Skip to main content
Log in

Gene mobility and the concept of relatedness

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Cooperation is rife in the microbial world, yet our best current theories of the evolution of cooperation were developed with multicellular animals in mind. Hamilton’s theory of inclusive fitness is an important case in point: applying the theory in a microbial setting is far from straightforward, as social evolution in microbes has a number of distinctive features that the theory was never intended to capture. In this article, I focus on the conceptual challenges posed by the project of extending Hamilton’s theory to accommodate the effects of gene mobility. I begin by outlining the basics of the theory of inclusive fitness, emphasizing the role that the concept of relatedness is intended to play. I then provide a brief history of this concept, showing how, over the past fifty years, it has departed from the intuitive notion of genealogical kinship to encompass a range of generalized measures of genetic similarity. I proceed to argue that gene mobility forces a further revision of the concept. The reason in short is that, when the genes implicated in producing social behaviour are mobile, we cannot talk of an organism’s genotype simpliciter; we can talk only of an organism’s genotype at a particular stage in its life cycle. We must therefore ask: with respect to which stage(s) in the life cycle should relatedness be evaluated? For instance: is it genetic similarity at the time of social interaction that matters to the evolution of social behaviour, or is it genetic similarity at the time of reproduction? I argue that, strictly speaking, it is neither of these: what really matters to the evolution of social behaviour is diachronic genetic similarity between the producers of fitness benefits at the time they produce them and the recipients of those benefits at the end of their life-cycle. I close by discussing the implications of this result. The main payoff is that it makes room for a possible new mechanism for the evolution of altruism in microbes that does not require correlated interaction among bearers of the genes for altruism. The importance of this mechanism in nature remains an open empirical question.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It may well be. The precise wording of the brothers and cousins remark does not appear anywhere in Haldane’s published work, but he does discuss broadly similar ideas in a 1955 article (Haldane 1955). Indeed, he explicitly considers a hypothetical scenario in which one must choose whether or not to jump into a river to save a drowning child.

  2. As Seger (1981) points out, we will find huge numbers of such paths between any two organisms if we go back far enough. There is thus an implicit pragmatic dimension to Wright’s procedure: we look only at those genealogical relationships between organisms that are recent enough to have non-negligible path coefficients.

  3. This approximation relies on our assumptions that the plasmid is rare and that groups are large. If we do not make these assumptions, the frequency of plasmid bearers after conjugation is \(N+\lambda {N}(M-N)/(M-1)\). This quantity is approximated by \(N+\lambda {N}\) when \(M \gg N\) (the plasmid is rare) and \(M \gg 1\) (groups are large). I thank Patrick Forber and an anonymous referee for helpful suggestions here.

  4. Even without gene mobility, there is a sense in which the average genotype of a social group may be time-dependent, if the composition of this social group changes during the life-cycle; and this can introduce a form of time-dependence to measures of whole-group relatedness. Time-dependence of this sort (and its consequences for \(r\)) is discussed in Úbeda and Gardner (2012). My claim here is that diachronic variation in an individual’s genotype during its life-cycle introduces a yet more radical sort of time-dependence, with further consequences for the concept of relatedness.

  5. See, e.g., McElreath and Boyd (2007), p. 76: “The key to understanding the evolution of altruism is non-random interaction. If altruistic strategies are more likely to be paired with other altruistic strategies, altruism can evolve. If interaction is random, it cannot.”

  6. One may ask: is the phenotype really altruistic, if it is advantageous for the plasmid that produces it? The answer is that it is altruistic in the standard technical sense of the term, provided the phenotype detracts from the fitness of the organism that expresses it and confers benefits on other organisms. In general, any altruistic phenotype may be recast as ‘selfish’ from the point of view of the genes responsible, but this does not preclude its being altruistic in the standard technical sense of the term (West et al. 2007b; Okasha 2013)

References

  • Berleman JE, Chumley T, Cheung P, Kirby JR (2006) Rippling is a predatory behavior in Myxococcus xanthus. J Bacteriol 188:5888–5895

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biernaskie JM, West SA, Gardner A (2011) Are greenbeards intragenomic outlaws? Evolution 65:2729–2742

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birch J (2014) Hamilton’s rule and its discontents. Br J Philos Sci. doi:10.1093/bjps/axt016

  • Bonner JT (1959) The cellular slime molds. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Bourke AFG (2011a) Principles of social evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bourke AFG (2011b) The validity and value of inclusive fitness theory. Proc Roy Soc Lond B Biol Sci 278:3313–3320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breden F (1990) Partitioning of covariance as a method for studying kin selection. Trends Ecol Evol 5:224–228

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bushman F (2002) Lateral DNA transfer: mechanisms and consequences. Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory Press, Coldspring Spring Harbor

    Google Scholar 

  • Cockerham CC (1954) An extension of the concept of partitioning hereditary variance for analysis of covariances among relatives when epistasis is present. Genetics 39:8659–882

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornforth DM, Sumpter DJ, Brown SP, Brnnstrm (2012) Synergy and group size in microbial cooperation. Am Nat 180:296–305

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crespi BJ (2001) The evolution of social behaviour in microorganisms. Trends Ecol Evol 16:178–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies NB, Krebs JR, West SA (2012) An introduction to behavioural ecology. Wiley, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. W. W. Norton and Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunning Hotopp JC, Clark ME, Oliveira DC, Foster JM, Fischer P, Muoz Torres MC, Giebel JD, Kumar N, Ishmael N, Wang S, Ingram J, Nene RV, Shepard J, Tomkins J, Richards S, Spiro DJ, Ghedin E, Slatko BE, Tettelin H, Werren JH (2007) Widespread lateral gene transfer from intracellular bacteria to multicellular eukaryotes. Science 317:1753–1756

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (2012) Processes of life: essays in the philosophy of biology. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Falconer DS (1961) Introduction to quantitative genetics (\(1^{{\rm st}}\) edition). Oliver and Boyd, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Falconer DS, Mackay TFC (1996) Introduction to quantitative genetics (\(4^{{\rm th}}\) edition). Longman, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1918) The correlation between relatives on the supposition of Mendelian inheritance. Trans Roy Soc Edinburgh 52:399–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection, 1st edn. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher RA (1941) Average excess and average effect of a gene substitution. Ann Hum Genet 11:53–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank SA (1997) Models of symbiosis. Am Nat 150:S80–S99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank SA (1998) Foundations of social evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank SA (2006) Social selection. In: Fox CW, Wolf JB (eds) Evolutionary genetics: concepts and case studies. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 350–363

    Google Scholar 

  • Frost LS, Leplae R, Summers AO, Toussaint A (2005) Mobile genetic elements: the agents of open source evolution. Nat Rev Microbiol 3:722–732

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, Foster KR (2008) The evolution and ecology of cooperation history and concepts. In: Korb J, Heinze J (eds) Ecology of social evolution. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 1–36

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, West SA (2004a) Spite and the scale of competition. J Evol Biol 17:1195–1203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, West SA (2004b) Spite among siblings. Science 305:1413–1414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, West SA (2006) Spite. Curr Biol 16:R662–R664

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, West SA (2010) Greenbeards. Evolution 64:25–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, West SA, Wild G (2011) The genetical theory of kin selection. J Evol Biol 24:1020–1043

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giraud T, Shykoff JA (2011) Bacterial controlled by mobile elements: kin selection versus infectivity. Heredity 107:277–278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1985) A geometrical view of relatedness. Oxf Surv Evol Biol 2:28–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (2006) Optimization of inclusive fitness. J Theor Biol 238:541–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haldane JBS (1955) Population genetics. In: Johnson ML, Abercrombie M, Fogg GE (eds) New Biology 18. Penguin, London, pp 34–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Haldane JBS, Jayakar SD (1962) An enumeration of some human relationships. J Genet 58:81–107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1963) The evolution of altruistic behaviour. Am Nat 97:354–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1964) The genetical evolution of social behaviour. J Theor Biol 7:1–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1970) Selfish and spiteful behaviour in an evolutionary model. Nature 228:1218–1220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1971) Selection of selfish and altruistic behaviour in some extreme models. In: Eisenberg JF, Dillon WS (eds) Man and beast: comparative social behavior. Smithsonian Press, Washington, pp 57–91

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1972) Altruism and related phenomena, mainly in social insects. Ann Rev Ecol Syst 3:193–232

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1975) Innate social aptitudes of man: an approach from evolutionary genetics. In: Fox R (ed) Biosocial anthropology. Wiley, New York, pp 133–155

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin R (1982) Collective action. John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagel JH, Roth AE (eds) (1995) The handbook of experimental economics. Princeton University Press, Princeton

  • Kempthorne O (1954) The correlation between relatives in a random mating population. Proc Roy Soc Lond B Biol Sci 143:103–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kempthorne O (1955) The theoretical values of correlations between relatives in random mating populations. Genetics 40:153–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Kempthorne O (1957) An introduction to genetic statistics. Wiley, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederberg ND, Tatum J (1946) Genetic exchange in Salmonella. J Bacteriol 64:679–699

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1970) How to define theoretical terms. J Philos 67:427–446

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Li CC, Sacks L (1954) The derivation of joint distribution and correlation between relatives by the use of stochastic matrices. Biometrics 10:347–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McElreath R, Boyd R (2007) Mathematical models of social evolution: a guide for the perplexed. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mc Ginty SÉ, Rankin DJ, Brown SP (2011) Horizontal gene transfer and the evolution of bacterial cooperation. Evolution 65:21–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mc Ginty SÉ, Rankin DJ (2012) The evolution of conflict resolution between plasmids and their bacterial hosts. Evolution 66:1662–1670

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mc Ginty SÉ, Lehmann L, Brown SP, Rankin DJ (2013) The interplay between relatedness and horizontal gene transfer drives the evolution of plasmid-carried public goods. Proc Roy Soc Lond B Biol Sci 280:20130400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall JAR (2011) Group selection and kin selection: formally equivalent approaches. Trends Ecol Evol 26:325–332

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1964) Group selection and kin selection. Nature 200:1145–1147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1976) Letter to New Scientist. New Sci 71:247

    Google Scholar 

  • Michod RE, Hamilton WD (1980) Coefficients of relatedness in socio-biology. Nature 288:694–697

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nogueira T, Rankin DJ, Touchon M, Taddei F, Brown SP, Rocha EPC (2009) Horizontal gene transfer of the secretome drives the evolution of bacterial cooperation and virulence. Curr Biol 19(20):1683–1691

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson M (1965) The logic of collective action: public goods and the theory of groups. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. 2013. Biological altruism. In E. Zalta (ed), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2013 edition). URL=[http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/altruism-biological/] (Accessed 18/03/2014)

  • O’Malley M (ed) (2010) The tree of life [special issue]. Biol Philos 25(4)

  • O’Malley M (ed) (2013) Philosophy and the microbe [special issue]. Biol Philos 28(2)

  • O’Malley M, Boucher Y (eds) (2011) Beyond the tree of life. Biol Direct 25(4)

  • Orlove MJ, Wood CL (1978) Coefficients of relationship and coefficients of relatedness in kin selection: a covariance form for the RHO formula. J Theor Biol 73:679–686

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pepper JW (2000) Relatedness in trait-group models of social evolution. J Theor Biol 206:355–368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price GR (1970) Selection and covariance. Nature 227:520–1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price GR (1972) Extension of covariance selection mathematics. Ann Hum Genet 35:485–490

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Provine WB (1971) The origins of theoretical population genetics. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC (1985) Kinship, reciprocity, and synergism in the evolution of social behaviour. Nature 318:366–7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC, Goodnight KF (1989) Estimating relatedness using genetic markers. Evolution 43:258–275

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rankin DJ, Rocha EPC, Brown SP (2011a) What traits are carried on mobile genetic elements, and why? Heredity 106:1–10

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rankin DJ, Mc Ginty SE, Nogueira T, Touchon M, Taddei F, Rocha EPC, Brown SP (2011b) Bacterial cooperation controlled by mobile genetic elements: kin selection and infectivity are part of the same process. Heredity 107:279–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ridley M, Grafen A (1981) Are green beard genes outlaws? Anim Behav 29:954–955

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsek MR, Greenberg EP (2005) Sociomicrobiology: the connections between quorum sensing and biofilms. Trends Microbiol 13:27–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seger J (1981) Kinship and covariance. J Theor Biol 91:191–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smead R, Forber P (2013) The evolutionary dynamics of spite in finite populations. Evolution 67:698–707

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith J (2001) The social evolution of bacterial pathogenesis. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 268:61–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith J, van Dyken JD, Zee PC (2010) A generalization of Hamiltons rule for the evolution of microbial cooperation. Science 328:1700–1703

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strassmann JE, Queller DC (2011) Evolution of cooperation and control of cheating in a social microbe. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 108:10855–10862

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strassmann JE, Zhu Y, Queller DC (2000) Altruism and social cheating in the social amoeba Dictyostelium discoideum. Nature 408:965–967

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas CM, Nielsen KM (2005) Mechanisms of, and barriers to, horizontal gene transfer between bacteria. Nat Rev Microbiol 3:711–721

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toro M, Abugov R, Charlesworth B, Michod RE (1982) Exact versus heuristic models of kin selection. J Theor Biol 97:699–713

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Úbeda F, Gardner A (2012) Genomic imprinting in the social brain: elders. Evolution 66:1567–81

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uyenoyama MK, Feldman MW (1981) On relatedness and adaptive topography in kin selection. Theor Popul Biol 19:87–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velicer GJ, Vos M (2009) Sociobiology of the myxobacteria. Annu Rev Microbiol 63:599–623

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenseleers T, Gardner A, Foster KR (2010) Social evolution theory: a review of methods and approaches. In: Szkely T, Moore AJ, Komdeur J (eds) Social behaviour: genes, ecology and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 132–58

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Gardner A (2010) Altruism, spite and greenbeards. Science 327:1341–1344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Gardner A (2013) Inclusive fitness and adaptation. Curr Biol 23:R577–R584

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Griffin AS, Gardner A (2007b) Social semantics: altruism, cooperation, mutualism, strong reciprocity and group selection. J Evol Biol 20:415–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Griffin AS, Gardner A, Diggle SP (2006) Social evolution theory for microbes. Nat Rev Microbiol 4:597–607

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Diggle SP, Buckling A, Gardner A, Griffin AS (2007a) The social lives of microbes. Annu Rev Ecol Evol Syst 38:53–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright S (1922) Coefficients of inbreeding and relationship. Am Nat 56:330–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zinder ND, Lederberg J (1952) Genetic exchange in Salmonella. J Bacteriol 64:679–699

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank audiences at Cambridge, LSE, Carnegie Mellon, Exeter and Montpellier for their questions and comments, and I particularly thank my co-panellists at ISHPSSB 2013, Sara Mitri and John Dupré. I thank Christopher Clarke, John Dupré, Patrick Forber, Andy Gardner, Tim Lewens, Conor Mayo-Wilson, Sara Mitri, Tobias Uller and an anonymous referee for their comments on the manuscript. I also extend belated thanks to Rosa Cao for her comments on another paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Birch.

Appendices

Appendix 1: Diachronic relatedness in a Prisoner’s dilemma

In the main text I argue that, when organisms engage in plasmid conjugation following pairwise social interaction, the best measure of \(r\) is a diachronic variant of the usual regression definition. This appendix supports that argument by providing a formal analysis of a simple model of pairwise cooperation. This is not intended to provide a realistic model of microbial cooperation; it is a simple model designed to make the conceptual issues surrounding the definition of \(r\) as clear as possible.

Basic setup

We consider an infinite population of asexually reproducing organisms. The population is sorted at random into pairs, and each pair plays a one-shot two-player Prisoner’s Dilemma with the following payoff matrix:

 

COOPERATE

DEFECT

COOPERATE

\(B-C\)

\(-C\)

DEFECT

\(B\)

\(0\)

We assume that the population is under weak viability selection only, so that the payoffs can be interpreted as marginal costs and benefits to the viability of the players.

A fraction \(f_X\) of organisms bear a plasmid, \(X\), that reliably causes them to cooperate. Let \(g_{Xi}(t)\) represent the genic value of the ith organism with respect to \(X\) at time \(t\), such that \(g_{Xi}(t)=1\) for an organism that carries \(X\) at \(t\), and \(g_{Xi}(t)=0\) for an organism that does not. Meanwhile, a fraction \(f_Y\) of organisms bear a different plasmid, \(Y\), that has no fitness-relevant phenotypic effects on its host. Let \(g_{Yi}(t)\) represent the genic value of the ith organism with respect to \(Y\) at time \(t\), such that \(g_{Yi}(t)=1\) for an organism that carries \(Y\) at \(t\), and \(g_{Yi}(t)=0\) for an organism that does not. Both \(X\) and \(Y\) may in principle be carried by the same organism. We assume, however, that the two plasmids are transmitted independently of each other, so that there is no correlation, positive or negative, between possessing \(X\) and possessing \(Y\).

After playing the game and conferring payoffs, the players conjugate with probability \(\pi\). During conjugation, a bearer of plasmid \(X\) will transmit the plasmid to its social partner (if it is initially a non-bearer) with transmission probability \(\lambda _X\). The \(\lambda _X\) parameter may be interpreted as quantifying the infectivity of \(X\). Correspondingly, a bearer of plasmid \(Y\) will transmit the plasmid to its social partner (if it is initially a non-bearer) with transmission probability \(\lambda _Y\). The \(\lambda _Y\) parameter may be interpreted as quantifying the infectivity of \(Y\).

Next, there is a global competition phase, in which all individuals compete for representation in the next generation, and individuals are killed off with a probability equal to their net viability (i.e. individuals who received \(B\) without paying \(C\) are least likely to be killed off; individuals who paid \(C\) without receiving \(B\) are most likely). Finally, at the end of the life-cycle, the surviving cells divide to produce the next generation. We assume that all plasmids are transmitted from a parent cell to its daughter cells with perfect fidelity. In reality, plasmids are sometimes ‘lost’ during cell division (i.e. they are absent from one of the daughter cells). We neglect this phenomenon here, because it would complicate the analysis without affecting the main conceptual conclusions.

Because individuals are paired up at random in the social phase, there is no positive assortment at \(t_A\). We thus intuitively expect that defectors will outperform cooperators, and that plasmids (such as \(X\)) that encode cooperation will decrease in frequency at the expense of those (such as \(Y\)) that do not. But, as we will see, the possibility of plasmid transfer after social interaction complicates the picture.

Modified price equation

We can employ the Price equation (Price 1970, 1972) to study the conditions under which \(X\) will spread more rapidly than \(Y\), or vice versa. The standard Price equation describes the change in the additive genetic value of some trait between an ancestor population and a descendant population. These populations may represent consecutive generations in a discrete generations model, or appropriately chosen earlier and later census points in an overlapping generations model. Price showed that this change could be decomposed into a covariance term and an expectation term:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g_i} = \frac{1}{\overline{w}}\left[ {\mathrm{Cov}}({w_i},g_i) +{\mathrm{E}}(w_i\Delta g_i)\right] \end{aligned}$$
(7)

where \(w_i\) is the fitness of the ith individual, conceptualized as its total contribution to the descendant population, and \(g_i\) is its additive genetic value for the character of interest.

The standard version of the Price equation is not ideal in the present context, for two main reasons. Firstly, the genetic value in the Cov term is not indexed to any particular time in the life-cycle, so its value will be indeterminate in cases in which an organism’s genotype is altered during its life-cycle by plasmid transfer. For our purposes, we need to specify the time in the life-cycle at which \(g_i\) is to be evaluated. Secondly, both terms in the standard Price equation are affected by fitness differences; the equation thus splits the effects of differential fitness between its two terms. For our purposes, it will be convenient to capture all the effects of differential fitness in a single term. We overcome both these drawbacks by employing a modified version of the Price equation first derived by Frank (1998):

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g_i} = \frac{1}{\overline{w}}\left[ {\mathrm{Cov}}(w_i,g'_i)\right] +{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_i) \end{aligned}$$
(8)

where \({g'}_i\) is the transmitted genetic value of the ith individual with respect to the character of interest, i.e. the average genetic value of its descendants in the next generation.

In our model, in which we assume that plasmids are transmitted with perfect fidelity from parent cells to daughter cells, \(g'_i\) can be identified with \({g}_i(t_T)\), the terminal genetic value of the ith individual at the end of its life-cycle (that is, at either the time of cell death or the time of cell division, depending on the organism’s fate). \(\Delta {g}_i\) can then be interpreted as the average change in an organism’s genetic value between the beginning and end of its own life-cycle, while \(\Delta \overline{g_i}\) can be interpreted as the change in the population mean of \(g\) during a single iteration of the life-cycle. Hence:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g_i} = \frac{1}{\overline{w}}\left[ {\mathrm{Cov}}(w_i,{g}_i(t_T))\right] +{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_i) \end{aligned}$$
(9)

This is a particularly useful version of the Price equation in a microbial context, and has been employed to this end in recent work by Mc Ginty et al. (2013).

Fitness function

In the Price formalism, the fitness of the ith individual \((w_i)\) is defined as its total contribution to the descendant population. In a discrete generations model, this is simply its total number of offspring. In our simple model, we can write this as a function of net viability, plus a residual component representing the deviation from expectation:

$$\begin{aligned} w_i=2\left( V-C_ig_{Xi}(t_A)+B\hat{g}_{Xi}(t_A)\right) +\epsilon \end{aligned}$$
(10)

As explained in the basic setup, the net viability of an organism depends on a baseline component plus the net payoff it receives in the social phase. This payoff in turn depends on the genetic values of itself and its social partner at the time of action; hence the genetic values in the fitness function should be evaluated at \(t_A\). Note that every organism will deviate from expectation one way or the other, since it determinately either will or will not divide, and consequently its realized value for \(w_i\) will be either 2 or 0. This is unproblematic, provided the deviation from expectation does not co-vary with genetic value.

The intergenerational change in the frequency of \(X\)

We can derive an expression for the intergenerational change in the frequency of plasmid \(X\) by substituting Eq. (10) into Eq. (9), yielding:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Xi} = \frac{2}{\overline{w}}\left[ -C{\mathrm{Cov}}(g_{Xi}(t_A),{g}_{Xi}(t_T)) +B{\mathrm{Cov}}(\hat{g}_{Xi}(t_A),{g}_{Xi}(t_T))\right] +{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Xi}) \end{aligned}$$
(11)

Note that both \(V\) and \(\epsilon\) have now dropped out of the analysis, because neither co-varies with genetic value. We can rearrange 11 as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Xi} = \frac{2}{\overline{w}}\left[ \left( rB -C\right) {\mathrm{Cov}}(g_{Xi}(t_A),{g}_{Xi}(t_T))\right] +{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Xi}) \end{aligned}$$
(12)

where \(r\) is identified with the following covariance ratio:

$$\begin{aligned} r=\frac{{\mathrm{Cov}}\left( g_{Xi}(t_T),\hat{g}_{Xi}(t_A)\right) }{{\mathrm{Cov}}\left( g_{Xi}(t_T), g_{Xi}(t_A)\right) } \end{aligned}$$
(13)

We can therefore see that the expression for the change in frequency of \(X\) contains a Hamilton’s rule-like component, albeit one that requires an unorthodox definition or \(r\) (more on this below). However, we can see that it also contains a separate, second component, \({\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Xi})\), which reflects the fact that \(X\) may also spread partly in virtue of its infectivity, irrespective of its effects on its hosts fitness (cf. Smith 2001; Giraud and Shykoff 2011).

The intergenerational change in the frequency of \(Y\)

The equation describing the change in frequency of plasmid \(Y\) is much simpler. \(Y\) has no fitness-relevant phenotypic effect on its host organism, and it is uncorrelated with the fitness-relevant plasmid \(X\). Consequently, the presence or absence of \(Y\) does not co-vary with \(w_i\). Hence \({\mathrm{Cov}}(w_i,{g}_{Yi}(t_T))=0\), and only the second term in our modified Price equation remains:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Yi} = {\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Yi}) \end{aligned}$$
(14)

This reflects the fact that \(Y\) is selectively neutral. If \(Y\) spreads, it can only be as a result of its infectivity.

When will \(X\) outperform \(Y\)?

By combining (12) with (14), we can obtain a condition under which the intergenerational change in the frequency of \(X\) is greater than the intergenerational change in the frequency of \(Y\):

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Xi}>\Delta \overline{g}_{Yi} \iff \frac{2}{\overline{w}}\left[ \left( rB -C\right) {\mathrm{Cov}}(g_{Xi}(t_A),{g}_{Xi}(t_T))\right] >{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Yi})-{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Xi}) \end{aligned}$$
(15)

If we assume that \(X\) and \(Y\) are initially equal in their frequency \((f_X=f_Y)\) and in their infectivity \((\lambda _X=\lambda _Y)\), it follows that \({\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Yi}) = {\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Xi})\). This leaves the following simplified condition:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Xi}>\Delta \overline{g}_{Yi} \iff \frac{2}{\overline{w}}\left[ \left( rB -C\right) {\mathrm{Cov}}(g_{Xi}(t_A),{g}_{Xi}(t_T))\right] >0 \end{aligned}$$
(16)

On the further but relatively mild assumption that \({\mathrm{Cov}}(g_{Xi}(t_A),{g}_{Xi}(t_T))>0\) (i.e. an organism’s genotype at the time of action co-varies positively with its genotype at the end of its life-cycle), we can derive a condition under which \(X\) will outperform \(Y\) that is closely analogous to Hamilton’s rule in its traditional form:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Xi}>\Delta \overline{g}_{Yi} \iff rB-C>0 \end{aligned}$$
(17)

This expression can be interpreted as a statement of the conditions under which a plasmid that encodes a social phenotype will outperform a plasmid that is identical in its infectivity but neutral with regard to its host’s fitness. Importantly, the significance of this result is not limited to cases in which two very similar plasmids are actually competing. More generally, the expression can be interpreted as a statement of the conditions under which encoding a social phenotype is evolutionarily advantageous for a plasmid in a two-player Prisoner’s Dilemma. If \(rB - C < 0\), then the actual spread of the plasmid will be slower than the rate that would have been observed if the plasmid had been phenotypically inert, so the plasmid gains no advantage by encoding the social phenotype. By contrast, if \(rB - C > 0\), then the plasmid will spread more rapidly than an otherwise identical but phenotypically inert plasmid would have done. In this situation, encoding the social phenotype is advantageous for the plasmid, despite the deleterious effect it has on the host.

The derivation of this condition could not proceed without the unorthodox definition of relatedness given in (13), on which \(r\) is defined a measure of the diachronic genetic similarity between actors at the time of action and recipients at the end of their life-cycle. Adopting this diachronic measure is therefore essential if we want to arrive at a Hamilton’s rule-like condition that describes when encoding a social phenotype is evolutionarily advantageous for a plasmid in this model. Essentially, this is because in this model the advantageousness (or otherwise) of encoding the social phenotype is largely dependent on the probability (\(\pi \lambda _X\)) that the plasmid responsible will be able to ‘jump ship’ to the recipient after causing the altruistic act. Our diachronic measure of \(r\), in contrast to more traditional measures, takes this ‘ship jumping’ phenomenon into account.

The dependence of \(r\) on \(\pi \lambda _X\)

To calculate the precise dependence of \(r\) on \(\pi \lambda _X\), we begin by re-writing our covariance ratio as a ratio of regression coefficients:

$$\begin{aligned} r=\frac{{\mathrm{Cov}}\left( {g_{Xi}}(t_T),{\hat{g}_i}(t_A)\right) }{{\mathrm{Cov}}\left( g_{Xi}(t_T), g_{Xi}(t_A)\right) }=\frac{\beta _{{\hat{g}_{Xi}}(t_A),{g_{Xi}}(t_T)}}{\beta _{g_{Xi}(t_A),{g_{Xi}}(t_T)}} \end{aligned}$$
(18)

We then compute the regression coefficients from the conditional expected values:

$$\begin{aligned} \beta _{{\hat{g}_{Xi}}(t_A),{g_{Xi}}(t_T)}={\mathrm{E}}(\hat{g}_{Xi}(t_A)|{g_{Xi}}(t_T)=1)-{\mathrm{E}}(\hat{g}_{Xi}(t_A)|{g_{Xi}}(t_T)=0)=\pi \lambda _X\end{aligned}$$
(19)
$$\beta _{{g_{{Xi}} (t_{A} ),g_{{Xi}} (t_{T} )}} = E(g_{{Xi}} (t_{A} )|g_{{Xi}} (t_{T} ) = 1) - E(g_{{Xi}} (t_{A} )|g_{{Xi}} (t_{T} ) = 0) = 1 - (1 - f_{X} )\pi \lambda _{X}$$
(20)

This yields:

$$\begin{aligned} r=\frac{\pi \lambda _X}{1-(1-f_X)\pi \lambda _X} \end{aligned}$$
(21)

From which we see that in this model, all else being equal, the diachronic assortment between altruists \((r)\) increases with increasing probability of conjugation between social partners after social interaction \((\pi )\) and with increasing probability of plasmid transmission when they conjugate \((\lambda _X)\).

Appendix 2: Diachronic relatedness in a public goods game

We turn now to a linear public goods game, a somewhat more realistic model of microbial cooperation. The analysis of this game largely parallels that of “Appendix 1”. The aim is to derive a diachronic version of the whole-group relatedness (Eq. (3) in the main text) that provides the best measure of \(r\) in models in which plasmid transfer follows public goods production.

Basic setup

Consider, then, an infinite population of asexually reproducing organisms sorted randomly into groups of size \(N\). As before, a fraction \(f_X\) of organisms bear a plasmid, \(X\), that reliably causes them to produce a public good, while a fraction \(f_Y\) bear a different plasmid, \(Y\), that has no fitness-relevant phenotypic effects on its host. Genetic values are defined as before.

At \(t_A\), the organisms play a linear public goods game. Bearers of \(X\) produce a marginal viability benefit, \(B\), that is shared evenly among the members of their social group. Each group member (including the producer) thus receives a total benefit \((G_{Xi}(t_A))B\), where \(G_{Xi}(t_A)\) is the local (within-group) frequency of public good producers at \(t_A\). Each producer incurs a viability cost \(C\) as a consequence of producing the public good.

As in the previous model, players may conjugate after the game. Each organism may conjugate at most once, and does so with probability \(\pi\). These conjugating pairs are drawn at random from the group, and it is assumed that \(N\) is sufficiently large the frequencies of various possible pairs match the background frequencies in the global population. During conjugation, a bearer of plasmid \(X\) will transmit the plasmid to its social partner (if it is initially a non-bearer) with transmission probability \(\lambda _X\). Correspondingly, a bearer of plasmid \(Y\) will transmit the plasmid to its social partner (if it is initially a non-bearer) with transmission probability \(\lambda _Y\).

There follows a global competition phase, in which all individuals compete for representation in the next generation of groups, and individuals are killed off with a probability equal to their net viability. Finally, at the end of the life-cycle, the surviving cells divide to produce the next generation. We again assume that all plasmids are transmitted from a parent cell to its daughter cells with perfect fidelity.

Because groups are formed randomly, there is no positive assortment between the group members at \(t_A\). We thus intuitively expect that public goods production will be undermined by free-riding, and that plasmids (such as \(X\)) that produce public goods will decrease in frequency at the expense of those (such as \(Y\)) that free-ride. Again, however, we find that allowing for the possibility of plasmid transfer after social interaction complicates the picture.

Equations for gene frequency change

As before, we take an appropriately rearranged Price equation as our starting point:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g_i} = \frac{1}{\overline{w}}\left[ {\mathrm{Cov}}(w_i,{g}_i(t_T))\right] +{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_i) \end{aligned}$$
(10)

The fitness function for this game is as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} w_i=2\left( V-C_ig_{Xi}(t_A)+BG_{Xi}(t_A)\right) +\epsilon \end{aligned}$$
(22)

Substituting (22) into (9), we obtain:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Xi} = \frac{2}{\overline{w}}\left[ -C{\mathrm{Cov}}(g_{Xi}(t_A),{g}_i(t_T)) +B{\mathrm{Cov}}(G_{Xi}(t_A),{g}_{Xi}(t_T))\right] +{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Xi}) \end{aligned}$$
(23)

which can be re-written as:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Xi} = \frac{2}{\overline{w}}\left[ \left( r_GB -C\right) {\mathrm{Cov}}(g_{Xi}(t_A),{}_{Xi}(t_T))\right] +{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Xi}) \end{aligned}$$
(24)

where \(r_G\) is now identified with the following covariance ratio:

$$\begin{aligned} r_G=\frac{{\mathrm{Cov}}\left( g_{Xi}(t_T),G_{Xi}(t_A)\right) }{{\mathrm{Cov}}\left( g_{Xi}(t_T), g_{Xi}(t_A)\right) } \end{aligned}$$
(25)

Plainly, this covariance ratio is very similar to that given in Eq. (13); the only difference is that a whole-group genetic value has replaced the social partner’s genetic value in the numerator. The relationship between these covariance ratios is thus closely analogous to the relationship between the ‘whole-group relatedness’ (3) and the standard ‘others-only’ regression measure of \(r\) (2). We can think of the above ratio as a diachronic variant of the whole-group relatedness, designed to accommodate the effects of gene mobility occuring after social interaction.

Plasmid \(Y\), as before, is phenotypically inert, so its change in frequency is again given simply by:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Yi} = {\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Yi}) \end{aligned}$$
(26)

When will \(X\) outperform \(Y\)?

From here on, the analysis is virtually identical to that of “Appendix 1”. Combining (24) with (26), we see that \(X\) outperforms \(Y\) in this model under the following conditions:

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Xi}>\Delta \overline{g}_{Yi} \iff \frac{2}{\overline{w}}\left[ \left( r_GB -C\right) {\mathrm{Cov}}(g_{Xi}(t_A),{g}_{Xi}(t_T))\right] >{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Yi})-{\mathrm{E}}(\Delta g_{Xi}) \end{aligned}$$
(27)

In the special case in which plasmids \(X\) and \(Y\) are equal in their frequency and in their degree of infectivity, and on the further assumption that \({\mathrm{Cov}}\left( G_{Xi}(t_T),G_{Xi}(t_A)\right) >0\) (i.e. a social group’s average genetic value at \(t_A\) co-varies positively with its average genetic value at the end of the life-cycle), we can again derive a Hamilton’s rule-like condition under which \(X\) will be selectively favoured over \(Y\):

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta \overline{g}_{Xi}>\Delta \overline{g}_{Yi} \iff r_GB-C>0 \end{aligned}$$
(28)

This expression can be interpreted as a statement of the conditions under which encoding public goods production is evolutionarily advantageous for a plasmid in a public goods game. If \(r_GB - C < 0\), then the actual spread of the plasmid will be slower than the rate that would have been observed if the plasmid had been phenotypically inert, so the plasmid gains no advantage by encoding the social phenotype. By contrast, if \(r_GB - C > 0\), then the plasmid will spread more rapidly than an otherwise identical but phenotypically inert plasmid would have done. In this situation, producing the public good is advantageous for the plasmid, despite the deleterious effect it has on the host.

As before, the derivation of this result relies on our adopting an unorthodox, diachronic definition of \(r\). This time, \(r\) quantifies the fraction of the overall diachronic covariance between genotypes at \(t_A\) and genotypes at \(t_T\) that can be accounted for by covariance between the earlier and later group genetic values. It is a natural extension of the ‘whole-group relatedness’ to the diachronic case, and this extension is needed in order to capture the diachronic genetic correlations between group members generated after the social phase by plasmid transfer.

The dependence of \(r_G\) on \(\pi \lambda _X\)

When (as in our model) all groups are of equal size \(N\), there is a close relationship between the whole-group relatedness and the standard (‘others-only’) regression definition (Pepper 2000):

$$\begin{aligned} r_G=\frac{1+(N-1)r}{N} \end{aligned}$$
(29)

The same relationship holds between our modified diachronic measures for the whole-group and standard (‘others-only’) relatedness (i.e. (25) and (13) respectively).

In our model, each organism conjugates once (at most) with a randomly selected member of its randomly formed group, and \(N\) is sufficiently large that the frequencies of the various types of pair in each group match the background frequencies in the population. Consequently, we can treat these pairs as if they had been drawn at random from the global population. The probability that they conjugate successfully is \(\pi\), and the probability that an \(X\)-bearer will transfer \(X\) in this event is \(\lambda _X\). Given these assumptions, the value of \(r\) will be the same as it was in the previous game. We can therefore combine (21) with (29) to obtain an expression for \(r_G\):

$$\begin{aligned} r_G=\frac{1+(N-1)({\pi \lambda _X}/{(1-\pi \lambda _X(1-f_X)))}}{N} \end{aligned}$$
(30)

This shows that, all else being equal, increasing \(\pi\) or \(\lambda _X\) increases the diachronic whole-group relatedness at the plasmid locus.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Birch, J. Gene mobility and the concept of relatedness. Biol Philos 29, 445–476 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9445-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9445-z

Keyword

Navigation