Skip to main content
Log in

What the Middle-Aged Galileo Told the Elderly Galileo: Galileo’s Search for the Laws of Fall

  • Published:
Physics in Perspective Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent historiographic results in Galilean studies disclose the use of proportions, graphical representation of the kinematic variables (distance, time, speed), and the medieval double distance rule in Galileo’s reasoning; these have been characterized as Galileo’s “tools for thinking.” We assess the import of these “tools” in Galileo’s reasoning leading to the laws of fall (\(v^{2} \propto D\) and \(v \propto t\)). To this effect, a reconstruction of folio 152r shows that Galileo built proportions involving distance, time, and speed in uniform motions, and applied to them the double distance rule to obtain uniformly accelerated motions; the folio indicates that he tried to fit proportions in a graph. Analogously, an argument in Two New Sciences to the effect that an earlier proof of the law of fall started from an incorrect hypothesis (v  D) can be recast in the language of proportions, using only the proof that v  t and the hypothesis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The third motion does not belong in the same fall with the other two: neither the speed nor the time of fall when the body falls a distance equal to the mean proportional are equal to the speed and the time in the third motion. Furthermore, the third motion seems to be introduced as a computational trick; the mean proportional is only a way to find square roots.

  2. \(\tan \left( {\widehat{Xac }} \right) = \frac{20}{4} = \frac{30}{6} = \frac{cX}{9} = 5\) so that \(cX = 45.\)

  3. Mathematically, \(\frac{{t_{ac} }}{{t_{ab} }} = 1\) does not preclude the solutions \(1 = \mathop {\lim }\limits_{t \to 0} \left( {\frac{{t_{ac} }}{{t_{ab} }}} \right)\) and \(1 = \mathop {\lim }\limits_{t \to \infty } \left( {\frac{{t_{ac} }}{{t_{ab} }}} \right)\); the first solution means “instantaneous motion;” the second means infinite time, as Norton and Roberts claim. Furthermore, \(\sqrt {\frac{{D_{ac} }}{{D_{ab} }} } = 0\) is also a solution, and likewise, it does not preclude \(\mathop {\lim }\limits_{D \to 0} \sqrt {\frac{{D_{ac} }}{{D_{ab} }} } = 0\), or “no distance at all,” as claimed by Mach.

  4. "\(A\) at \(C\) has double the velocity of \(B\) at \(D\); therefore \(A\) has such velocity as to run in uniform motion four braccia in the time that \(B\) in uniform motion runs two braccia. The time in which \(B\) at \(D\) runs two braccia is the time in which it has run through \(BD\); therefore, the time in which \(A\) at \(C\) will run four braccia in uniform motion is equal to that in which \(B\), accelerated, has run through \(BD\). Now, the time in which \(A\) at \(C\) runs four braccia uniformly is equal to that in which it has run through \(AC\) with accelerated motion; therefore, the time of motion of \(A\) through \(AC\) is equal to the time of motion of \(B\) through \(BD\). But the time of motion of \(B\) through \(BD\) is equal to the time in which \(A\) has passed through \(AE\); therefore, the time of motion of \(A\) through \(AC\), which is seen to be the time of \(B\) through \(BD\), is equal to that of the motion of \(A\) through \(AE\). Therefore \(EC\) was passed over without time."

References

  1. Galileo Galilei, Discourse Concerning Two New Sciences, trans. Stillman Drake (Toronto: Wall & Thomson, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Winifred L. Wisan, “The New Science of Motion: A Study of Galileo’s De motu locali,” Archive for History of Exact Sciences 13, no. 2–3 (1974), 103–306.

    Article  ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  3. Stillman Drake, “Galileo’s Discovery of the Law of Free Fall,” Scientific American 228, no. 5 (1973), 84–92.

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  4. Drake, Galileo at Work (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978); Wisan, “New Science of Motion” (ref. 2), 227.

  5. Matthias Schemmel, “Medieval Representations of Change and Their Early Modern-Application,” Foundations of Science 19, no. 1 (2014), 11–34; Peter Damerow, Gideon Freudenthal, Peter McLaughlin, and Jürgen Renn, Exploring the Limits of Preclassical Mechanics (Dordrecht: Springer, 2004), ch. 3; Carla Rita Palmerino, “The Geometrization of Motion: Galileo’s Triangle of Speed and its Various Transformations,” Early Science and Medicine 15, no. 4–5 (2010), 410–47.

