Skip to main content
Log in

Topological connectedness and behavioral assumptions on preferences: a two-way relationship

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper offers a comprehensive treatment of the question as to whether a binary relation can be consistent (transitive) without being decisive (complete), or decisive without being consistent, or simultaneously inconsistent or indecisive, in the presence of a continuity hypothesis that is, in principle, non-testable. It identifies topological connectedness of the (choice) set over which the continuous binary relation is defined as being crucial to this question. Referring to the two-way relationship as the Eilenberg–Sonnenschein (ES) research program, it presents four synthetic, and complete, characterizations of connectedness and its natural extensions and two consequences that stem from it. The six theorems make connections that have eluded decision theory and thereby generalize the pioneering work of Eilenberg, Sonnenschein, Schmeidler and Sen. We draw the relevance to several applied contexts, as well as to ongoing theoretical work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The first sentence is taken from p. 298, and the second from p. 367 in Sen (2017). Sen fills the ellipsis in the first by referring to Molière, and in the second, by the Aristotelian counsel that one aspire to as much precision as the subject deserves.

  2. See, for example, Barten and Böhm (1982), a useful survey but one that misses the connections that we emphasize here. The properties of the binary relation referred to below constitute standard textbook material, as in Barten and Böhm (1982) or Sen (2017) for example, but precise definitions are spelt out for the reader’s convenience in the section to follow.

  3. We may point out here that Sonnenschein (1965) is an elaboration of his Ph.D. dissertation that dispensed with Eilenberg’s requirement that the binary relation be antisymmetric, that preferences not be constrained by the requirement of singleton indifference sets. We return to this point in the sequel.

  4. We return to this theorem below.

  5. Finite-dimensional Euclidean spaces, the simplex of (objective) lotteries over a finite set and infinite-dimensional topological vector spaces are some of the most obvious examples.

  6. This remains professional folk wisdom: see for example page 80 (last paragraph) in Gilboa (2009).

  7. We return to Wakker’s words, and to Narens (1985), in Sect. 4.1 below.

  8. As is well known, this aspect of Eilenberg’s paper was taken up by Debreu (1954).

  9. There is some irony in that we extend Sen’s work in a direction that he explicitly wanted to avoid. He criticizes the literature’s “ overwhelming concern with transitivity and continuity,” and referring to his results, writes how they are “derived without any assumption of continuity and related conditions as these conditions might not be very realistic for certain problems of rational choice, especially in dealing with social decisions.”

  10. This is nothing but a loose summary sentence of the ideas explicated in the four paragraphs above. We shall reserve the term “foundational” for the results enumerated in the second paragraph above.

  11. For a precise statement, see (a) \(\Rightarrow \) (b) in Theorem 1 and its detailed discussion encapsulated in Proposition 1 below.

  12. We do not mean to overemphasize the novelty: a cursory reference to Wilder (1949), or to Dugundji (1966), shows that spaces with finitely many components are well known and studied extensively. The reader should beware, however, that k-connectedness is used in algebraic topology with a totally different meaning.

  13. There is the weaker concept of a quasi-component of a topological space. In a compact Hausdorff space, the two are identical; see Wilder (1949). Even though many economic settings assume the Hausdorff separation axiom, compactness may fail, like the consumption set of a consumer in a Walrasian economy. Hence, it may be of interest to see whether the results in this paper generalize to quasi-components.

  14. In terms of a reader’s guide, and especially for a first reading, one may read these theorems for the case \(k=1,\) and instead of the full equivalence, even limit oneself to the forward direction as in the foundational papers.

  15. We are indebted to Ullman-Margalit and Morgenbesser (1977) for this terminological distinction; also taken up in Sen (1993), and under the heading of “the idea of internal consistency of choice,” in Sen (2017, pp. 309–312).

  16. We shall return to this below in Proposition 2 and in Theorems 5 and 6.

  17. We may point out here in anticipation that our joint treatment of these foundational results has also allowed us to provide alternative proofs of the results of Eilenberg and Sonnenschein. Our method of proof is inspired by Schmeidler and is totally different compared to theirs; see this observation formally made in the paragraph preceding the proof of this theorem, and in the remark following it.

