Skip to main content

The (In)Determinism of Biological Evolution: Where Does the Stochastic Character of Evolutionary Theory Come From?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbook of Evolutionary Thinking in the Sciences

Abstract

Evolutionary theory is readily acknowledged to be stochastic in that it only enables one to make probabilistic predictions, for instance regarding changes in genotypic frequencies within given populations. However, the very origin of this stochastic character has been the focus of much philosophical debate. Is it due to an inherent indeterminism? Or rather to epistemic limitations? In this chapter, we review some of the major arguments that have been exchanged on the topic recently. We argue that settling the issue would require first to answer the question of the relative contribution of the different factors of evolution. This leads us to defend a more nuanced vision of the origin of the stochastic character of evolutionary theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Sometimes, the main actors in this debate about the theory of evolution use different terms. As a matter of fact, Rosenberg, Horan and Graves talk about the “statistical” character of evolutionary theory; Brandon and Carson often use the expression “indeterministic theory of evolution”. Following Beatty (1984), we have decided to use the term “stochastic” in order to underline the fact that evolutionary theory is a indeed theory which, given the same initial conditions, allows one to make predictions not about one unique outcome but about the probabilistic distribution of many such outcomes.

  2. 2.

    For an introduction to the notion of “fitness”. Concerning the propensity interpretation of probability, see for instance Popper (1959).

  3. 3.

    A “dispositional property” is a propensity that manifests itself when some conditions are met; thus, for instance, a vase is fragile in so far as, if it were to fall down on a hard surface, it would break. Dispositional properties are often opposed to “categorical” properties (e.g., the property for an object of being spherical, property that does depend on the state of this object in the real world and not on some conditional counterfactual proposition).

  4. 4.

    A similar example at the intracellular level is the phenotypic variation, in isogenic populations in a homogeneous and constant environment or in an individual over time, that is due to stochastic fluctuations in gene expression (or noise) (See Merlin 2009).

  5. 5.

    Lateral gene transfer, also called horizontal gene transfer, brings together a set of processes that allow an organism to exchange genetic material with another organism without being its descendant. This phenomenon is relatively frequent in some unicellular organisms (See Thomas Heams’ chapter on heredity, Chap. 3, this volume).

  6. 6.

    In his article on natural selection and random genetic drift, Beatty argues that it is not interesting to ask the question of whether natural evolution is the result of selection or drift; rather, one has to ask which relative role is respectively of selection and of drift.

References

  • Beatty, J. (1984). Chance and natural selection. Philosophy of Science, 51(2), 183–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J., & Finsen, S. (1989). Rethinking the propensity interpretation of fitness: A peek inside Pandora’s box. In M. Ruse (Ed.), What the philosophy of biology is today: Essays for David Hull. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D. (1952). “A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of ‘Hidden’ variables”, I and II. Physical Review, 85, 166–193.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. (1978). Adaptation and evolutionary theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 9, 181–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. (1990). Adaptation and environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R., & Carson, S. (1996). The indeterministic character of evolutionary theory: No ‘no hidden variables’ proof but no room for determinism either. Philosophy of Science, 63, 315–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cain, A. J. (1979). Introduction to general discussion. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, B205, 599–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doolittle, F. (1999). Phylogenetic classification and the universal tree. Science, 284, 2124–2128.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Faye, J. (2008). Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/qm-copenhagen/

  • Futuyama, D. J. (1979). Evolutionary biology. Sunderland: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (1997). Probable causes and the distinction between subjective and objective chance. Noûs, 31(4), 496–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, B. (2001). Selection, indeterminism, and evolutionary theory. Philosophy of Science, 68, 518–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S. (2008). Bohmian mechanics. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2008) Edition, URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/qm-bohm/

  • Graves, L., Horan, B. L., & Rosenberg, A. (1999). Is indeterminism the source of the statistical character of evolutionary theory? Philosophy of Science, 66, 140–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartl, D. L., & Clark, A. G. (1989). Principles of population genetics (2ème Éd.). Sunderland: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodge, M. J. S. (1987). Natural selection as a causal, empirical, and probabilistic theory. In L. Krüger (Ed.), The probabilistic revolution (pp. 233–270). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horan, B. (1994). The statistical character of evolutionary biology. Philosophy of Science, 61, 76–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, T. (2009). De la diversité des probabilités. In J.-J. Kupiec (Ed.), Le hasard au coeur de la cellule. Paris: Syllepse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merlin, F. (2009). Pour une interprétation objective des probabilités dans les modèles stochastiques de l’expression génétique. In J.-J. Kupiec (Ed.), Le hasard au coeur de la cellule. Paris: Syllepse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mills, S. K., & Beatty, J. H. (1979). The propensity interpretation of fitness. Philosophy of Science, 46, 263–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein, R. (1996). Random drift and the omniscient viewpoint. Philosophy of Science, 63, S10–S18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein, R. (2000), Is the evolutionary process deterministic or indeterministic? An argument for agnosticism. Presented at the biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vancouver, Canada, November 2000. http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/millstein/papers/Millstein_agnosticism.pdf

  • Millstein, R. (2002). Are random drift and natural selection conceptually distinct? Biology and Philosophy, 17, 33–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein, R. (2003). How not to argue for the indeterminism of evolution: A look at two recent attempts to settle the issue. In A. Hüttermann (Ed.), Determinism in physics and biology (pp. 91–107). Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1959). The propensity interpretation of probability. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, X(37), 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (1988). Is the theory of natural selection a statistical theory? Canadian Journal of Philosophy (Suppl), 14, 187–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (1994). Instrumental biology or the disunity of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (2001). Discussion note: Indeterminism, probability, and randomness in evolutionary theory. Philosophy of Science, 68, 536–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden, J. (1979). Theory of population genetics and evolutionary ecology: An introduction. New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1984). The nature of selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1993). Philosophy of biology. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamos, D. N. (2001). Quantum indeterminism and evolutionary biology. Philosophy of Science, 68, 164–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Timofeef-Ressovsky, N. W. (1940). Mutations and geographical variation. In J. S. Huxley (Ed.), The new systematics. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2005). Indeterminism in neurobiology. Philosophy of Science, 71, 663–674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank the audience of the “PhilBio Seminar” at the IHPST where an earlier version of this paper was presented in 2007. C.M. also acknowledges financial support from the Institut de France (grant from the Fondation Louis D).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christophe Malaterre .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Malaterre, C., Merlin, F. (2015). The (In)Determinism of Biological Evolution: Where Does the Stochastic Character of Evolutionary Theory Come From?. In: Heams, T., Huneman, P., Lecointre, G., Silberstein, M. (eds) Handbook of Evolutionary Thinking in the Sciences. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9014-7_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics