Skip to main content
Log in

Single-dipped preferences with satiation: strong group strategy-proofness and unanimity

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We study the problem of the location of a public facility that generates negative externalities. We consider that agents have single-dipped preferences with satiation: each agent considers a location as the worst, the “dip”, and the farther the location is from the dip, the better for the agent. In addition, an agent might be indifferent between all the locations sufficiently far from his dip, reaching his highest level of satisfaction. We characterize the family of strongly group strategy-proof and unanimous rules. Opposite to previous results without satiation, the locations selected are not necessarily at the extremes of the alternatives’ space.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Another interpretation is as follows: apply the consensus rule, \( C^{d}(R)\), proposed by Manjunath (2014). This will select \(b\in \{0,T\}\). If there exist an alternative a that Pareto-dominates b, then choose a.

  2. In our case, the default d corresponds to the bias b.

References

  • Barberà S, Berga D, Moreno B (2010) Individual versus group strategy-proofness: when do they coincide? J Econ Theory 145:1648–1674

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S, Berga D, Moreno B (2012a) Domains, ranges and strategy-proofness: the case of single-dipped preferences. Soc Choice Welf 39:335–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S, Berga D, Moreno B (2012b) Group strategy-proof social choice functions with binary ranges and arbitrary domains: characterization results. Int J Game Theory 41:791–808

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogomolnaia A, Nicolò A (2005) Stable assignment of public facilities under congestion. J Public Econ Theory 7:65–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bossert W, Peters H (2012) Single-plateaued choice. Working Paper, Maastricht Research School of Economics of Tecnhology and Organization

  • Cantala D (2004) Choosing the level of a public good when agents have an outside option. Soc Choice Welf 22:491–514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehlers L (2002) Multiple public goods and lexicographic preferences: replacement principle. J Math Econ 37:1–15

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ehlers L (2003) Mutiple public goods, lexicographic preferences and single-plateaued preferences rules. Games Econ Behav 43:1–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freudenberg W, Pastor S (1992) NIMBYs and LULUs: stalking the syndromes. J Soc Issues 48:36–61

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (1973) Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result. Econometrica 41:587–601

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manjunath V (2014) Efficient and strategy-proof social choice when preferences are single-dipped. Int J Game Theory 43:579–597

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1980) On strategy-proofness and single-peakedness. Public Choice 35:437–455

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Öztürk M, Peters H, Storcken T (2012) Strategy-proof location of a public Bad on a Disc., Working Paper, Maastricht Research School of Economics of Tecnhology and Organization

  • Satterthwaite M (1975) Strategy-proofness and arrow’s conditions: existence and correspondence theorems for voting procedures and social welfare functions. J Econ Theory 10:187–217

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank our PhD advisors, Jordi Massó and Salvador Barberà for their patience, inspiration, and to all comments we received along these years. Special thanks to William Thomson and two anonymous refereers for their suggestions and comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Grisel Ayllón.

Appendix

Appendix

Lemma 1

Let \(b\in \{0,T\}\) and \(R\in {\mathcal {R}}_{D}^{n}\) be such that \(U(R)=\emptyset \). If \(E(b;R)\not =\emptyset \), then \(\#E(b;R)=1\).

Proof

Let \(b=0\) and \(R\in {\mathcal {R}}_{D}^{n}\) be such that \( U(R)=\emptyset \) and \(E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \). Then, there exists at least one alternative \(a\in P(R)\), such that \(aR_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N\) and \( aP_{j}0\) for some \(j\in N\). Since \(U(R)=\emptyset \), then \( N_{0}(R)\not =\emptyset \) and \(N_{T}(R)\not =\emptyset \). By definition \( 0\not \in E(0;R)\).

First, take any \(i\in N_{0}(R)\). By definition, \(0P_{i}T\) and any \(x\in [0,l(R_{i})]\) is such that \(xI_{i}0\), and any \(k\in (l(R_{i}),T]\) is such that \(0P_{i}k\). Hence, no alternative \(k^{\prime }\in (l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)}),T]\) belongs to E(0; R). As \(E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \) and \(0\not \in E(0;R)\), \(E(0;R)\subseteq (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\). Hence, any alternative \(a\in E(0;R)\) is such that \(aI_{i}0\) for each \(i\in N_{0}(R).\)

Second, take any \(i\in N_{T}(R)\). Then, \(TP_{i}0\) and any alternative \(y\in [h(R_{i}),T]\) is such that \(yP_{i}0\). Notice that for each \(i\in N_{T}(R)\), \(\max W(0;R_{i})=cI_{i}0\) and any \(w\in \) \(W(0;R_{i})\diagdown \{c\}\) is such that \(0P_{i}w\). Hence, for every agent \(i\in N_{T}(R)\) it should be that if \(a\in E(0;R)\), then \(a\in [c,T]\). Therefore, \( E(0;R)\subseteq [\overline{c}(R),T]\).

If \(N_{0T}(R)=\emptyset \) and as \(U(R)=\emptyset \), then \( l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})<h_{max}(R_{N_{T}(R)})\). Furthermore, \(E(0;R)\subseteq (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\cap [\overline{c}(R),T]\). As it should be that for all \(i\in N_{0}(R),a\in E(0;R)\) is such that \(aI_{i}0\), then it can not be that an alternative \(z\in (h_{max}(R_{N_{T}(R)}),T]\) belongs to E(0; R), because \(0P_{i}z\) for any \(i\in N_{0}(R)\). Therefore, \(\overline{c} (R)\le l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\ \)and \(E(0;R)\subseteq (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\).

We can distinguish between two cases:

Case (i) \(\overline{c}(R)<\) \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\). By definition, \( a>b>d(R_{i})\) implies that \(aP_{i}bP_{i}d(R_{i})\). Hence, for any alternative \(x>\overline{c}(R)\) it is that \(xR_{i}\overline{c}(R)\) for each \( i\in N_{T}(R)\) and \(xP_{j}\overline{c}(R)\) for some \(j\in N_{T}(R)\). Then, \( l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})R_{i}\overline{c}(R)P_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N_{T}(R)\) and \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})P_{j}\overline{c}(R)P_{i}0\) for some \(j\in N_{T}(R)\). Furthermore, \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})I_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N_{0}(R)\). Any other alternative \(y\in (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)}))\) is such that \( l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})P_{i}y\) for some \(i\in N_{T}(R)\); hence \(y\not \in P(R)\). We conclude that \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})=E(0;R)\) (Fig. 9).

Fig. 9
figure 9

\(E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \), \(N_{0T}(R)=\emptyset \), and \(\overline{c} (R)< l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\)

Case (ii) \(\overline{c}(R)=l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\). Then \( (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\cap [\overline{c}(R),T]=\) \(E(0;R)=\overline{ c}(R)=l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\) (Fig. 10).

Fig. 10
figure 10

\(E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \), \(N_{0T}(R)=\emptyset \), and \(\overline{c} (R)=\) \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\)

Suppose that \(N_{0T}(R)\not =\emptyset \). Then, \(i\in N_{0T}(R)\) it should be that \(0I_{i}T\) and any \(x\in [0,l(R_{i})]\cup [h(R_{i}),T]\) is such that \(xI_{i}0\), and any \(y\in (l(R_{i}),h(R_{i}))\) is such that \( 0P_{i}y\). Hence, no alternative \(y\in (l(R_{i}),h(R_{i}))\) belongs to E(0; R). Then, for any \(a\in E(0;R)\) and any \(i\in N_{0T}(R)\) it should be that \(aI_{i}0\). Hence, \(E(0;R)\subseteq U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\diagdown \{0\}\) and \([0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})]\cup [h_{max}(R_{N_{0T}(R)}),T]\subseteq U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\).

Adding up, when \(N_{0T}(R)\not =\emptyset \), \(N_{0}(R)\not =\emptyset \) and \( N_{T}(R)\not =\emptyset \), then \(E(0;R)\subseteq (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\cap [\overline{c}(R),T]\cap U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\). In such case, we distinguish between two cases:

Case (iii) \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\le l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\). For any \(a\in E(0;R)\) it should be that \(aI_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N_{0}(R)\cup N_{0T}(R)\). Any alternative \(x\in (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\) accomplishes this latter condition. Furthermore, any \(y\in U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\diagdown [0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\) is such that \(0P_{i}y\) for all \(i\in N_{0}(R)\) although \(0I_{i}y\) for all \(i\in N_{0T}(R)\). As \(E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \), \( N_{0}(R)\not =\emptyset \), and \(N_{T}(R)\not =\emptyset \), \(\overline{c} (R)\le l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})<T\). Hence \(E(0;R)\subseteq (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\). By definition, \(a>b>d(R_{i})\) implies \( aP_{i}bP_{i}d(R_{i})\). Since \(d(R_{i})\le \overline{c}(R)\le \) \( l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\), for any \(i\in N_{T}(R)\) and any alternative \(e> \overline{c}(R)\), \(eP_{i}\overline{c}(R)\). Furthermore \(\overline{c} (R)R_{i}0 \) for all \(i\in N_{T}(R)\) and \(\overline{c}(R)P_{j}0\) for some \( j\in N_{T}(R)\). Then, \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})P_{i}\overline{c}(R)P_{i}0\) for some \(i\in N_{T}(R)\) and \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})R_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N\). We conclude that \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})=E(0;R)\) (Fig. 11).

Fig. 11
figure 11

\(E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \), \(N_{0T}(R)\not =\emptyset \), and \( l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\le l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\)

Fig. 12
figure 12

\(E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \), \(N_{0T}(R)\not =\emptyset \), and \( l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})>l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\). There is no alternative \(x\in U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) such that \(x\in (l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)}),l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\)

Case (iv) \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})>l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\). For any \(a\in E(0;R) \) it should be that \(aI_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N_{0}(R)\cup N_{0T}(R)\). Any alternative \(x\in (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})]\) accomplishes this latter condition, however, it is not the unique interval with this property. There might exist a preference profile \(R\in {\mathcal {R}}_{D}^{n}\) where there exist an interval \([h(R_{j}),l(R_{j^{\prime }})]\) for \(j,j^{\prime }\in N_{0T}(R)\), \(j\not =j^{\prime }\) such that any alternative \(y\in [h(R_{j}),l(R_{j^{\prime }})]\) is such that \(y\not \in (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)}))\) and \(yI_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N_{0}(R)\cup N_{0T}(R)\). This opens the possibility of three subcases:

(iv.a) There is no alternative \(x\in U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) such that \(x\in (l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)}),l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\). Hence, for any \( y\in (l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)}),l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\) it is that \(0R_{i}y\) for all \(i\in N_{0T}(R)\) and \(0P_{j}y\) for some \(j\in N_{0T}(R)\). Hence, \( y\not \in E(0;R)\). Furthermore, any alternative \(z\in (l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)}),T]\) is such that \(0R_{i}z\) for all \(i\in N_{T}(R)\) and \(0P_{j}z\) for some \(j\in N_{T}(R)\). Hence, \(z\not \in E(0;R)\). Therefore, any \(a\in E(0;R)\) should be such that \(a\in [\overline{c} (R),l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})]\). Since \(d(R_{i})\le \overline{c}(R)\le \) \( l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\), for any \(i\in N_{T}(R)\) and any alternative \(e\ge \overline{c}(R)\), \(eR_{i}\overline{c}(R)\) and \(eP_{j}\overline{c}(R)\) for some \(j\in N_{T}(R)\). Then, \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})P_{i}\overline{c} (R)P_{i}0 \) for some \(i\in N_{T}(R)\) and \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})R_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N\). We conclude that \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})=E(0;R)\) (Fig. 12).

Fig. 13
figure 13

\(E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \), \(N_{0T}(R)\not =\emptyset \), and \( l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})>l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\). There is no \(l(R_{j^{\prime }})\in U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) for \(j^{\prime }\in N_{0T}(R)\) such that \(l(R_{j^{\prime }})>l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\)

Fig. 14
figure 14

\(E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \), \(N_{0T}(R)\not =\emptyset \), and \( l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})>l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\). There exist \(l(R_{j^{\prime }})\in U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) for \(j^{\prime }\in N_{0T}(R)\) such that \(l(R_{j^{\prime }})\ge l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\)

(iv.b) There exists an alternative \(x\in U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) such that \(x\in (l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)}),l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\) and there is no interval \([h(R_{j}),l(R_{j^{\prime }})]\subset U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) for \( j,j^{\prime }\in N_{0T}(R)\) such that \(l(R_{j^{\prime }})>l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})>h(R_{j})>l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\). First, notice that \(x\not =l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\) as there is no a unanimous interval for \( N_{0T}(R)\) that includes that alternative. Furthermore, as any \(a\in E(0;R)\) should accomplish that \(aI_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N_{0}(R)\cup N_{0T}(R)\), then \(a\in (0,l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)}))\). As \(N_{T}(R)\not =\emptyset \), then \(a\in [\overline{c}(R),l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)}))\). Let \(\overline{l} (R_{N_{0T}(R)})=\underset{i\in N_{0T}(R)}{\max }\{\max l(R_{i}):l(R_{i})\in U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) and \(l(R_{i})<l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\}\). As \( E(0;R)\not =\emptyset \) it should be that \(\overline{l}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\ge \overline{c}(R)\), otherwise there is no alternative \(y\in [\overline{c}(R),l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)}))\) such that \(yI_{i}0\) for any \(i\in N_{0T}(R)\). Adding up, \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})>\overline{l}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\ge \overline{c }(R)\le l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) and any \(a\in E(0;R)\) is such that \(a\in [\overline{l}(R_{N_{0T}(R)}),l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)}))\). However, no alternative \(z\in (\overline{l}(R_{N_{0T}(R)}),l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)}))\) belongs to \(U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\). Hence, we conclude that \(\overline{l} (R_{N_{0T}(R)})=E(0;R)\) (Fig. 13).

(iv.c) There exists an alternative \(x\in U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) such that \(x\in (l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)}),l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})]\) and there is an interval \([h(R_{j}),l(R_{j^{\prime }})]\subset U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) for \( j,j^{\prime }\in N_{0T}(R)\) such that \(l(R_{j^{\prime }})\ge l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})>l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})>h(R_{j})\). First, notice that \( h(R_{j})\not =l_{min}(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) and that \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})I_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N_{0T}(R)\cup N_{0}(R)\). For any \(a\in E(0;R)\) it should be that \(aI_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N_{0T}(R)\cup N_{0}(R)\), hence, \(a\in U(R_{N_{0T}(R)})\) and \(a\le l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\). As \(N_{T}(R)\not = \emptyset \), \(a\ge \overline{c}(R);\) therefore \(\overline{c}(R)\le l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\). In particular, \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})R_{i}0\) for all \(i\in N_{T}(R)\) and \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})P_{j}0\) for some \(j\in N_{T}(R)\). By definition, for any other alternative y such that \( d(R_{i})<y<l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\), there exists an agent \(i^{\prime }\in N_{T}(R)\) such that \(l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})P_{i^{\prime }}y\). Hence, we conclude that \(E(0;R)=l_{min}(R_{N_{0}(R)})\) (Fig. 14).

A symmetric argument can be used for the case where \(U(R)=\emptyset \) and \( E(T;R)\not =\emptyset \). \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ayllón, G., Caramuta, D.M. Single-dipped preferences with satiation: strong group strategy-proofness and unanimity. Soc Choice Welf 47, 245–264 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0957-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-016-0957-0

Navigation