  18. Note that the usage here differs from that of Houthakker’s concept; see Sen (2017, pp. 94, 295–298, 299).

  19. On this, see Fig. 2 and Proposition 2. These relationships are partially available in Sonnenschein (1965, Theorem 3), Lorimer (1967, Theorem 2) and Sen (1969, Theorem I).

  20. We return to this in Sect. 4.1.

  21. To be sure, the discussion in this paragraph assumes \(k=1;\) the foundational literature is silent on higher values of the natural number k.

  22. We have already emphasized the first question in Footnote 8, but what is being emphasized here is the existence of the relation rather than a function, a question that is taken up in the social choice literature; see Khan and Uyanık (2018) for an exploration of this question and an elaboration of this connection. At any rate, as we shall see, it is essential to the result we present below.

  23. The reader is again warned about the lack of a uniform terminology in the literature; see Sen (2017, p. 54).

  24. This construction is illustrated in the backward direction of the proofs of Theorems 1 and 2; see the penultimate paragraph of the proof of Theorem 1 presented below. As regards Theorem 2, the cases \(k=1\) and \(k=2\) are considered separately; see the last paragraph of the proof in each case.

  25. We do not do this because Theorem 3 is primarily motivated by the transitivity claim of Eilenberg–Sonnenschein.

  26. We present here a slightly stronger version of Sonnenschein’s theorems in order to underscore the comparison. He assumes the connectedness of \(X\backslash I\) instead of connectedness of X. It is easy to prove a version of our results under this assumption. A result similar to Sonnenschein’s theorem is provided by Rader (1963, Lemma) under a stronger connectedness assumption which requires the upper sections of the weak preference relation to be connected.

  27. It should be noted, however, that Lorimer also shows that these conditions are not only sufficient for transitivity of a complete relation, but also necessary, and hence there is something extra and of consequent use in his paper.

  28. We are primarily motivated by forging connections to current work; there is little doubt that results of several of the papers that we connect to can be generalized to the setting of k-connected sets for any natural number k, and thereby to reformulate the theorem presented below along the lines of Theorem 1.

  29. These “covering” types of derived relations have important applications and implications in decision theory as well as in social choice theory. In particular, they have been used for the numerical representation of incomplete preferences; see, for example, Chateauneuf (1987) for representation of interval orders and Peleg (1970) and Galaabaatar and Karni (2013) for expected utility representation of incomplete preferences. In social choice theory, the “covering relation” has been used since mid-twentieth century; see Duggan (2013) for a comprehensive survey on covering relation.

  30. We investigate the deconstruction of the continuity postulate elsewhere. In particular, we study the topological and behavioral implications of linear, order and differentiability structures; see Khan and Uyanık (2019).

  31. We return to this issue in Sect. 5; see Footnote 61, and the text in footnotes.

  32. Since we exclusively work with a topological structure, we do not investigate the implications of the added assumptions related to linear structure on the ES program. Uzawa (1960) pioneered this line of research by showing that convexity of a complete preference relation defined on a convex subset of a topological vector space with closed upper sections and a transitive asymmetric part implies that the relation itself is transitive. This result is reproduced and generalized by Sonnenschein (1965, Theorems 5 and 6) and picked up by Neuefeind and Trockel (1995) and Galaabaatar et al. (2019).

  33. Note that to say that the symmetric part of a relation is complete renders the relation trivial, whereas to say that the asymmetric part is complete furnishes the contradiction that an element of the space is preferred to itself. In Sen (1969), is the crucial transitivity condition and he found it convenient to give it a more usable name: “quasi-transitivity.” In this connection, also see the subject index in Sen (2017) for additional discussion of his named concept.

  34. For example, to see and imply T from Fig. 3b, simply note that and imply which combined with then implies T. And so on for the other implications.

  35. There is a rich philosophical literature on the discussion of non-transitivity, already referred to in Footnote 35. One may add that Tullock (1964) defends transitivity by using simple logical arguments and criticizes the experiments which argue evidence against transitivity. Anand (1993) criticizes Tullock for not considering ternary relation; also see also Luce (1956), Fishburn (1970) and Gilboa and Lapson (1995).

  36. We warn the reader of the difference in terminology; see Footnote 18 above.

  37. As we shall have occasion to see below, all this supports the quotation from Wakker in the next section about the importance of judging the conditions in combination.

  38. See Sonnenschein (1965, Footnote 4 and Theorem 7A) where the alternative proof of the special case is justified on the grounds of furnishing “an interesting technique.”

  39. See, in particular, (Wilder 1949, Theorems 4:12 and 9.3); also Dickman (1984), Brown (2006), Brown and Camarena (2015) and their references for modern work on the property. Note that the PBP is not a strengthening of the connectedness assumption since any space with the discrete topology satisfies it, but rather a different separation property.

  40. In a connected and locally connected space, path-connectedness of the sections of a complete relation R implies that I has connected sections. Moreover, connectedness of the sections of I in a connected space implies that R has connected sections, which is weaker than path-connectedness. See Wilder (1949, Theorem 4.5 on p. 49 and Theorem 9.9 on p. 20) for the proofs.

  41. Gerasimou (2015) shows that reflexive, transitive and additive binary relation with closed upper sections has a closed graph, and hence, convexity of a relation has implications on its continuity; see Footnote 32 for further references and discussion on convexity.

  42. A celebrated example of the former is Malinvaud (1952); also see Footnote 48. An example of the latter is a reconsideration of Shafer’s non-transitive consumer that we present in Sect. 4.2, and of Schmeidler’s existence theorem in Sect. 4.3; also see Footnote 22. What we do not mean by the word hiddenness is the sense that is given to it by Tourky and Yannelis (2000). Their usage is orthogonal to ours, and perhaps also to redundancy: they refer to an assumption being “hidden” as one that is explicit but essential in the sense that eliminating it would require additional hypotheses to obtain the same consequences.

  43. The italics are the author’s, and the example is Wakker (1988a, Example 7.3). For further discussion on the empirical implication of technical assumptions, see Pfanzagl (1971, pp. 107–108) and Narens (1985, pp. 83–84).

  44. Gorno (2018, Proposition 10) presents a result that Schmeidler’s theorem as a special case, but rather than the necessity and sufficiency of the property, resets it on maximal \(\succeq \)-domains, maximal on which the relation is complete.

  45. This connects us to Luce’s (1956) semi-order, which is further elaborated in Fishburn (1970) and Alcantud and Gutiérrez (1999), a connection that we hope to explore in future work.

  46. As Kim–Richter also note, McKenzie (1981) raises a similar point and writes “Whether the preference relation \(\succcurlyeq _i\) is complete seems to be a matter of definition, since x incomparable with y can be replaced harmlessly by x indifferent to y in the absence of transitivity.”

  47. This claim is based on the use of the convexity assumption as in Shafer. There is little doubt that the thrust of the claim also holds in a modified form with the weaker convexity assumption that Kim–Richter rely on.

  48. As shown by Malinvaud (1952), von Neumann and Morgenstern (1947) do not state the independence axiom in their axiomatization. Nash (1950a) and Marschak (1950) independently provide complete axiomatization of expected utility; see Bleichrodt et al. (2016) and also Footnote 42 above.

  49. We summarize the assumptions of the version of Debreu’s theorem restated in Arrow and Debreu (1954, Lemma).

  50. Note that without non-triviality, the existence of an equilibrium is triviality, and hence the non-triviality assumption is non-restrictive.

  51. See Assumptions 2.1 (excluding (e) and (f)), 2.6, 2.7 and 2.8 in Broome (1972).

  52. See also Balasko and Tvede (2010), Carbonell-Nicolau and McLean (2018), Cerreia-Vioglio et al. (2018), Gerasimou (2016, 2018), Qin (2017), Quah (2006), Riella (2015) and Uyanık (2014) for recent results with weaker continuity and/or behavioral assumptions on preferences.

  53. Also see Wakker (1988b). For comprehensive treatments, see Bridges and Mehta (1995), Mehta (1998), Rébillé (2019), Hervés-Beloso and del Valle-Inclán Cruces (2019) and their references.

  54. Note that Eilenberg (1941, 2.1) observes the hiddenness of transitivity. Moreover, our insertion of non-triviality in the statement of Eilenberg’s theorem does not do violence to his original statement because of the consideration emphasized in Footnote 20 and in the text it footnotes.

  55. For additional references, the interested reader may see, for example, Debreu (1960), Gorman (1968), Fishburn (1968), Vilkas (1980), Bridges and Mehta (1995) and Vind (2003).

  56. While Peleg’s representation provides only froward direction representation result for incomplete preferences, Majumdar–Sen’s approach provides both directions.

  57. This literature stems from the classic work of Herstein and Milnor (1953), where the topological structure is restricted to that on the unit interval, and the overall thrust is algebraic. We also single out in this connection, Moldau (1996, Proposition 1) and Neuefeind and Trockel (1995). Moldau asserts that transitivity on every closed interval of a preference ration defined on a linear space follows from a weak convexity assumption, and as such, hidden by the convexity postulate. Neuefeind–Trockel show that completeness and transitivity of a relation defined on a topological vector space follow from a convexity postulate under suitable consistency and continuity postulates. Since we are limiting ourselves to the topological register, we hope to engage this claim elsewhere; also see footnote 32 for further references and discussion regarding the convexity assumption.

  58. Note that the implication (a) \(\Rightarrow \) (d) in Theorem 4 does not require the topological space to be quasi-ordered and hence is true for any topological space.

  59. See Bernheim and Rangel (2009, pp. 75–76); also their Theorem 7 which they see as following directly from standard results of Fon, Mandler, Otani, Rigotti and Shannon.

  60. See also Ioannides (2006) for a topological investigation of social interactions.

  61. In some sense, we have kept doing versions that approach such a portmanteau theorem.

  62. The reader is referred to the counterexample a little above the statement of Theorem 3.

  63. The reader is referred to Temkin (2015), Sen (2017) and their references, also to Anand (1987) and Anand (1993).

  64. As already pointed out in Footnote 3 in the context of the mathematical literature, Ward (1954) and Bridges and Mehta (1995) are important references subsequent to Nachbin’s pioneering monograph on “Topology and Order;” and McGehee (1992) for application to dynamical systems. The philosophical literature is immense but Anand (1987, 1993) furnishes an admirable entry into issues concerning the rationality or the irrationality of transitivity and completeness; in addition to the references in Sen (2017) and Temkin, see Tullock (1964). To be sure, any sharp lines to differentiate between the substantive and the technical eventually leads to sterility.

  65. For the first see Bernheim and Rangel (2009) and their references; and for the second, see Pfanzagl (1971) and Narens (1985).

  66. All this is now so much part of the folklore that detailed references are hardly necessary. But the reader can do no worse than beginning with Fishburn (1972) and Gilboa (2009) on the one hand, and Mehta (1998) and Bridges and Mehta (1995) on the other. For current activity in the field, in addition to the three references with which we began Sect. 4, we refer the reader to Gerasimou (2017) and Strzalecki (2013) and their references.

  67. Note that we can choose this connected subset as the component C of I(z) which contains \(I_z\). This follows from the fact that if a set is connected in a subspace Y of a topological space, then it is also connected in any subspace containing Y. In order to see this, note that it follows from \(I_z\) separates x and y that there exist distinct components \(C_x\) and \(C_y\) of \(X\backslash I_z\) such that \(x\in C_x\) and \(y\in C_y\). Assume that x and y are contained in the same component \(C_{xy}\) of \(X\backslash C.\) Since C contains \(I_z,\) \(X\backslash C\subset X\backslash I_z.\) Hence, \(C_{xy}\) is connected in \(X\backslash I_z.\) Then, \(x\in C_x\cap C_{xy}\) and \(y\in C_y\cap C_{xy}\) contradict \(C_x\) and \(C_y\) being distinct components of \(X\backslash I_z.\) Therefore, x and y are contained in distinct components of \(X\backslash C,\) i.e., C separates x and y. Since any component of a space is connected, the requirement that the subset \(I_z\) is closed in the definition of the Phragmen–Brouwer property in Wilder (1949, Property V\('\), p. 50) is not restrictive. However, our version requires the separation property holds only for open sets.

  68. Gerasimou (2013, Corollary 3) showed that this statement is true provided that the space is connected and R is reflexive. However, the statement is true without the reflexivity assumption and the construction in his proof directly follows. Hence, we drop reflexivity.

  69. A similar result for antisymmetric binary relations is provided by Eilenberg (1941, 1.4).

References

  • Alcantud, J., Gutiérrez, J.: Preference through indifference: a topological approach. J. Math. Econ. 31(4), 543–551 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anand, P.: Are the preference axioms really rational? Theory Decis. 23(2), 189–214 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anand, P.: The philosophy of intransitive preference. Econ. J. 103(417), 337–346 (1993)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K.J., Debreu, G.: Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy. Econometrica 22(3), 265–290 (1954)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K.J., Sen, A.K., Suzumura, K.: Social Choice Re-examined. vol. 1 and 2. St. Martin’s Press, New York (1995, 1996)

  • Arrow, K.J., Sen, A.K., Suzumura, K.: Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare. vol. 1 and 2. Elsevier, North Holland (2002, 2011)

  • Asheim, G.B., Bossert, W., Sprumont, Y., Suzumura, K.: Infinite-horizon choice functions. Econ. Theory 43(1), 1–21 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-008-0423-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balasko, Y., Tvede, M.: General equilibrium without utility functions: how far to go? Econ. Theory 45(1–2), 201–225 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-009-0496-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barten, A.P., Böhm, V.: Consumer theory. In: Arrow, K., Intriligator, M. D. (eds.) Handbook of Mathematical Economics, vol. 2, pp. 381–429. North Holland (1982)

  • Bergstrom, T.C., Parks, R.P., Rader, T.: Preferences which have open graphs. J. Math. Econ. 3(3), 265–268 (1976)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B.D., Rangel, A.: Beyond revealed preference: choice-theoretic foundations for behavioral welfare economics. Q. J. Econ. 124(1), 51–104 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H., Li, C., Moscati, I., Wakker, P.P.: Nash was a first to axiomatize expected utility. Theory Decis. 81(3), 309–312 (2016)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bridges, D.S., Mehta, G.B.: Representations of Preference Orderings. Springer, Berlin (1995)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J.: Approximate equilibrium in economies with indivisible commodities. J. Econ. Theory 5(2), 224–249 (1972)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, R.: Groupoids, the Phragmen–Brouwer property, and the Jordan curve theorem. J. Homotopy Relat. Struct. 1(1), 175–183 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, R., Camarena, O.A.: Erratum to: Groupoids, the Phragmen–Brouwer property, and the Jordan curve theorem. J. Homotopy Relat. Struct. 10(3), 669–672 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbonell-Nicolau, O., McLean, R.P.: Nash and Bayes–Nash equilibria in strategic-form games with intransitivities. Econ. Theory (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-018-1151-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, G.: Symposium on: existence of Nash equilibria in discontinuous games. Econ. Theory 48(1), 1–4 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-010-0576-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cerreia-Vioglio, S., Giarlotta, A., Greco, S., Maccheroni, F., Marinacci, M.: Rational preference and rationalizable choice. Econ. Theory (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-018-1157-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chateauneuf, A.: Continuous representation of a preference relation on a connected topological space. J. Math. Econ. 16(2), 139–146 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P., Maskin, E.: The existence of equilibrium in discontinuous economic games, I: theory, II: applications. Rev. Econ. Stud. 53(1), 1–41 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G.: A social equilibrium existence theorem. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 38(10), 886–893 (1952)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G.: Chapter 11: Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function. In: Thrall, M., Davis, R., Coombs, C. (eds.) Decision Processes, pp. 159–165. Wiley, New York (1954)

    Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G.: Topological methods in cardinal utility theory. In: Arrow, K., Karlin, S., Suppes, P. (eds.) Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences, pp. 16–26. Stanford University Press, California (1960)

    Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G.: Existence of competitive equilibrium. In: Arrow, K., Intriligator, M. D. (eds.) Handbook of Mathematical Economics, vol. 2, pp. 697–743. North Holland (1982)

  • Dickman Jr., R.F.: A strong form of the Phragmen–Brouwer theorem. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 90(2), 333–337 (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dierker, E.: Equilibrium analysis of exchange economies with indivisible commodities. Econometrica 39(6), 997–1008 (1971)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubra, J.: Continuity and completeness under risk. Math. Soc. Sci. 61(1), 80–81 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dubra, J., Maccheroni, F., Ok, E.A.: Expected utility theory without the completeness axiom. J. Econ. Theory 115(1), 118–133 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duggan, J.: Uncovered sets. Soc. Choice Welf. 41(3), 489–535 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dugundji, J.: Topology. Allyn and Bacon, Boston (1966)

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, P.H., Jamison, R.E.: The theory of convex geometries. Geom. Dedic. 19(3), 247–270 (1985)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eilenberg, S.: Ordered topological spaces. Am. J. Math. 63(1), 39–45 (1941)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evren, Ö.: On the existence of expected multi-utility representations. Econ. Theory 35(3), 575–592 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-007-0252-5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evren, Ö.: Scalarization methods and expected multi-utility representations. J. Econ. Theory 151, 30–63 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: Utility theory. Manag. Sci. 14(5), 335–378 (1968)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: Intransitive indifference in preference theory: a survey. Oper. Res. 18(2), 207–228 (1970)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: Mathematics of Decision Theory. Mouton, The Hauge (1972)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, M., Blanchet, D.: Beyond GDP: Measuring Welfare and Assessing Sustainability. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2013)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, M., Salles, M., Weymark, J.: Justice, Political Liberalism, and Utilitarianism. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Galaabaatar, T., Karni, E.: Subjective expected utility with incomplete preferences. Econometrica 81(1), 255–284 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galaabaatar, T., Khan, M.A., Uyanık, M.: Completeness and transitivity of preferences on mixture sets. Math. Soc. Sci. 99, 49–62 (2019)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerasimou, G.: Consumer theory with bounded rational preferences. J. Math. Econ. 46(5), 708–714 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerasimou, G.: On continuity of incomplete preferences. Soc. Choice Welf. 41(1), 157–167 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerasimou, G.: (Hemi) continuity of additive preference preorders. J. Math. Econ. 58, 79–81 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerasimou, G.: Partially dominant choice. Econ. Theory 61(1), 127–145 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-015-0869-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerasimou, G.: Indecisiveness, undesirability and overload revealed through rational choice deferral. Econ. J. 128, 2450–2479 (2017)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerasimou, G.: Dominance solvable multicriteria games with incomplete preferences. Econ. Theory Bull. (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-018-0159-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I.: Theory of Decision Under Uncertainty. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2009)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., Lapson, R.: Aggregation of semiorders: intransitive indifference makes a difference. Econ. Theory 5(1), 109–126 (1995). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01213647

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gorman, W.M.: The structure of utility functions. Rev. Econ. Stud. 35(4), 367–390 (1968)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gorno, L.: The structure of incomplete preferences. Econ. Theory 66(1), 159–185 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-017-1057-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J.C.: Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility. J. Political Econ. 63(4), 309–321 (1955)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • He, W., Yannelis, N.C.: Existence of Walrasian equilibria with discontinuous, non-ordered, interdependent and price-dependent preferences. Econ. Theory 61(3), 497–513 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-015-0875-x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herstein, I.N., Milnor, J.: An axiomatic approach to measurable utility. Econometrica 21(2), 291–297 (1953)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hervés-Beloso, C., del Valle-Inclán Cruces, H.: Continuous preference orderings representable by utility functions. J. Econ. Surv. 33(1), 179–194 (2019)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ioannides, Y.M.: Topologies of social interactions. Econ. Theory 28(3), 559–584 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-005-0646-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, M.O.: Socal and Economic Networks. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2008)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Karni, E.: Axiomatic foundations of expected utility and subjective probability. In: Machina, M., Viscusi, K. (eds.) Handbook of the Economics of Risk and Uncertainty, vol. 1, pp. 1–39. Elsevier (2014)

  • Khan, M.A., Sun, Y.: On a reformulation of Cournot–Nash equilibria. J. Math. Anal. Appl 146(2), 442–460 (1990)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khan, M.A., Sun, Y.: Non-cooperative games with many players. In: Aumann, R., Hart, S. (eds.) Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications, vol. 3, pp. 1761–1808. North Holland (2002)

  • Khan, M.A., Uyanık, M.: On the existence of continuous binary relations on a topological space. mimeo (2018)

  • Khan, M.A., Uyanık, M.: The continuity postulate in economic theory: a deconstruction and an integration. mimeo (2019)

  • Khan, M.A., Yamazaki, A.: On the cores of economies with indivisible commodities and a continuum of traders. J. Econ. Theory 24(2), 218–225 (1981)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, T., Richter, M.K.: Nontransitive-nontotal consumer theory. J. Econ. Theory 38(2), 324–363 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lorimer, P.: A note on orderings. Econometrica 35(3–4), 537–539 (1967)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R.D.: Semiorders and a theory of utility discrimination. Econometrica 24(2), 178–191 (1956)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magyarkuti, G.: Revealed preferences: a topological approach. J. Math. Econ. 46(3), 320–325 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Majumdar, M., Sen, A.: A note on representing partial orderings. Rev. Econ. Stud. 43(3), 543–545 (1976)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malinvaud, E.: Note on von Neumann–Morgenstern’s strong independence axiom. Econometrica 20(4), 679 (1952)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marschak, J.: Rational behavior, uncertain prospects, and measurable utility. Econometrica 18(2), 111–141 (1950)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell, A.: An equilibrium existence theorem without complete or transitive preferences. J. Math. Econ. 1(3), 237–246 (1974)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell, A.: A model of equilibrium with differentiated commodities. J. Math. Econ. 2(2), 263–295 (1975)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell, A.: Indivisible commodities and general equilibrium theory. J. Econ. Theory 16(2), 443–456 (1977)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mas-Colell, A., Zame, W.R.: Equilibrium theory in infinite dimensional spaces. In: Hildenbrand, W., Sonnenschein, H. (eds.) Handbook of Mathematical Economics, vol. 4, pp. 1835–1898 (1991)

  • McGehee, R.: Attractors for closed relations on compact Hausdorff spaces. Indiana Univ. Math. J. 41(4), 1165–1209 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenzie, L.W.: The classical theorem on existence of competitive equilibrium. Econometrica 49(4), 819–841 (1981)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenzie, L.W.: Classical General Equilibrium Theory, vol. 1. The MIT Press, Cambridge (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehta, G.B.: Preference and utility. In: Barbera, S., Hammond, P. J., Seidl, C. (eds.) Handbook of Utility Theory: Principles, vol. 1, pp. 1–47. Kluwer Academic Publishers (1998)

  • Moldau, J.H.: A simple existence proof of demand functions without standard transitivity. J. Math. Econ. 25(3), 325–333 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narens, L.: Abstract Measurement Theory. MIT Press, Cambridge (1985)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J.F.: The bargaining problem. Econometrica 18(2), 155–162 (1950a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J.F.: Equilibrium points in n-person games. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 36(1), 48–49 (1950b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neuefeind, W., Trockel, W.: Continuous linear representability of binary relations. Econ. Theory 6(2), 351–356 (1995). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01212495

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, M.E.J.: Modularity and community structure in networks. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 103(23), 8577–8582 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg, B.: Utility functions for partially ordered topological spaces. Econometrica 38(1), 93–96 (1970)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pfanzagl, J.: Theory of Measurement. Springer, Berlin (1971)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Qin, D.: Partially dominant choice with transitive preferences. Econ. Theory Bull. 5(2), 191–198 (2017)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quah, J.K.: Weak axiomatic demand theory. Econ. Theory 29(3), 677–699 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-005-0017-y

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rader, T.: The existence of a utility function to represent preferences. Rev. Econ. Stud. 30(3), 229–232 (1963)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rébillé, Y.: Continuous utility on connected separable topological spaces. Econ. Theory Bull. 7, 147–153 (2019)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reny, P.J.: On the existence of pure and mixed strategy Nash equilibria in discontinuous games. Econometrica 67(5), 1029–1056 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reny, P.J.: Introduction to the symposium on discontinuous games. Econ. Theory 61(3), 423–429 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-016-0962-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richter, M., Rubinstein, A.: Back to fundamentals: Equilibrium in abstract economies. Am. Econ. Rev. 105(8), 2570–94 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riella, G.: On the representation of incomplete preferences under uncertainty with indecisiveness in tastes and beliefs. Econ. Theory 58(3), 571–600 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-015-0860-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P.A.: Bergsonian welfare economics. In: Rosefields, S. (ed.) Economic welfare and the economics of Soviet socialism: essays in honor of Abram Bergson, pp. 223–266. Cambridge University Press, New York (1981)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D.: Competitive equilibria in markets with a continuum of traders and incomplete preferences. Econometrica 37(4), 578–585 (1969)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D.: A condition for the completeness of partial preference relations. Econometrica 39(2), 403–404 (1971)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A.: Quasi-transitivity, rational choice and collective decisions. Rev. Econ. Stud. 36(3), 381–393 (1969)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A.: Internal consistency of choice. Econometrica 61(3), 495–521 (1993)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A.: Collective Choice and Social Welfare: An Expanded Edition. Harvard University Press, Massachusetts (2017)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, W.: The nontransitive consumer. Econometrica 42(5), 913–919 (1974)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer, W., Sonnenschein, H.: Equilibrium in abstract economies without ordered preferences. J. Math. Econ. 2(3), 345–348 (1975)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sonnenschein, H.: The relationship between transitive preference and the structure of the choice space. Econometrica 33(3), 624–634 (1965)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sonnenschein, H.: Reply to “A note on orderings”. Econometrica 35(3, 4), 540 (1967)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sonnenschein, H.: Demand theory without transitive indifference with applications to the theory of competitive equilibrium. In: Chipman, J., Hurwicz, L., Richter, M., Sonenschein, H. (eds.) Preferences, Utility and Demand: A Minnesota Symposium, pp. 215–234. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, New York (1971)

    Google Scholar 

  • Strzalecki, T.: Temporal resolution of uncertainty and recursive models of ambiguity aversion. Econometrica 81(3), 1039–1074 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suzumura, K.: Choice, Preferences and Procedures. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (2016)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Temkin, L.S.: Rethinking the Good: Moral Ideals and the Nature of Practical Reasoning. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, W.: Fair allocation rules. In: Arrow, K., Sen, A., Suzumura, K. (eds.) Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, vol. 2, pp. 393–506. Elsevier (2011)

  • Tourky, R., Yannelis, N.C.: Markets with many more agents than commodities: Aumann’s “hidden” assumption. J. Econ. Theory 101(1), 189–221 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tullock, G.: The irrationality of intransitivity. Oxf. Econ. Pap. 16(3), 401–406 (1964)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ullman-Margalit, E., Morgenbesser, S.: Picking and choosing. Soc. Res. 44(4), 757–785 (1977)

    Google Scholar 

  • Uyanık, M.: Maximality in games and economies. Unpublished manuscript (2014)

  • Uzawa, H.: Preference and Rational Choice in the Theory of Consumption. Stanford University Press, Palo Alto (1960)

    Google Scholar 

  • Vilkas, É.: Utility theory. J. Sov. Math. 13(4), 532–550 (1980)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vind, K.: Independence, Additivity, Uncertainty. With Contributions by B. Grodal. Springer, Berlin (2003)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J., Morgenstern, O.: Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, 2nd edn. Princeton University Press, New Jersey (1947)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.: The algebraic versus the topological approach to additive representations. J. Math. Psychol. 32(4), 421–435 (1988a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.: Continuity of preference relations for separable topologies. Int. Econ. Rev. 29(1), 105–110 (1988b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.P.: Additive Representations of Preferences: A New Foundation of Decision Analysis. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston (1989)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, L.: Partially ordered topological spaces. Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 5(1), 144–161 (1954)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilder, R.L.: Topology of Manifolds. American Mathematical Society Colloquium Publications XXXII, Berlin (1949)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yannelis, N.C., Prabhakar, N.D.: Existence of maximal elements and equilibria in linear topological spaces. J. Math. Econ. 12(3), 233–245 (1983)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yannelis, N.C., Zame, W.R.: Equilibria in Banach lattices without ordered preferences. J. Math. Econ. 15(2), 85–110 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Metin Uyanık.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

A previous version of this paper was completed while Uyanık was a post-doctoral fellow at the Allen Wallis Institute of Political Economy at the University of Rochester; earlier versions were presented at Rutgers University (April 19, 2017), the University of Rochester (May 4, 2017), the 17th SAET Conference in Faro (June 25–30, 2017), Positivity IX Conference in Edmonton (July 17–21, 2017), the 36th Australasian Economic Theory Workshop in Canberra (February 8, 2018) and the University of Queensland (August 8, 2018). We are grateful to Rich McLean for the SAET invitation, and thank him for detailed and indispensable advice on the presentation of our results. We also thank Max Amarante, Paul Anand, Han Bleichrodt, Ying Chen, John Duggan, Hülya Eraslan, Yorgos Gerasimou, Filippo Massari, Andy McLennan, Onur Ozgur, John Quah, Eddie Schlee and Rajiv Vohra for stimulating conversation. Finally, we thank four anonymous referees for their erudition and sympathetic reading.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Khan, M.A., Uyanık, M. Topological connectedness and behavioral assumptions on preferences: a two-way relationship. Econ Theory 71, 411–460 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-019-01206-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-019-01206-7

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

JEL Classification

Navigation