  6. Marshal Clagett, The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1959), 414.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Schemmel, “Medieval Representations” (ref. 5), 12.

  8. Palmerino, “The Geometrization of Motion” (ref. 5), 414.

  9. Drake, “Galileo’s Discovery” (ref. 3); Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5).

  10. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5); Wisan, “The New Science of Motion” (ref. 2).

  11. Drake, Galileo at Work (ref. 4), 86–90.

  12. R. H. Naylor, “Galileo’s Theory of Motion: Processes of Conceptual Change in the Period 1604–10,” Annals of Science 34, no. 4 (1977), 365–402.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. “Galileo Galilei,” in A. Favaro, ed., Le Opere di Galileo Galilei, vol. 10, 115–16 (Florence: Barbèra, 1900). Also in Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 354–55.

  14. Galileo Galilei, letter to Sarpi, translated in Drake, Galileo at Work (ref. 4), 103.

  15. Drake, Galileo at Work (ref. 4), 103. Also in Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 360.

  16. Wisan, “The New Science of Motion” (ref. 2), 210.

  17. Damerow et al. (ref. 5).

  18. Palmerino, “The Geometrization of Motion” (ref. 5), 424.

  19. Galileo, Two New Sciences (ref. 1), 159–61 (Third Day, 203–4).

  20. Drake, “Uniform Acceleration, Space, and Time,” The British Journal for the History of Science 5, no. 1 (1970), 21–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Ernst Mach, The Science of Mechanics (A Critical and Historical Account of its Development), trans. Thomas J. McCormack (Chicago: Open Court, 1893, 1902, 1919); first published in German in 1883; John D. Norton and B. W. Roberts, “Galileo’s Refutation of the Speed-Distance Law of Fall Rehabilitated,” Centaurus 54, no. 2 (2012), 148–64.

  22. Isaac Bernard Cohen, “Galileo’s Rejection of the Possibility of Velocity Changing Uniformly with Respect to Distance,” Isis 47, no. 2 (1956), 231–35; A. Rupert Hall, “Notes & Correspondence,” Isis 49, no. 3 (1958), 342–49; Drake, “Uniform Acceleration” (ref. 20); Palmerino, “Aggregating Speeds and Scaling Motions: A Response to Norton and Roberts,” Centaurus 54, no. 2 (2012), 165–76; W. R. Laird, “Stillman Drake on Salviati’s Proof,” Centaurus 54, no. 2 (2012), 177–81.

  23. Noel M. Swerdlow, “Galileo’s Mechanics of Natural Motion and Particles,” The Oxford Handbook of The History of Physics, ed. Jed Z. Buchwald and Robert Fox, 25–55 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013).

  24. Carla Palmerino, “Reading the Book of Nature: The Ontological and Epistemological Underpinnings of Galileo’s Mathematical Realism,” in The Language of Nature: Reassessing the Mathematization of Natural Philosophy in the Seventeenth Century, ed. Geoffrey Gorham, Benjamin Hill, Edward Slowik, and C. Kenneth Waters, 29–50 (Minneapolis, London: University of Minnesota Press, 2016), 31–32.

  25. Archimedes, “On Spirals,” in The Works of Archimedes, ed. T. L. Heath, 151–88 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1897), proposition I, 155.

  26. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 6), 15–16; Aristotle, “Physica,” in The Works of Aristotle, ed. W. D. Ross (Cambridge: Clarendon Press, 1930), v.II, vi.2, 232a 24–27.

  27. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5).

  28. Wisan, “The New Science of Motion” (ref. 2), 213.

  29. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 17.

  30. Hall, “Notes” (ref. 28). Cohen, The Birth of a New Physics (1960; London: Penguin, 1992); Palmerino, “Aggregating Speeds and Scaling Motions” (ref. 22). Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5).

  31. Galileo, cited in Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 166.

  32. Eduard J. Dijksterhuis, The Mechanization of the World Picture (Pythagoras to Kepler) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1950).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Clagett, The Science of Mechanics (ref. 6), 290–97, 305–17, 347–67, 567.

  34. Clagett, The Science of Mechanics (ref. 6), 210, 343.

  35. Clagett, The Science of Mechanics (ref. 6), 414.

  36. Clagett, The Science of Mechanics (ref. 6), 384.

  37. William Heytesbury, cited in Clagett, The Science of Mechanics (ref. 6), 271.

  38. Galileo, cited in Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 361.

  39. Wisan, “The New Science of Motion” (ref. 2), 206.

  40. Drake, “Galileo’s Discovery” (ref. 3), 85.

  41. Cohen, The Birth of a New Physics (ref. 30); Naylor, “Galileo’s Theory of Motion” (ref. 12). Palmerino, “The Geometrization of Motion” (ref. 5)

  42. Wisan, “Galileo’s Scientific Method: a Reexamination,” in New Perspectives on Galileo, ed. R. E. Butts and J. C. Pitt (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1978), 1–58.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Wisan, “The New Science of Motion” (ref. 2), 211–12; Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 7), 187; Drake, “Galileo’s Discovery” (ref. 3).

  44. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 182–88; Wisan, “The New Science of Motion” (ref. 2), 185–87.

  45. Palmerino, “The Geometrization of Motion” (ref. 5).

  46. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 180.

  47. Wisan, “The New Science of Motion” (ref. 2), 212; Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 192.

  48. The texts are quoted from Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 365.

  49. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 184–85.

  50. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 185–87.

  51. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 187.

  52. Drake, “Galileo’s Discovery” (ref. 3), 86.

  53. Wisan, “The New Science of Motion” (ref. 2).

  54. Drake, “Galileo’s Discovery” (ref. 3).

  55. Galileo, Two New Sciences (ref. 1), 203, 160.

  56. Norton and Roberts, “Galileo’s Refutation” (ref. 21).

  57. Mach, The Science of Mechanics (ref. 21).

  58. Giovanni Andres, cited in Drake, “Uniform Acceleration” (ref. 20), 41–42.

  59. Drake, “Uniform Acceleration” (ref. 20), 27–28.

  60. Swerdlow, “Galileo’s Mechanics” (ref. 32), 36; Galileo, Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems – Ptolemaic & Copernican, trans. Stillman Drake (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967).

  61. Galileo, Dialogue (ref. 60), 228–29.

  62. Swerdlow, “Galileo’s Mechanics” (ref. 23).

  63. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 365.

  64. Damerow et al., Exploring the Limits (ref. 5), 366.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mariana Faria Brito Francisquini.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Penha Maria Cardozo Dias researches on the foundations of classical physics, using the history of physics to clarify meanings of concepts and laws. Mariana Francisquini teaches at the Instituto Federal do Rio de Janeiro. Her main interests are history of physics and physics education. Carlos Eduardo Aguiar is associate professor of physics at the Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro. His main research interests are nuclear physics and physics education. Marta Feijó Barroso is professor of physics and the Universidade Federal do Rio de Janeiro and researches on physics education.

Appendices

Appendix A: The Proof of the Parabola \(\varvec{v^{2} = 2gD}\) (Folio 152r)

In this appendix, the proof in folio 152r is reproduced,63 and recast in the notation in figure 5 and table 2.

First Paragraph

Let \(ba\) be to \(ad\) as \(da\) to \(ac\) and let \(be\) be the gradus velocitatis in \(b\).

$$\left[ {\frac{ba}{ad} = \frac{da}{ac}\;and\;be = v_{b} } \right]$$

In the paragraph, \(ad\) is defined as the mean proportional between the distances \(D_{ac} = ac\) and \(D_{ab} = ab\):

$$ad \equiv D_{mp} = \sqrt {D_{1} D_{2} } \equiv \sqrt {ba \times ca}$$

That \(be = v_{b}\) follows from the construction of the motions in table 1 or table 2, and the double distance rule.

Second Paragraph

And let \(be\) be to \(cf\) as \(ba\) to \(ad\), then \(cf\) will be the gradus velocitatis in \(c\):

$$\left[ {\frac{be}{cf} = \frac{ba}{ad}\;{\text{then}}\;cf = v_{c} } \right]$$

With the notation in table 2, this is:

$$\frac{{v_{b} }}{cf} = \frac{{D_{ab} }}{{D_{mp} }}\;{\text{then}}\;cf = v_{c}$$
(11)

The result follows from the construction in table 2, and the double distance rule.

Third Paragraph

Since therefore as \(ca\) is to \(ad\), \(cf\)is to \(be\), also \(\square ac\) will be to \(\square ad\) as \(\square cf\) to \(\square be.\)

$$\left[ {\frac{ca}{ad} = \frac{cf}{be}\;{\text{then}}\;\frac{{ac^{2} }}{{ad^{2} }} = \frac{{cf^{2} }}{{be^{2} }}} \right]$$

With the notation in table 2, this is:

$$\frac{{D_{ca} }}{{D_{mp} }} = \frac{{v_{c} }}{{v_{b} }} {\text{then}} \frac{{D_{ca}^{2} }}{{D_{mp}^{2} }} = \frac{{v_{c}^{2} }}{{v_{b}^{2} }}$$
(12)

The result follows, making \(v_{c} = cf\) (equation 11).

Fourth Paragraph, Part 1

But as \(\square ca\) to \(\square ad\), \(ca\) is to \(ab\);

$$\left[ {\frac{{ca^{2} }}{{ad^{2} }} = \frac{ca}{ab}} \right] .$$

The result follows from the definition of mean proportional:

$$\frac{{D_{ca}^{2} }}{{D_{mp}^{2} }} = \frac{{D_{ac} }}{{D_{ab} }}$$
(13)

Fourth Paragraph, Part 2

But therefore as \(ca\) to \(ab\), \(\square cf\) is to \(\square be\). Therefore, the points \(e\), \(f\) are on a parabola

$$ \left[ {\frac{ca}{ab} = \frac{{cf^{2} }}{{be^{2} }}} \right] $$

From equation 12 and equation 13:

$$\frac{{D_{ca} }}{{D_{ab} }} = \frac{{v_{c}^{2} }}{{v_{b}^{2} }}$$
(14)

Appendix B: The Proof of the Straight Line v = gt (Folio 91v)

In this appendix, the proof in folio 91v is reproduced,64 and recast in the notation in figure 3 and table 1.

The folio starts with a proof for the composition of velocities. Then Galileo proposes a problem:

In motion from rest the moment of velocity and the time of this motion are intensified in the same ratio

$$\left[ {{\text{to prove that}}:\frac{{v_{c} }}{{v_{b} }} = \frac{{t_{ac} }}{{t_{ac} }}} \right]$$

For let there be a motion through ab from rest in a, and let an arbitrary point c be assumed; and let it be posited that ac is the time of fall through ac, and the moment of the acquired speed in c is also as ac,

$$\left[ {t_{ac} = ac\quad v_{c} \propto ac} \right]$$

[Explanation: in uniform motion, for fixed \(v_{c}\), it is \(d \propto t\). Then \(d_{1} \equiv cd = 2D_{ac}\) (\(v_{c}\) constant on \(cd\)), the time is \(t_{ac} \propto d_{1} = 2ac\). This is the “conflation” observed by Palmerino.]

and assume again any point \(b\): I say that the time of fall through \(ab\) to the time through \(ac\) will be as the moment of velocity in \(b\) to the moment in \(c\)

$$\left[ {\frac{{t_{ab} }}{{t_{ac} }} = \frac{{v_{b} }}{{v_{c} }}} \right]$$

Let \(as\) be the mean [proportional] between \(ba\) and \(ac\);

$$\left[ {as = \sqrt {ba \times ac} } \right]$$

and since the time of fall through \(ac\) was set to be \(ac\), as will be the time through \(ab\): it thus has to be shown that the moment of speed in \(c\) to the moment of speed in \(b\) is as \(ac\) to \(as.\)

[Explanation: because it is \(\frac{{t_{ac} }}{{t_{ab} }} = \frac{{d_{1} }}{{d_{2} }}\), it has to be proved that \(\frac{ac}{as} = \sqrt {\frac{ac}{ab}} = \sqrt {\frac{{d_{1} }}{{d_{2} }}} = \frac{{v_{b} }}{{v_{c} }}.\)]

The Proof

First Paragraph

Assume the horizontal [line] \(cd\) to be double \(ca\), but \(be\) to be double \(ba\): it follows from what has been shown, that the [body] falling through \(ac\), deflected into the horizontal \(cd\), will traverse \(cd\) in uniform motion in an equal time as it also traversed \(ac\) in naturally accelerated motion; and, similarly, it follows that \(be\) is traversed in the same time as \(ab\): but the time of \(ab\) itself is \(as\): therefore, the horizontal [line] \(be\) is traversed in the time \(as\)

$$\left[ {cd = 2ca,be = 2ba} \right]$$

Second Paragraph

Let \(eb\) be to \(bl\) as the time \(sa\) is to the time \(ac\); and since the motion through \(be\) is uniform, the space \(bl\) will be traversed in the time \(ac\) according to the moment of speed in \(b\): but according to the moment of speed in \(c\), in the same time \(ac\) the space \(cd\) will be traversed; but the moments of speed are to one another as the spaces, which according to these moments are traversed in the same time: therefore the moment of speed in \(c\) is to the moment of speed in \(b\) as \(dc\) to \(bl\).

The text states relations among the uniform motions that follow from table 7:

$$\frac{cd}{bl} = \frac{{v_{c} }}{{v_{b} }}\;{\text{and}}\;\frac{bl}{be} = \frac{{t_{ac} }}{{t_{ab} }}.$$
(15)
Table 7 Double distance rule in the accelerated motion in figure 3

When Galileo refers to ac and as also as time, he is using what Palmerino calls “conflation” of coordinates. This shows that Galileo requires a separated vertical line to represent time. In the Two New Sciences, he uses the coordinates speed versus time, and an independent line for distance.

Third Paragraph, Part 1

But as \(dc\) to \(be\), so are their halves, i.e., \(ca\) to \(ab:\)

$$\left[ {\frac{dc}{be} = \frac{2ca}{2ab}} \right].$$

The uniform motions are associated with uniformly accelerated motions, using the double distance rule:

$$\frac{{D_{ac} }}{{D_{ab} }} = \frac{ac}{ab} = \frac{dc}{be}$$
(16)

Third Paragraph, Part 2

But as \(eb\) to \(bl\), so \(ba\) to \(as\):

$$\left[ {\frac{eb}{bl} = \frac{ba}{as} {\text{that is }}\frac{{t_{ab} }}{{t_{ac} }} = \frac{ba}{as} } \right].$$

This result uses the double distance rule: \(\frac{{d_{2} }}{{d_{mp} }} = \frac{{2D_{ab} }}{{2D_{mp} }}\); from equation 16 and table 7

$$\frac{{D_{ba} }}{{D_{mp} }} \equiv \sqrt {\frac{{D_{ba} }}{{D_{ca} }}} = \frac{{t_{ab} }}{{t_{ac} }}.$$
(17)

Third Paragraph, Part 3

Therefore, by the same [ex aequali], as \(dc\) to \(bl\), so \(ca\) to \(as\): that is, as the moment of speed in \(c\) to the moment of speed in \(b\), so \(ca\) to \(as\),

$$\left[ { \frac{dc}{bl} = \frac{ca}{as} {\text{that is}} \frac{{v_{c} }}{{v_{b } }} = \frac{ca}{as}} \right].$$

This is analogous to paragraph 3, part 2: from the double distance rule: \(\frac{{d_{1} }}{{d_{mp} }} = \frac{{2D_{1} }}{{2D_{mp} }}\); from equation 16 and table 7

$$\frac{{D_{ca} }}{{D_{mp} }} \equiv \sqrt {\frac{{D_{ba} }}{{D_{ca} }}} = \frac{{v_{c} }}{{v_{b} }}.$$
(18)

Third Paragraph, Part 4

That is, the time through \(ca\) to the time through \(ab\). Quod erat demonstrandum

$$\left[ {\frac{{v_{c} }}{{v_{b} }} = \frac{{t_{c} }}{{t_{b} }}} \right].$$

This follows from equation 17 and equation 18.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dias, P.M.C., Francisquini, M.F.B., Aguiar, C.E. et al. What the Middle-Aged Galileo Told the Elderly Galileo: Galileo’s Search for the Laws of Fall. Phys. Perspect. 21, 194–221 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00016-019-00243-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00016-019-00243-y

Keywords

Navigation