Skip to main content

From Carl Menger to John R. Commons: Human Volition and Value Theory in Institutional Economics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Contemporary Meanings of John R. Commons’s Institutional Economics

Part of the book series: Evolutionary Economics and Social Complexity Science ((EESCS,volume 5))

Abstract

In the 1927 manuscript of Institutional Economics, John R. Commons explicitly referenced Menger’s functional analysis of the human–goods relationship developed in Grundsätze der Volkswirtschaftslehre. By chronologically scrutinizing the Menger–Commons link in the writing of Institutional Economics, this chapter aims to show the methodological inheritance that influenced the value theory of Commons. Commons had been inspired by Austrian value theory during his youth via interpretations of Clark and Smart, especially with regard to the ideas of human volition and social power. After obtaining rich working experiences in the legal and political fields, but encountering setbacks in his attempts to theorize those experiences, Commons began to scrutinize Menger’s functional analysis in Grundsätze, and this scrutiny informed the construction of his volitional theory of “reasonable value.” Menger’s functional analysis was important for Commons because it proposed the conditional logic that drives the value determination process in a power relationship between human subjective evaluation and the objective conditions of goods. Additionally, Commons was inspired by the revised portions of the second edition of Grundsätze, especially the distinction between the “economizing” and “technological” directions within the economy, and the explanation of the process through which institutions emerge from the resolution of “conflicts of interest.” Criticizing the value theory of Menger for being restricted to the field of scarcity, Commons attempted to develop it by introducing other social powers in production, bargaining and legislation. Commons’ theory of reasonable value can be understood as an extension of Menger’s subjectivist value theory based on conditional logic, because it describes human volitional actions under social situations that involve collective action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    More interesting is that Wieser and Böhm-Bawerk, the second generation of Austrians, and Clark, the introducer of Austrian theory to the USA, also participated in the seminars of Knies at Heidelberg. In that sense, one can say that Commons, Elly, and early Austrians shared the “habitus” of the economics of the German-speaking world.

  2. 2.

    Commons refers to Menger 65 times in the draft manuscript of 1927 and 57 times in the final book published in 1934; he refers to Wieser 36 times in the 1927 draft and 24 times in the 1934 book; he refers to Böhm-Bawerk six times in the 1927 draft and 64 times in the 1934 book.

  3. 3.

    In The Distribution of Wealth (1893), Commons made no reference to Menger. Meanwhile, in Legal Foundations of Capitalism (1924), Commons referred to Menger only twice, when describing the marginal revolution that followed from the work of other economists such as Jevons, Walras, and Gossen (Commons 1924, pp.4, 40). By developing the idea of marginal utility, Menger, Jevons, and Walras were considered to have overcome the classical value theory that explains value as deriving from certain sources such as labor or usefulness. Marginal explanations explain a paradox of Smith—why diamonds are highly valued despite having no use value, while water is not valued despite being essential to human survival. Marginal theory was introduced to the USA quite early, and marginal utility is explained in the chapter titled “Consumption” in Elly’s textbook from 1893. Undoubtedly, the young Commons had evaluated Menger as one of the greatest economists in history, but he showed no special interest in the Grundsätze until the 1924 draft of Institutional Economics.

  4. 4.

    The preoccupation of the Austrian school with an individualistic approach methodology was first expanded by Schumpeter (1908) and then confirmed by Mises, from the third generation of the Austrian school, whose epistemological book declares social science should start from “human behaviors to achieve their ends” (Mises 1933/1960, 1962). The neo-Austrians who followed Mises can be called methodological individualists, but this label should not be applied to the first and second generations of the Austrian school. Some evidence exists that these neo-Austrians did not regard individuals as absolute final factors; when Menger (1871) discusses public or national wealth (Volksvermögen) and wants, he regards states, provinces, and associations as having needs as collective independent economic agents (p.112): in Book 6 of Natural Value, Wieser regards states from the perspective of independent evaluation (pp.217–243).

  5. 5.

    Commons (1934a) evaluated Wieser and proposed a bidirectional theory of power. Referring to two books by Wieser—Natural Value (1889) and Law of Power (1926)—Commons states, “[it] turns out that first book was individualistic, the second collectivistic. The first was a relation of man to nature, the second a relation of man to man. The unit of the first was a commodity that satisfies wants, the unit of the second was a moral, monopolistic, or violent force that collectively subdues the individual… In the law of value Wieser sought what is permanent and enduring under all historical and institutional changes… he finds that history is the history of collective suppression of individuals” (p. 677–678).

  6. 6.

    Commons described his motivations in writing the volume as stemming from his working experiences, particularly in relation to “labor problems and problems connected with regulation and valuation of public utility,” after his first attempts in The Distribution of Wealth to combine Böhm-Bawek’s hedonic psychology with legal rights (Commons 1924, p.vii).

  7. 7.

    Commons (1924) repeatedly uses the term “power” (this term appears in the work 1045 times) to explain the importance of political and legal process in economic value.

  8. 8.

    One exception was Commons’ teacher Mitchell (1924), who wrote an admiring review that presented Commons as a reformer of conventional economics, developing original ideas based on his experiences of taxation, labor reforms, and legislation. Mitchell’s review even observed that innovative ideas are sometimes difficult to understand.

  9. 9.

    Most of these paragraphs appear in the 1934 manuscript with some revisions. İn the 1934 manuscript, “physical economists, from Locke to Marx” is revised to read “from Locke to the end of the nineteenth Century” (Commons 1934a, p.16).

  10. 10.

    Yagi (2004) also discusses that in the process of writing Grundsätze, Menger found in relational analysis focused on humans and goods the “teleological relationship of human action and existential causality of humans and the external world at the same time” (p. 62).

  11. 11.

    Interestingly, the German term “Verfügung,” which Commons translates as “control,” comes from verb “verfügen”—a combination of the emphatic marker “ver” and the verb “combine.” Dingwall and Hoselitz (1871) translate the same sentence as “command of the thing” in the English translation of Principles of Economics. Commons interpreted the derivative word “Verfügbar qualitäten” as meaning “quantity available.”

  12. 12.

    The title “Scarcity and Efficiency” was proposed in the 1927 draft. The title was changed to “Efficiency and Scarcity” in the 1934 published version.

  13. 13.

    Grundsätze was structured to reformulate the methods of the German historicists, especially Roscher, who attempted to establish “Volkswirtschaftlehre” (the theory of the national economy) through integrative social science, including the national legal system and transaction customs, to be more “scientific” by separating economic aspects from others.

  14. 14.

    As Yagi (2004) discusses, Menger introduced relational analysis of humans and goods based on the economic traditions of the contemporary German-speaking world. For instance, Roscher and Knies wrote landmark works on economics in the German-speaking world of the day, starting with the theory of goods, which analyzes the relationships between humans and goods, and involved philosophical thoughts on humans and their relationships with the external world (p.62).

  15. 15.

    Although neither the terms “internal power” nor “external power” are used by Menger, I have introduced them for clarity. Menger uses the terms “subjective” and “objective” to mean almost the same thing.

  16. 16.

    For comparison of the revisions and additions in the second edition of Grundsätze relative to the first edition, see the editor’s preface in Menger (1923), written by his son Karl Menger Jr.

  17. 17.

    Menger (1923) criticizes Smith and Ricardo for not distinguishing the technological and economic aspects of goods, and for concentrating on the technological aspect in their economic inquiry, which should have been directed mainly at the allocation of scarce goods. Both the 1927 draft and the final published version of Institutional Economics contain similar lines of criticism: Commons (1927, 1934a) criticizes “physical” economists such as Ricardo, Marx, and Malthus for focusing only on the “economy of engineering” and confusing economic aspects with technological ones.

  18. 18.

    Commons had already referred to both topics in Legal Foundations of Capitalism (1924), but he conveyed clear distinctions in Institutional Economics.

  19. 19.

    The direction of this discussion resembles arguments put forward by Commons. However, Menger went no further than the legal origins of property rights, whereas Commons made the concept of institutions being created by the resolution of conflicts of interest central to his analysis. This may partly reflect a difference between the continental system of statute law and the Anglo-American common law system: Menger had in mind the legal system of central Europe, where laws were relatively static once enacted, whereas Commons was exposed to the American common law system, wherein dynamic processes emerge from custom. Thus Menger observed a process by which legal order emerges from custom or a historical situation, but he regarded the legal order as rather fixed.

References

  • Böhm-Bawerk, E.v. 1891/1930. Positive Theory of Capital. Trans. W. Smart. New York: G.E. Stechert & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boulding, K.E. 1957. A New Look at Institutionalism. American Economic Review 47: 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S. 2004. Microeconomics: Behavior, Institutions, and Evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, J.B. 1886. Philosophy of Wealth: Economic Principles Newly Formulated. Boston: Ginn & Co..

    Google Scholar 

  • Commons, J.R. 1893. The Distribution of Wealth. New York/London: Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1924/1959. Legal Foundations of Capitalism. Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1927. Reasonable Value: A Theory of Volitional Economics. Manuscript. Collection of the Kyoto Prefectural Library. Call mark: /331.04/C85/, Material code: 1102508007.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934a. Institutional Economics: Its Place in Political Economy. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934b. Myself. Wisconsin: The University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1950. The Economics of Collective Action. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elly, T.R., T.S. Adams, and M. Lorenz. 1893/1919. Outlines of Economics. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, W.H. 1919. The Institutional Approach to Economic Theory. The American Economic Review 9(1): 309–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G.M. 2004. The Evolution of Institutional Economics: Agency, Structure and Darwinism in American Institutionalism. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lowenberg, A.D. 1990. Neoclassical Economics as a Theory of Politics and Institutions. Cato Journal 9(3): 619–639.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marangos, J. 2007. John Rogers Commons on Power. Journal of Political Economy 35(4): 50–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menger, C. 1871/1976. Principles of Economics (Grundsätze der Volkswirtschaftslehre). Trans. J. Dingwall and B.F. Hoselitz. Institute for Humane Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1883. Untersuchungen über die Methode der Socialwissenschaften, und der Politischen Oekonomie insbesondere (Investigations into the Method of the Social Sciences with special reference to economics). Leibzig: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1923. Grundsätze der Volkswirtschaftslehre 2. Aufl (Principles of Economics, second edition), mit einem Geleitwort von Richard Schüller, aus dem Nachlass herausgegeben von Karl Menger. Wien. Leipzig: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milford, K. 1990. Menger’s Methodology. In Carl Menger and His Legacy in Economics. Annual supplement to History of Political Economy 22: 215–240. Ed. Bruce J. Caldwell. Durham/London: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises, L.V. 1933/1960. Grundprobleme der Nationalökonomie: Untersuchungen über Verfahren, Aufgaben und Inhalt der Wirtschafts und Gesellschaftslehre. Epistemological Problems of Economics (trans: Reisman, G.). Princeton: D. Van Nostrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1962. The Ultimate Foundation of Economic Science: An Essay on Method. Princeton: D.Van Nostrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, W.C. 1924. Commons on the Legal Foundations of Capitalism. The American Economic Review 14(2): 240–253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palermo, G. 1999. The Convergence of Austrian Economics and New Institutional Economics: Methodological Inconsistencies and Political Motivations. Journal of Economic Issues 33(2): 277–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramstad, Y. 1995. John R. Commons’s Puzzling Inconsequentiality as an Economic Theorist. Journal of Economic Issues 29(4).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter, J.A. 1908. Das Wesen und der Hauptinhalt der theoretischen Nationalökonomie (The Nature and Essence of Economic Theory). Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 1977. Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic Theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs 6(4): 317–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sharfman, I.L. 1925. Commons’s Legal Foundations of Capitalism. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 39(2): 300–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. 1996. The Sciences of the Artificial, 3rd ed. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, W. 1891/1931. An Introduction to the Theory of Value: on the Lines of Menger, Wieser, and Böhm-Bawek. London: Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tokumaru, N. 2015. Wieser’s Unity of Thought. Journal of the History of Economic Thought 37(4): 583–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. 1989. Carl Menger’s Evolutionary and John R. Commons’ Collective Action Approach to Institutions: a Comparison. Review of Political Economy 1(3): 334–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wieser F. v. 1889. Natural Value (Der natürliche Werth, Wien: Alfred Hölder). Trans. Christian A. Malloch. 1956. New York: A.M. Kelley

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1914/2003. Social Economics. Trans. A.F. Hinrichs. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1926/1983. The Law of Power . Trans. W.E. Kuhn. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yagi, K. 1981. Commentary: Menger’s Investigation and the Revision of Principles of Economics, in Carl Menger, General Theory of Economics (second edition of Principle of Economics) (Japanese translation). Tokyo: Misuzu Shobo (in Japanese).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Economic Thought in Vienna: From the Menger Brothers to the Twentieth Century. Kyoto: Minerva Shobo (in Japanese).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was supported by the Japan Society for the Promotion of Science (JSPS) and the KAKENHI Grant-in-Aid for Scientific Research (B) (grant number 26285048). I sincerely thank Dr. Ryuichiro Terakawa, Dr. Taizo Yamamoto, and Professor Hiroshi Osaka for providing fruitful comments and criticisms, according to which I have considerably revised this chapter. Naturally, all mistakes are mine.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Natsuka Tokumaru .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tokumaru, N. (2017). From Carl Menger to John R. Commons: Human Volition and Value Theory in Institutional Economics. In: Uni, H. (eds) Contemporary Meanings of John R. Commons’s Institutional Economics. Evolutionary Economics and Social Complexity Science, vol 5. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-3202-8_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-3202-8_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-10-3201-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-10-3202-8

  • eBook Packages: Economics and FinanceEconomics and Finance (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics