Skip to main content
Log in

On some oligarchy results when social preference is fuzzy

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We consider a model in which individual preferences are orderings of social states, but the social preference relation is fuzzy. We motivate interest in the model by presenting a version of the strong Pareto rule that is suited to the setting of a fuzzy social preference. We prove a general oligarchy theorem under the assumption that this fuzzy relation is quasi-transitive. The framework allows us to make a distinction between a “strong” and a “weak” oligarchy, and our theorem identifies when the oligarchy must be strong and when it can be weak. Weak oligarchy need not be undesirable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Intuitively, a quasi-transitive preference relation is one where the strict preference relation is transitive, whereas the indifference relation need not be. An acyclic relation is one with no cycles in the strict preference relation. A Suzumura consistent relation rules out not only strict preference cycles, but all cycles that involve at least one strict preference. Acyclicity is the weakest concept of the three. Suzumura consistency and quasi-transitivity are logically independent.

  2. Gibbard’s paper was written in the 1969–1970 academic year but remained unpublished until Gibbard (2014). An introduction to the paper is given by Weymark (2014).

  3. A collective choice rule is a function that takes a profile of preference orderings as its input (one ordering for each individual) and produces a social preference relation as its output.

  4. The idea that preferences can be numerically valued (or “fuzzy”) has, of course, been considered before. A sample of the literature is Orlovsky (1978), Ovchinnikov (1981), Basu (1984), Billot (1995), Dutta et al. (1986), Dutta (1987), Ponsard (1990), Dasgupta and Deb (1991, 1996, 2001), Ovchinnikov and Roubens (1992) and Banerjee (1993, 1994). Salles (1998) surveys the field and Piggins and Salles (2007) discuss some underlying philosophical issues.

  5. Formally, let \(n(xP_{i}y)\) denote the number of people who strictly prefer x to y. Then, under this rule, \(p(x,y)=\frac{n(xP_{i}y)}{n(xP_{i}y)+n(yP_{i}x)}.\) If everyone is indifferent between x and y then we set \(p(x,y)=1\).

  6. A simple proof of Gibbard’s theorem is given by Piggins (2017).

  7. Barrett and Salles (2011) survey the field. A sample of the literature is Barrett et al. (1986), Dutta (1987), Ovchinnikov (1991), Banerjee (1994), Billot (1995), Richardson (1998), Dasgupta and Deb (1999), García-Lapresta and Llamazares (2000, 2001), Fono and Andjiga (2005), Perote-Peña and Piggins (2007), Duddy et al. (2010, 2011) and Gibilisco et al. (2014). See also Leclerc (1984, 1991) and Leclerc and Monjardet (1995). Note that our model bears some formal similarities with the interesting framework of sophisticated social welfare functions introduced by Sanver and Selçuk (2009). They interpret the values assigned to ordered pairs of distinct alternatives as a measure of the “weight” by which one alternative is strictly preferred to another. They assume that, for all distinct x and y, the weight of preference for x vs. y plus the weight of preference for y vs. x must sum to one. We do not assume that any adding-up constraint holds for our central theorem. Further, our formulation of transitivity differs. In our fuzzy model, we assume that social preferences are “max-star” transitive. This assumption, in fact, admits a range of different possible transitivity conditions as special cases. The fact that this family of cases can be partitioned into two parts is central to our characterization theorem.

  8. The proportional rule satisfies unrestricted domain, independence of irrelevant alternatives, and the Pareto principle.

  9. Note that Barrett et al. (1986) use a fuzzy strict social preference relation as their primitive concept, not a weak one. The transitivity condition they use is Condition 2.3 in their paper.

  10. One possible objection to the proportional rule is that it does not agree with the majority rule at profiles where the latter is transitive.

  11. If X is an arbitrary set then a fuzzy relation is a function \(t:X\times X\rightarrow [0,1]\). We say that t is connected if \(t(x,y)+t(y,x)\ge 1\) for all \(x,y\in X\). Note that the only time we assume connectedness in our results section (Sect. 3) is in Corollary 6 and Corollary 8. In the literature, a related condition called “reciprocity” is often assumed (see De Baets et al. 2006; Llamazares et al. 2013). This condition says that \(t(x,y)+t(y,x)=1\) for all \(x,y\in X\). This condition is stronger than connectedness and is natural in models of preference intensity. However, we are not using fuzzy set theory here to model the intensity of preference, but rather the degree of truth. In the intensity literature, if x and y are socially indifferent then we would have \(t(x,y)=t(y,x)=\frac{1}{2}\). However, for us, indifference means that it is true that x is at least as good as y, and true that y is at least as good as x. Hence, \(t(x,y)=t(y,x)=1.\)

  12. Interesting characterizations of some approaches to factorization are contained in Llamazares (2005).

  13. Note that Banerjee’s method of factorization satisfies (C) only if connectedness of r is assumed.

  14. Klement et al. (2000) is a comprehensive survey of triangular norms.

  15. The role of these concepts in judgment aggregation is explored in Duddy and Piggins (2013). In Duddy et al. (2011) we considered these concepts with respect to a fuzzy version of Arrow’s theorem. In the current paper, we are concerned with Weymark’s theorem, not Arrow’s. Additionally, in our earlier paper we used a stronger version of the independence condition. The version we use here is weaker than that one, and is closer to the standard version employed in social choice theory.

  16. The independence condition in Barrett, Pattanaik and Salles (1986, p. 4), Dutta (1987, p. 222) and Banerjee (1994, p. 125) is equivalent to ours under the assumption of crisp individual preferences. Translating the independence condition of Duddy et al. (2011) into the setting of this paper yields: For all \(x,y\in X\) and all \((R_{1},...,R_{n}),(R_{1}',...,R_{n}')\in D\), \([xR_{i}y\leftrightarrow xR'_{i}y]\) for all \(i\in N\) implies \(r(x,y)=r'(x,y)\). To see the difference between the two formulations, consider the following collective choice rule. Suppose there are two people and one strictly prefers x to y, the other y to x. A natural outcome is a tie, i.e. \(r(x,y)=r(y,x)=1\). However, if the first person is indifferent then the natural outcome is to let the second break the tie, i.e. \(r(x,y)=0\) and \(r(y,x)=1\). Our original formulation prohibits this since each person’s \(xR_{i}y\) preference is the same in both profiles. This problem does not arise under our new formulation.

  17. The \(wP_{i}x\rightarrow wP'_{i}z\) direction comes from the preceding sentence. The \(wP_{i}'z\rightarrow wP_{i}x\) direction comes from taking the contrapositive of \(xP_{i}w\rightarrow zP'_{i}w\) (which again appears in the preceding sentence).

  18. The idea of a pivotal voter originates with Barberà (1980). This technique has been used in various proofs of Arrow’s theorem, e.g. Geanakoplos (2005) and Perote-Peña and Piggins (2002). We use the same technique here to prove the existence of an oligarchy.

  19. The proof of this is straightforward.

References

  • Arrow KJ (1963) Social choice and individual values. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee A (1993) Rational choice under fuzzy preferences: the Orlovsky choice function. Fuzzy Sets Syst 53:295–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee A (1994) Fuzzy preferences and Arrow-type problems in social choice. Soc Choice Welf 11:121–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banks JS (1995) Acyclic social choice from finite sets. Soc Choice Welf 12:293–310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S (1980) Pivotal voters: a new proof of Arrow’s theorem. Econ Lett 6:13–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett CR, Pattanaik PK, Salles M (1986) On the structure of fuzzy social welfare functions. Fuzzy Sets Syst 19:1–10

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett R, Salles M (2011) Social choice with fuzzy preferences. In: Arrow KJ, Sen A, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of social choice and welfare, vol 2. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 367–389

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Basu K (1984) Fuzzy revealed preference. J Econ Theory 32:212–227

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Billot A (1995) Economic theory of fuzzy equilibria. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blair DH, Pollak RA (1982) Acyclic collective choice rules. Econometrica 50:931–943

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert W, Suzumura K (2008) A characterization of consistent collective choice rules. J Econ Theory 138:311–320

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert W, Suzumura K (2010) Consistency, choice, and rationality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown DJ (1975) Aggregation of preferences. Quart J Econ 89:456–469

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta M, Deb R (1991) Fuzzy choice functions. Soc Choice Welf 8:171–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta M, Deb R (1996) Transitivity and fuzzy preferences. Soc Choice Welf 13:305–318

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta M, Deb R (1999) An impossibility theorem with fuzzy preferences. In: de Swart H (ed) Logic, game theory and social choice: proceedings of the international conference, LGS ’99, May 13-16, 1999. Tilburg University Press, pp 482–490

  • Dasgupta M, Deb R (2001) Factoring fuzzy transitivity. Fuzzy Sets Syst 118:489–502

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Baets B, De Meyer H, De Schuymer B, Jenei S (2006) Cyclic evaluation of transitivity of reciprocal relations. Soc Choice Welf 26:217–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duddy C, Perote-Peña J, Piggins A (2010) Manipulating an aggregation rule under ordinally fuzzy preferences. Soc Choice Welf 34:411–428

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duddy C, Perote-Peña J, Piggins A (2011) Arrow’s theorem and max-star transitivity. Soc Choice Welf 36:25–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duddy C, Piggins A (2013) Many-valued judgment aggregation: characterizing the possibility/impossibility boundary. J Econ Theory 148:793–805

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta B (1987) Fuzzy preferences and social choice. Math Soc Sci 13:215–229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta B, Panda SC, Pattanaik PK (1986) Exact choice and fuzzy preferences. Math Soc Sci 11:53–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fono LA, Andjiga NG (2005) Fuzzy strict preference and social choice. Fuzzy Sets Syst 155:372–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • García-Lapresta JL, Llamazares B (2000) Aggregation of fuzzy preferences: some rules of the mean. Soc Choice Welf 17:673–690

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • García-Lapresta JL, Llamazares B (2001) Majority decisions based on difference of votes. J Math Econ 35:463–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geanakoplos J (2005) Three brief proofs of Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Econ Theor 26:211–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (2014) Intransitive social indifference and the Arrow dilemma. Rev Econ Design 18:3–10

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibilisco MB, Gowen AM, Albert KE, Mordeson JN, Wierman MJ, Clark TD (2014) Fuzzy social choice theory. Springer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Klement EP, Mesiar R, Pap E (2000) Triangular norms. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leclerc B (1984) Efficient and binary consensus functions on transitively valued relations. Math Soc Sci 8:45–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leclerc B (1991) Aggregation of fuzzy preferences: a theoretic Arrow-like approach. Fuzzy Sets Syst 43:291–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leclerc B, Monjardet B (1995) Lattical theory of consensus. In: Barnett W, Moulin H, Salles M, Schofield N (eds) Social choice, welfare and ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 145–162

    Google Scholar 

  • Llamazares B (2005) Factorization of fuzzy preferences. Soc Choice Welf 24:475–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Llamazares B, Pérez-Asurmendi P, García-Lapresta JL (2013) Collective transitivity in majorities based on difference in support. Fuzzy Sets Syst 216:3–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell A, Sonnenschein H (1972) General possibility theorems for group decisions. Rev Econ Stud 39:185–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orlovsky SA (1978) Decision-making with a fuzzy preference relation. Fuzzy Sets Syst 1:155–167

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ovchinnikov SV (1981) Structure of fuzzy binary relations. Fuzzy Sets Syst 6:169–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ovchinnikov SV (1991) Social choice and Lukasiewicz logic. Fuzzy Sets Syst 43:275–289

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ovchinnikov SV, Roubens M (1992) On fuzzy strict preference, indifference and incomparability relations. Fuzzy Sets Syst 49:15–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perote-Peña J, Piggins A (2002) Geometry and impossibility. Econ Theor 20:831–836

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perote-Peña J, Piggins A (2007) Strategy-proof fuzzy aggregation rules. J Math Econ 43:564–580

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piggins A (2017) Sen’s proofs of the Arrow and Gibbard theorems. Econ Lett 161:99–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piggins A, Salles M (2007) Instances of indeterminacy. Analyse und Kritik 29:311–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plott CR (1973) Path independence, rationality, and social choice. Econometrica 41:1075–1091

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ponsard C (1990) Some dissenting views on the transitivity of individual preference. Ann Oper Res 23:279–288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson G (1998) The structure of fuzzy preferences: social choice implications. Soc Choice Welf 15:359–369

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salles M (1998) Fuzzy utility. In: Barberà S, Hammond PJ, Seidl C (eds) Handbook of utility theory, vol.1: principles, vol 1. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 321–344

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanver MR, Selçuk Ö (2009) Sophisticated preference aggregation. Soc Choice Welf 33:73–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1969) Quasi-transitivity, rational choice and collective decisions. Rev Econ Stud 36:381–393

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1970) Collective choice and social welfare. Holden-Day, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Weymark JA (1984) Arrow’s theorem with social quasi-orderings. Pub Choice 42:235–246

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weymark JA (2014) An introduction to Allan Gibbard’s oligarchy theorem paper. Rev Econ Design 18:1–2

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ashley Piggins.

Additional information

We are grateful to participants at the 13th Meeting of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare, in particular Christian List and Bill Zwicker, for their helpful comments on this paper. We also thank the Managing Editor, Clemens Puppe, the Associate Editor, and two anonymous referees for their comments on the original version of this paper. Financial support from the Irish Research Council for the Humanities and Social Sciences co-funding from the European Commission, and from the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness through MEC/FEDER Grant ECO2013-44483-P is gratefully acknowledged.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Duddy, C., Piggins, A. On some oligarchy results when social preference is fuzzy. Soc Choice Welf 51, 717–735 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-018-1134-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-018-1134-4

Navigation