Skip to main content

Abstract

Climate change is changing not only our physical world, but also our intellectual, social, and moral worlds. We are realizing that our situation is profoundly unsafe, interdependent, and uncertain. What, then, does climate change demand of economists, as human beings and as professionals? A discipline of economics based on Enlightenment notions of mechanism and disembodied rationality is not suited to present problems. This essay suggests three major requirements: first, that we take action; second, that we work together; and third, that we focus on avoiding the worst, rather than obtaining the optimal. The essay concludes with suggestions of specific steps that economists should take as researchers, teachers, and in our other roles.

Originally published as: Nelson, J.A. 2013. Ethics and the economist: What climate change demands of us, Ecological Economics, 85(0), 145–154.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, for example, DeCanio (2003), Howarth and Norgaard (1992), Howarth (2003), Dietz and Stern (2008), and Ackerman (2009).

  2. 2.

    In computer-speak, a potentially buggy version of a software package released for testing by prospective users is called a “beta version.” Later releases considered error-free and stable enough for general use (though they will usually be further revised) are often referred to by version numbers.

  3. 3.

    See, as one examples of this now vast literature, Williams and Bargh (2008). Some of these phenomena have been incorporated into behavioral economics (Kahneman, 2003).

  4. 4.

    Weitzman (2010), quoting climate scientist Wallace Broecker.

  5. 5.

    Or, as put by a broader-thinking ethical philosopher: “Ethics is not about what detached, impersonal, objective , rational agents engaged in grand theorizing deduce. Rather, ethics is and should be about what imperfect human beings living in particular historical, socioeconomic contexts can and should do, given those contexts” (Warren, 2000, p. 114).

  6. 6.

    Or, perhaps, we arrive at the judgments opportunistically. Mary C. Gentile recounts this tale of an MBA graduate being asked about what he had learned in a traditional course on business ethics graduate explained that he had “learned all about the models of ethical analysis…and that whenever he encountered a conflict, he could decide what he wanted to do and then select the model of ethical reasoning that would best support his choice” (Gentile, 2010, p. xi).

  7. 7.

    See Frank, Gilovich, et al. (1993) for evidence that economics teaching has this effect.

  8. 8.

    In Nelson (2005) I call this “asymmetric mutuality.”

  9. 9.

    While U.S. culture seems to draw less from these later two than many other cultures, they are not completely absent: “Ask not what your country can do for you,” President John F. Kennedy famously exhorted, “but what you can do for your country.”

  10. 10.

    Perhaps more acceptance by scholars of climate change of such demands on us would also help create better ties between scholars and members of more traditional cultures or moderate religious groups. A haughty attitude of superior secularism, and out-of-hand dismissal of the sorts of rituals and practices that encourage communal and spiritual identities, does not win academics many friends.

  11. 11.

    Exactly how specific environmental structures (e.g., default rules, incentives, framing factors, feedback or lack thereof, and peer pressure) can has been interestingly demonstrated in two recent explorations. Gigerenzer reports on the analysis of the judgments of a group of English magistrates. While perceiving themselves as making complex and rational decisions in the service of justice, the magistrates in actuality acted more in accord with a goal of not being blamed for bad releases of criminal suspects (Gigerenzer, 2007, p. 197). Kitcher, in a refreshing change from philosophies of science that treat science as a pure search for truth, takes into account the more personal goal of a scientist to be “the one who found out the truth” (2011, p. 238), and looks at the implications of this for that social project. A similar study of economists does not come to mind, though a brief study by Margolis suggests that economists are just as prone to the errors of logic that rational choice theorists disdain (Margolis, 1982).

  12. 12.

    Kitcher writes, for example, that “…our Paleolithic predecessors sat down together to decide on the precepts for governing their group life” (2011, p. 42). Relevant to the discussion of the previous section, Kitcher also seems to prioritize reason over emotion when thinking about human motivation. Kitcher assumes that his imagined contemporary human conversationalists, in their weighing of benefits and economic costs, are more moved by the idea of harm to future humans than by issues of species extinction, so that the moral focus should be on the former (2011, pp. 296–7). Yet it seems, empirically, that people are—for better or (mostly, from a humanitarian viewpoint) worse—often more moved by the plight of their pets, to whom they have emotional attachments, and by the plight of big-eyed animals that bring out protective feelings, than by human suffering abroad (especially chronic poverty). While it may be appealing, from the point of view of ethical principles, to disdain the human tendency to focus on “charismatic metafauna” such as baby seals and polar bears, from the point of view of ethical motivation it is not so clear that vividly describing the effects of climate change on Fido and Whiskers is a bad idea.

  13. 13.

    The idea that companies are immune from ethical concerns because their nature is to maximize profits is a creation of economists—strongly preached by Milton Friedman, and weakly preached in all orthodox economics classes. It does not need to be believed (Nelson, forthcoming).

  14. 14.

    See also DeMartino (2011, pp. 144–153) for a discussion of the ethical implications of economists advocating “optimal” but (since much is unknown) potentially damaging structures.

  15. 15.

    For an example of advocacy of this from within the U.S. Environmental Protection Agency, see Carlin (2008).

  16. 16.

    Other economistic approaches are also apparent in his work—for example, in the idea that (a la Schelling) a loss of agriculture in wealthy countries would not hurt much because agricultural production makes up a small proportion of GDP (Sunstein, 2002/2003, p. 36), and in a pervasive framing of the issues in terms of cost–benefit individual freedom (Sunstein, 2005).

  17. 17.

    This definition has been used by Institutional, social, and feminist economists (e.g., Nelson, 1993).

  18. 18.

    For example, Camerer, Loewenstein, et al. (2003), Kahneman (2003), Gui and Sugden (2005), Frey (2008), and Gui and Stanca (2010).

  19. 19.

    This approach is used in teaching materials from the Global Development and Environment Institute (e.g., Goodwin, Nelson, et al., 2008).

  20. 20.

    This includes even prominent women directing important U.S. economic offices: See the comments made by Sheila Bair, chair of the FDIC (in Scherer, 2010).

References

  • Ackerman, F. (2009). Can we afford the future? (The economics of a warming world). London: Zed Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ackerman, F., & Finlayson, I. (2006). The economics of inaction on climate change: A sensitivity analysis. Climate Policy, 6(5), 509–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ackerman, F., Munitz, C. (2011). Climate damages in the FUND model: A disaggregated analysis. Economists for equity and the environment. Working Paper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2006). Valuing policies in response to climate change: Some ethical issues. Supporting research for the stern review on the economics of climate change. http://www.hm-treasury.gov.uk/media/5/0/stern_review_supporting_technical_material_john_broome_261006.pdf

  • Broome, J. (2008). The ethics of climate change. Scientific American, 298(6), 97–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, D., Lemons, J., et al. (2006). The importance of expressly integrating ethical analyses into climate change policy formation. Climate Policy, 5, 549–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. F., Loewenstein, G., et al. (Eds.). (2003). Advances in behavioral economics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlin, A. (2008). Why a different approach is required if global climate change is to be controlled efficiently or even at all. William & Mary Environmental Law and Policy Review, 32(3), 685–758.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuomo, C. (2005). Ethics and the eco/feminist self. In M. E. Zimmerman, J. B. Callicot, K. J. Warren, I. J. Klaver, & J. Clark (Eds.), Environmental philosophy: From animal rights to radical ecology (pp. 194–207). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: G.P. Putnam’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R. (1997). Exploring the minded brain. The Tanner lectures on human values. Salt Lake City: University of Utah

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P. (2005). What do economists analyze and why: Values or facts? Economics and Philosophy, 21, 221–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P. (2007). Economics: A very short introduction. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • DeCanio, S. J. (2003). Economic models of climate change: A critique. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dees, J. G., & Cramton, P. C. (1991). Shrewd bargaining on the moral frontier: Toward a theory of morality in practice. Business Ethics Quarterly, 1(2), 135–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeMartino, G. F. (2011). The economist’s oath: On the need for and content of professional economic ethics. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dietz, S., & Stern, N. (2008). Why economic analysis supports strong action on climate change: A response to the Stern review’s critics. Review of Environmental Economics and Policy, 2(1), 94–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dijksterhuis, A., Bos, M. W., et al. (2006). On making the right choice: The deliberation without-attention effect. Science, 311(5763), 1005–1007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drèze, J., & Sen, A. (1989). Hunger and public action. Oxford, UK: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Folbre, N. (2001). The invisible heart: Economics and family values. New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R. H., Gilovich, T., et al. (1993). Does studying economics inhibit cooperation? Journal of Economic Perspectives, 7(2), 159–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frey, B. S. (2008). Happiness: A revolution in economics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, S. M., Caney, S., et al. (2010). Climate ethics: Essential readings. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentile, M. C. (2010). Giving voice to values: How to speak your mind when you know what’s right. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2007). Gut feelings: The intelligence of the unconscious. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Fiedler, K. (undated). Minds in environments: The potential of an ecological approach to cognition. Berlin, Germany: Max Planck Institute for Human Development.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, C. (1982). In a difference voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. E. (2010). Selling environmental indulgences. In S. M. Gardiner, S. Caney, D. Jamieson, & H. Shue (Eds.), Climate ethics: Essential readings (pp. 231–246). Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, N., Nelson, J. A., et al. (2008). Macroeconomics in context. Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J., & Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where) does moral judgment work? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6(12), 517–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., et al. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gui, B., & Stanca, L. (2010). Happiness and relational goods: Well-being and interpersonal relations in the economic sphere. International Review of Economics, 57(2), 105–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gui, B., & Sugden, R. (Eds.). (2005). Economics and social interaction. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108(4), 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2006). The happiness hypothesis: Finding modern truth in ancient wisdom. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howarth, R. B. (2003). Discounting and sustainability: Towards reconciliation. International Journal of Sustainable Development, 6(1), 87–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howarth, R. B., & Norgaard, R. B. (1992). Environmental valuation under sustainable development. American Economic Review, 82(2), 473–477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iacoboni, M. (2008). Mirroring people: The new science of how we connect with others. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iyengar, S. S., & Lepper, M. R. (2000). When choice is demotivating: Can one desire too much of a good thing? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79(6), 995–1006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaffee, S., & Hyde, J. S. (2000). Gender differences in moral orientation: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 126(5), 703–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, D. (2010). Ethics, public policy, and global warming. In S. M. Gardiner, S. Caney, D. Jamieson, & H. Shue (Eds.), Climate ethics: Essential readings (pp. 77–86). Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1984). The imperative of responsibility: In search of ethics for the technological age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2003). Maps of bounded rationality: Psychology for behavioral economics. American Economic Review, 93, 1449–1475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, E. F. (1985). Reflections on gender and science. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). Science in a democratic society. New York: Prometheus Books. Book Manuscript, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (2004). Don’t think of an elephant! Know your values and frame the debate. White River Junction, VT: Chelsea Green.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, H. (1982). Selfishness, altruism, and rationality: A theory of social choice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, A. (1898). Distribution and exchange. Economic Journal, 8(29), 37–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, D. N. (1985). The rhetoric of economics. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKibben, B. (1989). The end of nature. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyers, D. (2010). Feminist perspectives on the self. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (electronic). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/feminism-self

  • Nelson, J. A. (1993). The study of choice or the study of provisioning? Gender and the definition of economics. In M. Ferber & J. A. Nelson (Eds.), Beyond economic man (pp. 23–36). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, J. A. (1995). Feminism and economics. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9(2), 131–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, J. A. (2005). Interpersonal relations and economics: Comments from a feminist perspective. In B. Gui & R. Sugden (Eds.), Economics and social interaction (pp. 250–261). Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, J. A. (forthcoming). Does profit-seeking rule out love? Evidence (or not) from economics and law. Washington University Journal of Law and Policy, 35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action. Cambridge, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2003). For ethics and economics without the dichotomies. Review of Political Economy, 15(3), 395–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruddick, S. (1989). Maternal thinking: Toward a politics of peace. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarry, E. (2011). Thinking in an emergency. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, M. (2010). The new sheriffs of Wall Street. Time, 175, 22–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1977). Rational fools: A critique of the behavioral foundations of economic theory. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6, 317–344. Summer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanton, E. (2011). Negishi welfare weights in integrated assessment models: The mathematics of global inequality. Climatic Change, 107(3), 417–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, N. (2011). How should we think about the economics of climate change? Lecture for the Leontief Prize. Medford, OR: Global Development and Environment Institute. http://www.ase.tufts.edu/gdae/about_us/leontief/SternLecture.pdf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2002–2003). The paralyzing principle. Regulation Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2005). Laws of fear: Beyond the precautionary principle. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taleb, N. N. (2010). The black swan: The impact of the highly improbable. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • The Onion. (2011). Republicans vote to repeal Obama-backed bill that would destroy asteroid headed for earth. The Onion, 47(5).

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, K. J. (2000). Ecofeminist philosophy: A western perspective on what it is and why it matters. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Lanham.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman, M. L. (2009). On modeling and interpreting the economics of catastrophic climate change. The Review of Economics and Statistics, 91(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman, M. L. (2010). GHG targets as insurance against catastrophic climate damages. Working paper. Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman, M. L. (2011). Fat-tailed uncertainty in the economics of catastrophic climate change. REEP symposium on fat tails. Cambridge: Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, L. E., & Bargh, J. A. (2008). Experiencing physical warmth promotes interpersonal warmth. Science, 322, 606–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Financial support for this project was received from Economists for Equity and the Environment.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Julie A. Nelson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Nelson, J.A. (2016). Ethics and Climate Change Policy. In: Searing, E., Searing, D. (eds) Practicing Professional Ethics in Economics and Public Policy. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-7306-5_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics