Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy ((SLAP,volume 95))

  • 799 Accesses

Abstract

Properties as set of individuals, or of features? Worlds, or propositions? Time-points, or events? Preference, or choice? Natural kinds, or similarity? In modern analytic philosophy it is standard to take (i) individuals as basic, and properties as defined in terms of them; (ii) worlds as basic, and propositions as defined in terms of them; (iii) time-points as basic, and intervals as constructions out of them; (iv) preference as basic, and optimal choice as defined in terms of them; and (v) natural kinds as basic, and similarities as defined in terms of them. In this chapter we show that in all cases the other direction is possible as well. Most of the constructions used are well-known. But by putting them collectively on the table we hope to show that the constructions have something in common, and that it is not always clear which perspective is ontologically less committing.

We would like to thank the anonymous reviewers for this volume, as well as the volume editors

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    If we think of the extensional counterpart, this means that ‘some bike is red’ is true not because there actually exists a red bike, but rather that it is possible that such a bike exists. And indeed, what Leibniz considers to be the extension of a term (a set of individuals scattered around all worlds) is very much what in possible worlds semantics is its intension (cf. Leibniz 1966 and Ishiguro 1972, p. 49).

  2. 2.

    This is what he believed, but he was not able to work out a full semantics for syllogisms with complex terms.

  3. 3.

    Interestingly, Allen and Hayes define the notion of ‘meet’ ‘\(:\)’, as follows:

    \(I{:}J\) iff\(_{def}\)\(I < J \wedge \lnot \exists K,L(I < K \wedge K \sim L \wedge L < J)\).

  4. 4.

    For a necessary condition, see Lück (2006). In this paper it is also proven under which circumstances one can generate a continuous order of instants.

  5. 5.

    Of course, it is not necessarily to define intervals as having open beginnings and closed ends. The other way is possible as well. Just to assume that it any convex set is an interval doesn’t give rise to endless descent even if \(\langle T,<^{**}\rangle \) is dense.

  6. 6.

    This axiom is a finitary version of Sen’s Property \(\gamma \).

  7. 7.

    Interestingly enough, this is exactly analogue to what Klein (1980) intended to do in linguistics: the meaning of ‘taller than’ (or ‘better than’) should be defined in terms of the meaning of ‘tall’ (or ‘good’), not that of ‘tallest’ (or ‘best’).

  8. 8.

    The existence of maximal similarity sets is, in general, guaranteed by Zorn’s Lemma.

  9. 9.

    This is so, because in order for \(f(\langle 1,2\rangle ) \cap f(\langle 2,3\rangle ) \not = \emptyset \) it must be that \(\exists X: X \in f(1) \cap f(2) \cap f(3)\) such that \(\{1,2,3\} \subseteq X\), see below.

  10. 10.

    Only after writing this chapter we discovered Paseau (2012), where something very similar was worked out very precisely. Paseau argues that resemblance similarity can be saved, but that the cost of assuming similarity relations between sets of individuals is probably a too high price to pay for a nominalist.

  11. 11.

    The empty set will be similar to no other set.

  12. 12.

    Because if \(p \in X\), it follows that \(p \subseteq \bigcup X\), we can do with only condition (ii). Notice that (ii) entails that all individuals in \(\bigcup X\) resemble each other.

References

  • Allen, J. F., & Hayes, P. J. (1985). A common-sense theory of time. In A. Joshi (Ed.), Proceedings of the the Ninth Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, Los Altos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1941). Basic works. In R. McKeon (Ed.) New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1989). Universals: An opinionated introduction. Oxford: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. (1959). Rational choice functions and orderings. Economica, 26, 121–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berge, C. (1989). Hypergraphs. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1923), Die Quasizerlegung. Ein Verfahren zur Ordnung nichthomogener Mengen mit den Mitteln der Beziehungslehre. Unpublished manuscript RC-081-04-01, University of Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1928). Der logische Aufbau der Welt. Berlin: Weltkreis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1947). Meaning and necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. C. (1970). Intransitive indifference with unequal indifference intervals. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 7, 144–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual spaces. Cambridge: MIT.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glashoff, K. (to appear). An intensional Leibniz semantics for Aristotelian logic. The Review of Symbolic Logic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1972). Seven strictures on similarity. In N. Goodman (Ed.), Problems and projects (pp. 437–446). Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1953). The structure of appearance (2nd ed.). Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ishiguro, H. (1972). Leibniz’ Philosophy of Logic and Language. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H. (1979). Events, instants and temporal reference. In R. Bäuerle et al. (Eds.), Semantics form different points of view (pp. 131–175). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, E. (1980). The semantics of positive and comparative adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4, 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (1981). Partition and revision: The semantics of counterfactuals. Journals of Philosophical Logic, 10, 242–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. (1686). Discours de Métaphysique, (first published in English by Open Court, 1902).

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. (1966). Rules from which a decision can be made, by means of numbers, about the validity of inferences and about the forms and moods of categorical syllogisms. In G. H. R. Parkinson (ed.), Leibniz: Logical papers (pp. 25–32). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. (2007). A new analysis of Quasianalysis. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 36, 181–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work on the theory of universals. Australian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 85–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lück, U. (2006). Continuous time goes by Russell. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 47, 397–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mormann, T. (2009). New work for Carnap’s quasi-analysis. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 38, 249–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paseau, A. (2012). Resemblance theories of properties. Philosophical Studies, 157, 361–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1941). Republic (F. Cornford, Trans). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1969). Natural kinds. In W. V. Quine (Ed.), Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 114–138). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1954). Leibniz’s interpretation of his logical calculi. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 19, 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (1999). Resemblance nominalism and the imperfect community. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59, 965–982.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2002). Resemblance Nominalism: A solution to the problem of universals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. London: Home University Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1914). Our knowledge of the external world. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1936). On order in time. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 3, 216–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1971). Choice functions and revealed preference. The Review of Economic Studies, 38, 307–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory, American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series (pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, S. K. (1984). On constructing instants from events. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 13, 85–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, R. (1981). Counterfactuals without possible worlds. Journals of Philosophical Logic, 10, 453–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J. (1982). Later than late: On the logical origin of the temporal order. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63, 193–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J. (1991). The logic of time. Synthese Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, R. (2011). Semi-orders and satisficing behavior. Synthese, 179, 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veltman, F. (1976). Prejudices, presuppositions, and the theory of counterfactuals. In J. Groenendijk & M. Stokhof (Eds.), Amsterdam papers in formal grammar. Proceedings of the 1st Amsterdam Colloquium (pp. 248–281), Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiener, N. (1914). A contribution to the theory of relative position. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 17, 441–449.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert van Rooij .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rooij, R.v., Schulz, K. (2014). A Question of Priority. In: McCready, E., Yabushita, K., Yoshimoto, K. (eds) Formal Approaches to Semantics and Pragmatics. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol 95. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-8813-7_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics