition is larger with than without altruism. Finally, Fig. 4 shows that global emissions decrease and global material welfare increases with the altruism parameter in the numerical example. Furthermore, as the coalition gets larger at \(\alpha =0.223\) and at \(\alpha =0.839\), global emissions jump downwards and global material welfare jumps upwards, but these jumps are (almost) not visible.

5 Discussion

The previous sections have shown that altruism affecting the membership decision and the policy decision leads to small (Proposition 2) or ineffective (Proposition 6) climate coalitions. By contrast, altruism affecting the membership decision only (van der Pol et al. 2012) can stabilise the grand coalition (Proposition 3).Footnote 29 Given that the effects of altruism on the formation of climate coalitions crucially depends on its modelling, this section discusses which realms of decision making might be influenced by social preferences in general.Footnote 30

We start by looking at what assumptions the literature on self-enforcing international environmental agreements with social preferences makes and how it justifies them. First, the literature incorporating inequality aversion (Lange and Vogt 2003; Lange 2006; Vogt 2016; Rogna and Vogt 2022) considers social preferences at both stages of the game and argues that governments interested in re-election must take (median) voters’ fairness preferences into account in national policy and international negotiations. Second, the literature incorporating reciprocal fairness (Grüning and Peters 2010; Nyborg 2018) also considers social preferences at both stages of the game.Footnote 31 Nyborg (2018, p. 707) argues that although groups may act differently than individuals, policy makers and treaty negotiators tend to be reciprocal when the general population is reciprocal, and tend to act reciprocally when the median voter is reciprocal. Third, the literature incorporating Kantian ethics (Eichner and Pethig 2022; Ulph and Ulph 2023) allows for different moral behaviour at the two stages of the game. Nevertheless, Eichner and Pethig (2022, pp. 18–19) argue that moral behaviour at just one stage of the game or different moral behaviour at the two stages of the game appears to be implausible, and Ulph and Ulph (2023, p. 12) “recognise that there is a strong argument that an agent should take the same moral stance to all decisions.” However, the latter argue that governments decide on coalition membership, while both governments and individuals decide on domestic emissions through public policy and private behaviour, respectively, such that the “decisions involve somewhat different agents”, which might explain different moral behaviour at the two stages of the game. Finally, van der Pol et al. (2012, p. 114) argue that “agents may hold different preferences when acting in different social situations, for example as consumers or as citizens.” They then distinguish between the decision about the technology employed and the domestic regulations adopted of a homo economicus with “personal well-being functions” (Nyborg 2000, p. 305), and the decision about the membership in the coalition of a homo politicus with “subjective social welfare functions” (Nyborg 2000, p. 305).

To sum up, most of the literature assumes that individual social preferences affect both stages of the game via the median voter (or because policy makers and treaty negotiators tend to have the same social preferences as the general population). On the other hand, taken together, van der Pol et al. (2012) and Ulph and Ulph (2023) provide good arguments that social preferences could be different at the two stages of the game: If there is a distinction between homo economicus and homo politicus and if homo economicus can influence domestic emissions, then social preferences might be more pronounced at the membership stage than at the policy stage. However, note that the cited literature (and the present paper) abstracts from individual decisions and assumes that countries or governments decide on both coalition membership and domestic emissions. In this case, all decisions are made by citizens rather than by consumers, and there should be no qualitative difference between social preferences at the two stages of the game.

However, strategic delegation could be another argument for different social preferences at different game stages. The literature on strategic delegation shows that strategic voters elect policy makers who care less about global public goods when policy makers bargain over their provision. Thereby, Buchholz et al. (2005) and Loeper (2017) assume that policy makers decide on the cooperative bargaining outcome and on the non-cooperative bargaining default (strong delegation), while Segendorff (1998) and Graziosi (2009) also consider policy makers deciding on the cooperative bargaining outcome but median voters deciding on the non-cooperative bargaining default (weak delegation), which leads to different preferences at different game stages.Footnote 32 Spycher and Winkler (2022) introduce strategic delegation into the standard two-stage game of self-enforcing international environmental agreements. They distinguish between weak delegation, i.e. elected policy makers decide on coalition membership but median voters decide on emissions policy, and strong delegation, i.e. elected policy makers decide at both stages of the game. While weak delegation does not increase coalition size but does increase global emissions, strong delegation can stabilise the grand coalition and thereby bring about the social optimum. These results suggest that strategic delegation can pay off. In this context, Lange and Schwirplies (2017) argue that there is indeed strategic delegation in climate policy because the social preferences of climate negotiators and the general population differ in that the former are more likely to support burden-sharing rules with low economic costs for their regions than the latter.

6 Extensions

This section performs two model extensions. The first subsection shows that a small degree of community altruism can stabilise the grand coalition. The second subsection reveals that altruism can stabilise coalitions of two countries but tends to destabilise coalitions of three or more countries with linear climate damages and asymmetric countries.Footnote 33

6.1 Community Altruism

In this subsection, we consider community altruism. In particular, we distinguish between out-group altruism \(\alpha\) and in-group altruism \(\beta >\alpha\). The psychological literature has developed and tested two theories in particular for the preference of in-group members over out-group members (Balliet et al. 2014): The social identity theory assumes that individuals identify themselves with their memberships in social groups (Tajfel et al. 1979), while the theory of bounded generalized reciprocity assumes that groups contain individuals with cooperative reputations, which induces indirect reciprocity (Yamagishi and Kiyonari 1999). Cheikbossian (2021a) shows that in-group altruism is evolutionary stable, Cheikbossian (2021b) finds that a combination of in-group altruism and out-group altruism can be evolutionary stable, and Balliet et al. (2014) summarize the significant evidence for in-group altruism (and against out-group spite) in psychological experiments.

In the following, we first analyse community altruism in the Nash game then report the effects of community altruism in the Stackelberg game. In the Nash game of coalition formation, each fringe country does not belong to a group, such that its moral welfare (1) and its first-order condition (4) do not change. By contrast, each coalition country belongs to the climate coalition, such that its moral welfare becomes

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i\in M}V_i&=\sum _{i\in M}\left[ W_i+\beta \sum _{j\in M\backslash i} W_j+\alpha \sum _{j\in N\backslash M} W_j\right] \nonumber \\&=[1-\alpha +(\beta -\alpha )(m-1)]\sum _{i\in M}W_i+\alpha m W. \end{aligned}$$
(16)

Thus, community altruism ceteris paribus increases the weight of the coalition’s material welfare. Rearranging the corresponding first-order condition yieldsFootnote 34

$$\begin{aligned} B'(e_c)&=\frac{1+\alpha (n-m)+\beta (m-1)}{1+\beta (m-1)}mD'(e)\le nD'(e), \end{aligned}$$
(17)

where the numerator reflects the altruistic preferences of the respective coalition country for all other countries’ climate damages, and the denominator reflects the altruistic preferences of all other coalition countries for the respective coalition country’s consumption benefits. Community altruism reduces the relative importance of the fringe countries’ climate damages, which ceteris paribus increases the coalition’s emissions. However, from (4) and (17), we infer

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{B'(e_c)}{B'(e_f)}&=\frac{m}{1+\alpha (n-1)}\frac{1+\alpha (n-m)+\beta (m-1)}{1+\beta (m-1)}\in (1,m]. \end{aligned}$$
(18)

Consequently, each fringe country’s emissions are still greater than each coalition country’s emissions. In Online Appendix B.1.1, we prove that the first bullet and the third bullet of Proposition 1 also hold with community altruism: Each coalition country consumes less than at BAU, which reduces global emissions and, thus, marginal climate damages, such that each fringe country consumes more than at BAU. Consequently, the material welfare of each fringe country is greater than that of each coalition country and greater than that at BAU. However, and in contrast to the case without community altruism, the moral welfare of each coalition country can be greater than that of each fringe country if the material welfare of each coalition country is positive, because then community altruism ceteris paribus increases the former but does not affect the latter. In particular, we have \(V_f-V_c=(1-\alpha )(W_f-W_c)-(\beta -\alpha )(m-1)W_c\), which ceteris paribus decreases with the degree of community altruism and with the coalition size if \(W_c>0\). This welfare effect of community altruism can reduce the free-rider incentives.

To analyse the policy effect of community altruism, we prove in Online Appendix B.1.1Footnote 35

Lemma 4

(Effects of community altruism on emissions and welfare)

  • \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e_f}{{\textrm{d}}\beta }<0\), \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e_c}{{\textrm{d}}\beta }>0\) and \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e}{{\textrm{d}}\beta }>0\),

  • \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}W_f}{{\textrm{d}}\beta }<0\) and \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}W_c}{{\textrm{d}}\beta }>0\),

  • \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}V_c}{{\textrm{d}}\beta }>0\) and \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}(V_f-V_c)}{{\textrm{d}}\beta }<0\) for \(W_c\ge 0\) (sufficient).

Ceteris paribus, community altruism does not affect each fringe country’s consumption, see (4), but increases each coalition country’s consumption, see (17). Thus, \(e_c\) increases, which increases global emissions and, thus, marginal climate damages, such that \(e_f\) decreases. Consequently, each fringe country’s material welfare decreases, while the increase in each coalition country’s consumption benefits outweighs the increase in the climate damages, such that its material welfare increases. This policy effect of community altruism raises each coalition country’s moral welfare and reduces the difference between the moral welfare of each fringe country and each coalition country if \(W_c\ge 0\). Furthermore, it reduces each fringe country’s moral welfare \(V_f=(1-\alpha )W_f+\alpha W\) if \(\alpha\) is sufficiently small, such that the decrease in \(W_f\) outweighs the potential increase in W.

Taken together, the sign of each coalition country’s material welfare plays an important role for the effects of community altruism on the free-rider incentives. This also becomes clear when we look at the (internal) stability condition of the grand coalition:

$$\begin{aligned}&V_c(n)-V_f(n-1)\nonumber \\&=(1-\beta )W_c(n)+\beta W(n)-\left[ (1-\alpha )W_f(n-1)+\alpha W(n-1)\right] \nonumber \\&=W(n)-(1-\beta )(n-1)W_c(n)-\left[ W(n-1)-(1-\alpha )(n-1)W_c(n-1)\right] . \end{aligned}$$
(19)

First note that the grand coalition maximizes global material welfare from \(V_c(n)=[1+\beta (n-1)]W_c(n)\) as in the case without community altruism. Now consider \(\beta =1\). Then, \(V_c(n)\) is maximized global material welfare W(n), and \(V_f(n-1)\) is non-maximized global material welfare \(W(n-1)\) minus the coalition’s material welfare weighted by \(1-\alpha\). Thus, the grand coalition is stable if \(W_c(n-1)\ge 0\). By contrast, if \(W_c(n-1)<0\), the grand coalition need not be stable. For example, consider \(\alpha =0\). Then, \(V_f(n-1)\) is equal to the fringe country’s material welfare \(W_f(n-1)\), and this material welfare can exceed maximized global welfare W(n) if \(W_c(n-1)<0\). However, it can be shown that \(W_c(n-1)>0\) holds with specification (9) when there is a sufficiently large number of countries (\(n\ge 9\)). Then, the emissions policy of one fringe country is relatively unimportant for the material welfare of many coalition countries. In this case, the grand coalition is stable for \(\beta =1\).

Note that \(W_c(n)\) is always non-negative because the grand coalition could choose \(e_c=0\) and, thus, \(B(0)\ge 0\) and \(D(0)=0\). Consequently, in-group altruism increases each country’s moral welfare in the grand coalition. Furthermore, it reduces each fringe country’s material welfare, but raises each coalition country’s material welfare with any other coalition, such that the effect on each fringe country’s moral welfare is in general ambiguous. However, in Online Appendix B.1.1 we prove that this effect is definitely negative if there is only one fringe country. Then, in-group altruism increases the emissions of so many coalition countries that the corresponding increase in climate damages and decrease in the fringe country’s consumption benefits outweigh the increase in the coalition country’s consumption benefits. To sum up, in-group altruism increases the stability of the grand coalition.

Finally, out-group altruism does not affect each country’s moral welfare in the grand coalition, but it reduces global emissions and increases global material welfare with any other coalition, see Lemma 1. Thus, it also tends to increase \(V_f(n-1)=W_f(n-1)+\alpha (n-1)W_c(n-1)\) if \(W_c(n-1)>0\). Consequently, it can be shown that out-group altruism increases the fringe country’s moral welfare with specification (9) when there is a sufficiently large number of countries (\(n\ge 10\)). In this case, out-group altruism decreases the stability of the grand coalition. We prove our results in Online Appendix B.1.1 and summarize them in

Proposition 7

(Stability of grand coalition with community altruism) Consider specification (9).

  • The internal stability condition of the grand coalition increases with \(\beta\), and it decreases with \(\alpha\) for \(n\ge 10\) and \(d\le {\bar{d}}\) (sufficient).

  • The grand coalition is stable for \(\beta =1\), \(n\ge 6\) and \(d\le {\bar{d}}\) (sufficient).

Thus, community altruism can stabilise the grand coalition and thereby bring about the social optimum. Figure 5 depicts thresholds of \(\beta -\alpha\) for the grand coalition to be stable dependent on \(\alpha\) in the Nash game (left-hand side figure) for different values of the climate damage parameter d.Footnote 36 When this parameter is small, emissions policy is determined mainly by marginal emissions benefits rather than marginal climate damages, so that the difference between the emissions and therefore the material welfare of each fringe country and each coalition country is small, which reduces free-rider incentives and stabilises the grand coalition. Figure 5 shows that the grand coalition can be stable even with a small difference between in-group altruism and out-group altruism of less than 0.03.Footnote 37 Note that community altruism does not change the grand coalition’s emissions policy, so its stabilizing effect relies on the worse emissions policy for the final fringe country (policy effect) and on the increased moral welfare of each coalition country for a given emissions policy (welfare effect).Footnote 38

Fig. 5
figure 5

Thresholds of \(\beta -\alpha\) for the grand coalition to be stable dependent on \(\alpha\) in the Nash game (left-hand side figure) and in the Stackelberg game (right-hand side figure) with \(n=100,a=100,b=1\) and \(d=1/10{,}000\) (solid curve), \(d=2.375/10{,}000\) (dashed curve) and \(d=3.75/10{,}000\) (dotted curve)

Finally, we report the effects of community altruism in the Stackelberg game. Since the results are simply a combination of those in the Stackelberg game without community altruism and those in the Nash game with community altruism, we delegate the full analysis to Online Appendix B.1.2. First, there is a unique threshold coalition \({\hat{m}}\in (1,n)\) where the Stackelberg equilibrium and BAU coincide in terms of emissions and material welfare. If \(W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\ge 0\), then \(V_c(m)\ge V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) and \(V_f(m)\le V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) for \(m\le {\hat{m}}\), such that all coalition \(m\le {\hat{m}}\) are externally unstable, and the coalition \(m=\left\lfloor {\hat{m}}+1\right\rfloor \ge 2\) is internally stable as in the case without community altruism.Footnote 39 Second, community altruism increases each coalition country’s emissions and global emissions, and it decreases each fringe country’s emissions as in the Nash game. Consequently, \({\hat{m}}\) increases with \(\beta\), which can stabilise larger coalitions. Furthermore, community altruism decreases each fringe country’s moral welfare, and it increases each coalition country’s moral welfare if \(W_c\ge 0\) as in the Nash game, which then stabilises larger coalitions. In particular, in-group [out-group] altruism increases [decreases] the internal stability condition of the grand coalition [when there is a sufficiently large number of countries] as in the Nash game. Furthermore, it can be shown that the condition for the grand coalition to be stable is laxer in the Stackelberg game than in the Nash game. However, Fig. 5 shows that the thresholds of \(\beta -\alpha\) for the grand coalition to be stable dependent on \(\alpha\) in the Stackelberg game (right-hand side figure) are close to those in the Nash game (left-hand side figure).

6.2 Asymmetric Countries

In this subsection, we consider asymmetric countries in terms of consumption benefits \(B_i(e_i)\) and climate damages \(D_i(e)\). With convex climate damages \(D''_i>0\) (or abatement benefits), the results of previous literature on coalition stability with asymmetric countries are based on numerical analyses (Barrett 1997; Botteon and Carraro 2001; McGinty 2007; Bakalova and Eyckmans 2019; McGinty 2020). In order to obtain analytical results, we thus rely on linear climate damages \(D''_i=0\) in this subsection. This implies that each fringe country has a dominant strategy, such that the Nash game and the Stackelberg game coincide. Furthermore, we focus on the case without transfers.

In such a framework with two types of countries, Fuentes-Albero and Rubio (2010) show that a coalition of at most three countries is stable if either climate damages or emissions benefits are symmetric. Pavlova and De Zeeuw (2013) confirm this result and show that the same holds if climate damages and emissions benefits are positively correlated. By contrast, if climate damages and abatement costs are negatively correlated, a coalition of all countries with low climate damages and two countries with high climate damages can be stable. Finus and McGinty (2019) extend this analysis by allowing for any type of countries. They show that the grand coalition can be stable if climate damages and abatement costs are negatively correlated.

Following van der Pol et al. (2012), we consider a unique altruism parameter to derive the general effects of altruism on the formation of climate coalitions. Furthermore, we abstract from community altruism to check the robustness of our main model with linear climate damages and asymmetric countries. With a unique altruism parameter and without community altruism, each country’s moral welfare function is still given by (1), and the global moral welfare function is still given by (2). Consequently, the socially optimal emissions always maximize global material welfare, and the individually optimal emissions maximize global material welfare if and only if \(\alpha =1\). In Appendix A.1, we prove that global emissions decrease and global material welfare increases with the altruism parameter in the individually optimal solution as in the main model. Consequently, the relative global emissions \(e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}/e^{{\textrm{SO}}}\) decrease and the relative global material and moral welfare \(W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}/W^{{\textrm{SO}}}=V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}/V^{{\textrm{SO}}}\) increase with the altruism parameter.

In the coalition formation game, each fringe country’s moral welfare is still given by (1), and the sum of the coalition countries’ moral welfare is still given by (3). Rearranging the corresponding first-order conditions yields

$$\begin{aligned} B'_i(e_i)&=(1-\alpha )D'_i(e)+\alpha \sum _{j\in N}D'_j(e)\le \sum _{j\in N}D'_j(e),{} & {} \forall i\notin M, \end{aligned}$$
(20)
$$\begin{aligned} B'_i(e_i)&=\frac{(1-\alpha )\sum _{j\in M}D'_j(e)+\alpha m\sum _{j\in N}D'_j(e)}{1+\alpha (m-1)}\nonumber \\&=(1-\alpha )D'_i(e)+\alpha \sum _{j\in N}D'_j(e)\nonumber \\&\quad +(1-\alpha )\frac{\sum _{j\in M\backslash i}D'_j(e)+\alpha (m-1)\sum _{j\in N\backslash i}D'_j(e)}{1+\alpha (m-1)}\le \sum _{j\in N}D'_j(e),{} & {} \forall i\in M. \end{aligned}$$
(21)

Consequently, considering two ex ante identical countries, the emissions of the country outside the coalition are greater than those of the country inside the coalition, which means that also the material and moral welfare of the country outside the coalition are greater than those of the country inside the coalition. In Online AppendixB.2.1, we proveFootnote 40

Proposition 8

(Comparison of Nash equilibrium and BAU with asymmetric countries)

  • \(e_i<e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) for all \(i\in M\), \(e_i=e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) for all \(i\notin M\) and \(e<e^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\),

  • \(V_i>V_i^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for all \(i\notin M\) and \(V>V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\),

  • \(W_i>W_i^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for all \(i\notin M\) and \(W>W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\).

(21) implies that the coalition countries are ceteris paribus more ambitious in the fight against climate change than at BAU. This results in smaller emissions inside the coalition, while the fringe countries’ dominant strategies imply that the emissions outside the coalition do not change, such that global emissions are smaller than at BAU. Smaller global emissions and constant fringe country’s emissions imply \(W_i>W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_i\) for all \(i\notin M\). The remaining results arise from the superadditivity of the game, i.e. \(\sum _{j\in M}V_j\ge \sum _{j\in M}V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}_j\): Superadditivity implies \(W>W^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\), which in turn implies \(V_i>V_i^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\) for all \(i\notin M\) and \(V>V^{{\textrm{BAU}}}\).

To prepare the analysis of the first stage of the Nash game, we prove in Online Appendix B.2.2Footnote 41

Lemma 5

(Effects of coalition size and altruism on emissions and welfare with asymmetric countries)

  • If another country joins the coalition, then each coalition country’s emissions decrease, each fringe country’s emissions do not change and global emissions decrease. Furthermore, each fringe country’s material and moral welfare increase, and global material and moral welfare increase.

  • \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}e_i}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }<0\) for all \(i\in N\) and \(\frac{{\textrm{d}}W}{{\textrm{d}}\alpha }>0\).

The first bullet of the lemma reveals that the comparison between Nash equilibrium and BAU from Proposition 8 can be transferred to the comparison between the equilibrium with some coalition M and the equilibrium with some smaller coalition \(M\backslash i\): The larger the coalition, the more it fights against climate change, which leads to smaller emissions of the original coalition members, to smaller emissions of the new coalition member and, thus, to smaller global emissions. The material welfare of each fringe country increases, because its consumption benefits do not change, but its climate damages decrease. Superadditivity implies that global welfare increases, which in turn implies that the moral welfare of each fringe country and global moral welfare increase.

The second bullet of the lemma reveals that each country’s emissions decrease and global material welfare increases with the altruism parameter. Consequently, the relative global emissions \(e/e^{{\textrm{SO}}}\) decrease and the relative global material and moral welfare \(W/W^{{\textrm{SO}}}=V/V^{{\textrm{SO}}}\) increase with the altruism parameter as in the main model with symmetric countries and convex climate damages.

For the first stage of the game, we use the following specification

$$\begin{aligned} B_i(e_i)=a_ie_i-\frac{b_i}{2}e_i^2,\quad D_i(e)=d_ie,\quad \text {with }a_i,b_i,d_i>0. \end{aligned}$$
(22)

In Online Appendix B.2.3, we then prove

Proposition 9

(Stability of coalitions with asymmetric countries) Consider the specification (22).

  • Suppose \(b_i=b\) and \(d_i=d\) for all \(i\in N\). Then, any coalition with three members is stable for \(\alpha =0\), and any coalition with two members is stable for \(\alpha >0\).

  • Suppose \(\big \{b_1<b_2<\dots <b_n\) and \(d_1\le d_2\le \dots \le d_n\big \}\) or \(\big \{b_1\le b_2\le \dots \le b_n\) and \(d_1<d_2<\dots <d_n\big \}\). Then, only coalitions with two members can be stable, and the condition for at least one coalition to be stable is tighter for \(\alpha =0\) than for \(\alpha >0\).

  • Suppose \(b_1\le b_2\le \dots \le b_n\) and \(d_1\ge d_2\ge \dots \ge d_n\). Then, any coalition can be stable, and the condition for the grand coalition to be stable is laxer for \(\alpha =0\) than for \(\alpha >0\).

For \(\alpha =0\), Proposition 9 replicates the results of Finus and McGinty (2019): With identical \(b_i\) and \(d_i\) parameters, a coalition of three countries is stable. With a positive covariance between these parameters, either a coalition of two countries or no coalition is stable. The coalition becomes smaller because countries with small \(b_i\) and \(d_i\) parameters profit greatly from additional emissions benefits and suffer little from additional climate damages when they leave a coalition.Footnote 42 With a negative covariance, countries with small \(b_i\) and large \(d_i\) parameters and countries with large \(b_i\) and small \(d_i\) parameters can mutually benefit from a large coalition, which can even stabilise the grand coalition.

For \(\alpha >0\), we get mixed results. With identical \(b_i\) and \(d_i\) parameters, the negative effect of altruism is even stronger than with quadratic climate damages, since the coalition is always smaller for \(\alpha >0\) than for \(\alpha =0\) with linear climate damages. In Online Appendix B.2.4, we prove that the effects of altruism on the internal stability condition are comparable to those of the main model: The direct effect is positive, the policy effect inside the coalition is positive, but the policy effect outside the coalition is also positive and predominates, such that staying in the coalition becomes less important as countries become more altruistic. With individual \(b_i\) and \(d_i\) parameters, altruism has two effects on the internal stability condition: First, it reduces the effective variance of the \(d_i\) parameters, because each coalition country accounts for the climate damages of all fringe countries. Second, it increases the incentive to stay in small coalitions \(|M|=2\), but reduces the incentive to stay in large coalitions \(|M|\ge 3\). Both effects stabilise \(|M|=2\) with a positive covariance between \(b_i\) and \(d_i\), but tend to destabilise \(|M|\ge 3\) with a negative covariance between these parameters. In particular, the condition for the grand coalition to be stable is laxer for \(\alpha =0\) than for \(\alpha >0\).

Finally, to further check the robustness of our main model, we also analyse the second stage of the Nash game with convex climate damages and asymmetric countries in Online Appendix B.2. We find that global emissions decrease and each fringe country’s emissions and material welfare increase if another country joins the coalition as in the main model. Consequently, global emissions are smaller and each fringe country’s emissions and material welfare are greater than at BAU. Furthermore, global emissions decrease with the altruism parameter as in the main model. However, in contrast to the main model, some fringe country’s emissions could increase with the altruism parameter. For example, suppose that only one fringe country faces climate damages and countries become more altruistic. Then, all other countries consume less (because this benefits the respective fringe country), which reduces global emissions and, thus, marginal climate damages, such that the respective fringe country consumes more (because this does not harm the other countries). The effects of altruism on global material welfare also become ambiguous. However, if countries only differ in their emissions benefits and not in their climate damages, then each fringe country’s emissions decrease and global material welfare increases with the altruism parameter as in the main model.

7 Conclusion

This paper analyses the effects of altruism on the formation of climate coalitions in the canonical two-stage game of self-enforcing international environmental agreements. Thereby, altruism implies that each country values, to some extent, every other country’s welfare when deciding on its coalition membership and emissions policy. In the Nash [Stackelberg] game with linear-quadratic emissions benefits and quadratic emissions damages, altruism weakly decreases [increases] the coalition size. However, the coalition never comprises more than six countries, and the corresponding global emissions and global welfare are close to the non-cooperative values. Nevertheless, altruism reduces global emissions and raises global welfare by narrowing the gap between the individually optimal values and the socially optimal values. Thus, altruism affecting the membership decision and the policy decision appears to be more of a substitute than a complement for large climate coalitions. Consequently, altruism may help explain why countries are willing to internalize their climate externalities onto other countries, but are unwilling to conclude a large and effective climate agreement.

We find that these results crucially depend on the modelling of altruism: If altruism affects the membership decision but not the policy decision (van der Pol et al. 2012), countries stay in the coalition to avoid worse policy outcomes from smaller coalitions, which can stabilise large coalitions. If each coalition country is more altruistic toward other coalition countries than toward fringe countries (community altruism), coalition countries achieve greater moral welfare and become less ambitious in the fight against climate change, which reduces the free-rider incentives and can stabilise the grand coalition. Finally, altruism can stabilise small coalitions but destabilises large coalitions with linear climate damages and asymmetric countries.

Our analysis can be extended in several directions. For example, one could analyse the optimal strategic delegation of each country’s principal to a country’s agent with different altruistic preferences between the first and the second stage of the game (Spycher and Winkler 2022). Furthermore, it may be interesting to replace the assumption of pure altruism with the assumption of paternalistic or impure altruism. In the first case, one could consider different altruistic parameters for other countries’ consumption benefits and climate damages. In the second case, one could add warm-glow transfers between countries at a third stage of the game. Finally, the results at the first stage of the Nash game and the Stackelberg game depend on the functional forms of the benefit function and the damage function, such that it may be interesting to replace our linear-quadratic specification with, e.g., an isoelastic specification (Nkuiya 2020). These issues are beyond the scope of the present paper but may represent interesting and important tasks for future research.