Skip to main content

Philosophy of Education and Science Education: A Vital but Underdeveloped Relationship

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching

Abstract

This chapter examines the relationship between the two fields of science education and philosophy of education to inquire how philosophy could better contribute to improving science curriculum, teaching, and learning, especially science teacher education. An inspection of respective research journals exhibits an almost complete neglect of each field for the other (barring exceptions).While it can be admitted that philosophy has been an area of limited and scattered interest for science education researchers for some time, the subfield of philosophy of education has been little canvassed and remains an underdeveloped area. To help bring science education closer into the fold of educational philosophy and theorizing, the historical development of science education and philosophy of education are sketched to reveal their common roots, interests, and concerns. Thereto, the contours of a new philosophy of science education are presented (as an integration of three academic fields). Arguments are provided which seek to illustrate why philosophy in general and philosophy of education in particular can make positive contributions to teacher education and the research field together with suggesting future directions and possible reform contributions (scientific literacy, educational aims, educational theory, pedagogical content knowledge, science teacher, and curricular epistemologies).

It was through the feeling of wonder that men now and at first began to philosophize. … but he who asks and wonders expresses his ignorance … thus in order to gain knowledge they turned to philosophy.

—Aristotle (Metaphysics)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 749.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The prominent US National Science Teachers Association (NSTA) has made STEM a central reform emphasis: www.nsta.org/stem. References for the other more common science classroom curricular emphases are Aikenhead (1997, 2002, 2007), Carson (1998), DeBoer (1991), Donnelly (2001, 2004, 2006), Pedretti and Nazir (2011), Roberts (1982), Schwab (1978), Witz (2000), and Yager (1996).

  2. 2.

    “Regrettably, much of the constructivist literature relating to education has lacked precision in the use of language and thereby too readily confused theories of knowledge with ideas about how students learn and should be taught” (Jenkins 2009, p. 75).

  3. 3.

    The literature on constructivism is vast. Critiques are found in Davson-Galle (1999), Phillips (2000), Grandy (2009), Kelly (1997), Matthews (1998b, 2000), and Scerri (2003). Also see chapter 31 in Handbook.

  4. 4.

    This component is meant to include the associated disciplines and not just the philosophy discipline itself.

  5. 5.

    Whether or not science students themselves should be presented with PS ideas and controversies is still being debated among researchers (Hodson 2009). One philosopher of education has reversed his earlier standpoint (Davson-Galle 1994, 2004, 2008a).

  6. 6.

    It has also been historically associated with particular schools of thought (e.g., idealism, rationalism, empiricism, existentialism); hence, particular philosophies which themselves are often associated with individual philosophers (e.g., Plato, Kant, Marx, Nietzsche).

  7. 7.

    This is not meant to discount the next three. Logic has made a renewed appearance in science education under the guise of critical thinking and scientific argumentation; those in ethics intersect with discussions of values and socio-ethical issues (Allchin 2001; Corrigan et al. 2007; Witz 1996; Zeidler and Sadler 2008); even aesthetics has been considered for the field (Girod 2007).

  8. 8.

    See the chapters in Bonjour and Sosa (2003) for a concise overview; Sect. 39.5.2.2 targets the former.

  9. 9.

    That one must inevitably justify the value of philosophy for teachers and many researchers suggests a cultural predicament already exists concerning what constitutes “education” in our present age.

  10. 10.

    Which includes essentially their “orientations” towards teaching, identified in science teacher education research as formative dispositions attached to identity (Van Driel and Abell 2010; Witz and Lee 2009)

  11. 11.

    Probably the ongoing reality of the academic divide between the “two cultures” maintained as two solitudes in universities to this day (as described by C.P. Snow; Shamos 1995; Stinner 1989) contributes to the hostility or indifference since science teachers are not generally required to endure Arts faculty courses. All this in combination with the common negative image that academic philosophy is preoccupied with obtuse speculation, arcane technical jargon, and unresolved disputes are remote from everyday matters. Certainly quite different, encouraging evaluations can be had (Matthews 1994a; Nola and Irzik 2005).

  12. 12.

    They continue: “… Too often the selected textbook defines course scope, sequence, and depth implying that a textbook’s inclusion of information, in part, legitimizes teaching that content. Textbooks also exert a significant influence on how content is taught…” (ibid).

  13. 13.

    Many teachers would probably declare “science for all” or “scientific literacy” though seldom with awareness these slogans are replete with ambiguities—the latter goal even suffering inherent incompatibilities due to serious shifts in connotation, and this despite its ultimate prominence in worldwide “standards” documents (Jenkins 2009; Schulz 2009b; Shamos 1995). The science for all theme arguably partially appropriate for junior science nonetheless vanishes when specialty upper secondary or tertiary courses are reached, for here the status quo is maintained as “technical pre-professional training” (Aikenhead 1997, 2002, 2007). In this case an extreme narrowing of the “literacy” notion is found, HPSS aspects are distorted or abused, while the concealment of existent curriculum ideologies remains unrecognized in absence of educational philosophy (e.g.,. scientism, academic rationalism, “curriculum as technology” or social utility; Eisner 1992).

  14. 14.

    In his comprehensive review, the categories “vision I” and “vision II” were postulated to account for two major competing images of science literacy behind many curricular reforms. The former designates those conceptions which are “internally oriented,” that is, towards science as a knowledge- and inquiry-based discipline and including the image of science education as heavily influenced by the identity, demands, and conceptions of the profession. The latter vision, alternatively, is “outward looking,” towards the application, limitation, and critical appraisal of science in society—the image influenced instead by the needs of society and the majority of students not headed for professional science-based careers. Here the question of the “social relevance” of the curriculum is paramount. He claims that while the second vision can encompass the first, the opposite is not true.

  15. 15.

    For linked views, see Anderson (1992), Fensham (2004), Matthews (1994a/2014, 2002), and Schulz (2009a).

  16. 16.

    It should not be forgotten that the seventeenth-century scientific revolution introduced “science” as a field of research and study under the academic umbrella of Natural Philosophy to distinguish it from the reigning scholasticism of the universities, hermeticism, and Neoplatonism. Our modern conception of the term and the severance of philosophy from science are of relatively recent origin. The division emerged historically as a development in intellectual thought and specialization, which evolved within European industrial society in the mid-nineteenth century.

  17. 17.

    Quoted in Matthews (1994a), p. 84.

  18. 18.

    Scientists and philosophers alike have found it necessary to launch important new subdisciplines to address foundational questions and concerns arising from their scientific areas of expertise—notwithstanding those scientists who disparage the study of PS overall (e.g., Weinberg 1992). Philosophy of physics (Cushing 1998; Lange 2002), philosophy of chemistry (McIntyre 2007; Scerri 2001), and philosophy of biology (Ayala and Arp 2009) are becoming established research fields, including philosophy of technology (Scharff 2002), likewise lauded for teachers today (De Vries 2005).

  19. 19.

    Refer to the respective chapter in this Handbook.

  20. 20.

    Unfortunately it appears that science education worldwide and many science teachers themselves have tended not to keep abreast of these advances and what they possibly offer for curriculum design, instruction, and reform efforts. One might hope these subdisciplines offer, minimally, deeper and improved insights about subject content but, moreso, a better understanding of the essence of the discipline, the core of which teachers are required to inspire and impart to their students. Certainly these are less well known to science teachers and not canvassed by science education researchers to the extent of interest shown in the post-structuralist and “science studies” literature. See Allchin (2004), Collins (2007), Hodson (2008), Holton (2003), Kelly et al. (1993), Nola and Irzik (2005), Ogborn (1995), Roth and McGinn (1998), and Slezak (1994a, b).

  21. 21.

    With such a faculty, teachers could better function in their role as mediator between the scientific establishment and their pupils, also between public discourse about science with pupils or adults not conversant either how science evolves or the nature of modern techno-science (see also Hodson 2009).

  22. 22.

    The term “scientism” can be interpreted in different ways; most construe it negatively (Bauer 1992; Haack 2003; Habermas 1968; Matthews 1994a/2014). Nadeau and Desautels (1984) attribute five components. Irzik and Nola (2009) are careful to distinguish legitimate scientific worldviews from illegitimate scientistic ones: “A scientific worldview need not be scientistic. Scientism, as we understand it, is an exclusionary and hegemonic worldview that claims that every worldview question can be best answered exclusively by the methods of science… that claims to be in no need of resources other than science. By contrast, a scientific worldview may appeal to philosophy, art, literature and so on, in addition to science. For example, scientific naturalism can go along with a version of humanism in order to answer worldview questions about the meaning of life.”

  23. 23.

    Refer to the chapter contribution in this Handbook.

  24. 24.

    What is being suggested here can be taken to correspond with a key objective of critical pedagogy, popularized by the Marxist teacher educator Paulo Freire (1970), their advance to “critical consciousness.”

  25. 25.

    Science education to this day has been unable to resolve the principal dilemma concerning the conflict of the two competing “visions” of its purpose (hence competing conceptions of “scientific literacy”). Roberts (2007, p. 741) admits the community must “somehow resolve the problems associated with educating two very different student groups (at least two).”

  26. 26.

    Refer to Aikenhead (1997, 2007), Bybee and DeBoer (1994), Donnelly (2004), Donnelly and Jenkins (2001), Pedretti et al. (2008), Schulz (2009a), Shamos (1995), Witz and Lee (2009), and Yager (1996).

  27. 27.

    Grade 11 and 12 specialist science courses continue to serve primarily a gatekeeping function for college and university entrance, and their purpose, structure, and content usually replicate first-year tertiary courses—their chief rationale is exclusively with “science for scientists,” and not concerned with the large majority who will not specialize. In other words, as induction into pure academic science but at the neglect (if not deliberate omission) of discussing (never mind integrating), the epistemologies, social practices, and proper history of the sciences—otherwise termed nature-of-science perspectives (Hodson 2008; Irzik and Nola 2011; Lederman 2007; Matthews 1998a). Reform movements like Science-Technology-Society (STS), Science-Societal Issues (SSI), and (lately) scientific argumentation studies have been attempting to counter this dominant school paradigm for some time but continue to make only small inroads.

  28. 28.

    Yet despite these disturbing findings, researchers in these newer fields of study (also Chemical Education Research) still struggle uphill for respect and acceptance in their academic departments, where educational studies and research continue to be afforded a low priority (Gilbert et al. 2004; Hestenes 1998).

  29. 29.

    See Aikenhead (2006), Bencze (2001), Donnelly and Jenkins (2001), Fensham (2002, 2004), Roberts (1988), and Roberts and Oestman (1998). Laugksch (2000) draws attention to different social group interests in defining “science literacy.” Ernest (1991) also identifies several interest groups as determinants of mathematics education.

  30. 30.

    Fensham’s (2002) paper “Time to changing drivers for scientific literacy” (movement away from the academic driver to “social” and industry-based drivers) provoked a lively response from researchers about the “educo-politics” of curriculum development, especially about what role academic scientists should play, if any (Aikenhead 2002; Gaskell 2002); such a suggestion though would reorientate science education back towards the recurrent (and contentious) “social relevancy” goal and the progressivism of Deweyan-type philosophy (Darling and Nordenbo 2003; DeBoer 1991)—whose educational theory is often concealed. It may even involve a Faustian bargain with industrial- and vocational-driven interests. Gaskell believes the risk is worth it. But given the complexity of techno-science and the great diversity of vocations and business interests today leaves one wondering if any sort of meaningful consensus on curriculum is achievable, even locally.

  31. 31.

    Fensham in fact suggests that it is the “dominance of psychological thinking in the area” which attests to why Dewey is not cited more frequently among respondents in the USA (still the most prominent philosopher of education linked with science education in North America).

  32. 32.

    Important works are Bailey et al. (2010), Blake et al. (2003), Chambliss (1996a), and Winch and Gingell (1999).

  33. 33.

    Authors in alphabetical order include Bailin, Burbules, Davson-Galle, Garrison, Grandy, Hodson, Matthews, McCarthy, Norris, Phillips, Scheffler, Schulz, Siegel, and Zembylas (see respective references).

  34. 34.

    Matthews comments this may be the significant reason why the science education research literature “is dominated by psychological, largely learning theory, concerns” (ibid). Others have also cited the domination of psychology and conceptual change research (Gunstone and White 2000; Lee et al. 2009).

  35. 35.

    The typical tendency is to adopt philosophical or ideological views from well-known authors outside the field but often not accompanied by critical appraisal of such authors: “… the work of Kuhn, von Glasersfeld, Latour, Bruner, Lave, Harding, Giroux and others is appropriated but the critiques of their work go unread: it is rare that science education researchers keep up with psychological and philosophical literature” (ibid, p. 35).

  36. 36.

    Related to this topic is the question of what worldview(s) science assumes or requires in order to be sustained, hence which one(s) educators need to be supportive or cognizant of (Matthews 2009a). This further raises the question of the universalism of “Western science,” whether or not its knowledge and truth claims are necessarily culturally confined, or merely evolved. Disputes over the interpretations of “multicultural science” will not be addressed here, but again science educators require philosophical training in order to adequately tackle these controversial topics. Philosophical treatment of this subject can be found in Hodson (2009), Matthews (1994a), Nola and Irzik (2005), and chapters in this Handbook.

  37. 37.

    The literature on Bildung and Didaktik is extensive. Some references to its historical development are Barnard (2003), Beiser (1998), Gadamer (1960/1975), and Schiller (1795/1993).

  38. 38.

    “On the one hand, the concept Bildung describes how the strengths and talents of the person emerge, a development of the individual; on the other, Bildung also characterizes how the individual’s society uses his or her manifest strengths and talents, a “social” enveloping of the “individual” (Vásquez-Levy 2002, p. 118). Given this interpretation, one could in fairness associate the values and aims of the Bildung tradition with two prevalent “curriculum ideologies” identified by Eisner (1992) as “rational humanism” and the “personal” stream within progressivism.

  39. 39.

    Science education and Bildung in Germany have been examined by Benner (1990) and Litt (1963).

  40. 40.

    One Canadian study involving science teachers had sought to fuse the Bildung ideal with the STS paradigm and cross-curricular thinking (Hansen and Olson 1996).

  41. 41.

    “In the one, the maturing young person is the purpose of the curriculum. In the other, the teaching of subjects is the purpose. In the one case, disciplines of knowledge are to be mined to achieve its purpose; in the other, disciplines of knowledge are the purposes” (2004, p. 150).

  42. 42.

    Jenkins (2009) notes the same problem with reform movements and policy documents. This complaint (although dated but still relevant) was earlier attested by DeBoer in his Preface to his insightful History of Ideas in Science Education (1991).

  43. 43.

    Roberts (1988, p. 48) draws attention to where teacher loyalties commonly lie: “The influence of the subject community is an especially potent force in science education. In general, the ‘hero image’ … of the science teacher tends to be the scientist rather than the educator [or philosopher].”

  44. 44.

    Hirst (2008b) has recently complained that in some countries such as England, there are now moves afoot to delist such courses for teacher training altogether. It would not be a stretch to conclude that such a downgrade in the general value of philosophy-of-education cannot fail to negatively impact science teacher professional development.

  45. 45.

    The leading journals of the English-speaking world are Studies in Philosophy and Education, Educational Theory, Educational Philosophy and Theory, and Journal of the Philosophy of Education.

  46. 46.

    Some classroom case examples are Hadzigeorgiou et al. (2011), Kalman (2010), and Ruse (1990). Bailin and Battersby (2010), Giere (1991), and Kalman (2002) offer science teacher educators rich material for enhancing science subject-related critical thinking:

  47. 47.

    “Domination, resistance, oppression, liberation, transformation, voice, and empowerment are

    the conceptual lenses through which critical theorists view schooling and pedagogy” (Atwater 1996, p. 823).

  48. 48.

    Different kinds of answers are provided by Aikenhead (2006, 2007), Apple (1992), Bencze (2001), Donnelly and Jenkins (2001), Gaskell (2002), Gibbs and Fox (1999), Klopfer and Champagne (1990), Roberts and Oestman (1998), Schulz (2009a), and Zembylas (2006).

  49. 49.

    For examples of teachers caught in the debate, see Sullenger et al. (2000) and Witz and Lee (2009). For different perspectives on the debate in the academy, see Brown (2001), Giere (1999), Gross et al. (1995), Laudan (1990), Nola (1994), C. Norris (1997), Siegel (1987a, b), and Sokal and Bricmont (1998).

  50. 50.

    Science educators continue to quarrel whether basic NoS statements can or should be defined, even where a measure of recognized consensus is said to exist—inclusive of those now written into global policy documents. The dispute centers on how to determine “consensus” (among which experts?), or questions regarding disciplinary distinctions, or about NoS cultural dependence on “Western” science and Enlightenment traditions, among others (Hodson 2008; Irzik and Nola 2011; Matthews 1998a; Rudolph 2000, 2002). Good and Shymansky (2001) make the case NoS statements found in “standards” documents like NSES and Benchmarks could be read from opposing positivist- or postmodernist-type perspectives.

  51. 51.

    This viewpoint aligns to an extent with Hodson’s view (2009, p. 20) except for the fact he ignores relating his desired outcomes to educational philosophy and theory: “In my view, we should select NOS items for the curriculum in relation to other educational goals … paying close attention to cognitive goals and emotional demands of specific learning contexts, creating opportunities for students to experience doing science for themselves, enabling students to address complex socioscientific issues with critical understanding….” On what philo-educational grounds the selection is to be undertaken, we are not told though he considers students’ “needs and interests” (overlap with progressivism?), views of experts (“good” HPSS—the Platonic knowledge aim?), and “wider goals” of “authentic representation” of science and “politicization of students.” His lofty ambition for science education (thus his notion of “literacy”), however, includes too many all-encompassing and over-reaching objectives. These must clash and become prioritized (or so it seems) once his three stated criteria for subordinating goals force them under his socio-techno-activist umbrella of politicizing students—the ghost of Dewey beacons.

  52. 52.

    The focus here is on the normative nature of the question (i.e., what do policy documents, researchers, or theorists stipulate?), as opposed to the empirical (i.e., what is going on in classrooms now?).

  53. 53.

    This important topic is too often overlooked in curriculum theory or in the science education literature. See Fensham (2004), Geddis (1993), Klafki (1995), Lijnse (2000), Schulz (2011), Vásquez-Levy (2002), and Witz (2000); Dewey, Mach, and Schwab all in their day also identified the issue that the logic of the discipline does not conform with the psychologic of learning the subject matter of the discipline. Thereto, Aikenhead (1996) has argued that learning science involves a culturally rooted “border-crossing” on the part of the student, to negotiate the transition from the personal “lifeworld” to the “school-science world.”

  54. 54.

    See discussion on the topic of epistemic aims by Adler (2002), Hirst (1974), and Robertson (2009).

  55. 55.

    See discussion in Egan (1997) and Pring (2010). Smeyers (1994) discusses the European account.

  56. 56.

    Driver et al. (1996, pp. 16–23) offer five rationales for teaching NoS in classrooms, yet they either assume or overlook their dependence upon different, prior educational theories.

  57. 57.

    See Nola and Irzik (2005), Robertson (2009), and Siegel (2010) for discussion of these subjects.

  58. 58.

    See Brighouse (2009) and Pring (2010) for discussion of these subjects. Donnelly (2006) only scratches the surface of the problem with his defined dual clash between “liberal” and “instrumental” educational aims behind community reforms.

  59. 59.

    This remark also targets research concerning situated cognition models, where it has often been asserted; practice was either prior to theorizing or without theory. See critiques of Roth by Sherman (2004, 2005).

  60. 60.

    He continues: “Too often we try to simply derive pedagogical practices from theoretical positions on learning, or diversity, or language, or the latest research on the functioning of the brain, etc.” (ibid).

  61. 61.

    An example of the confusion which results in science education research when PE is ignored is the paper by Duschl (2008). Here empirical research from the learning sciences and science studies is confused with educational goals, which must be chosen on a normative basis. Such research may very tell us how students (and scientists) learn but expressly not why and what goals they should learn. And to argue for a “cultural imperative” is to make a normative claim extrapolated from such research—one is dabbling in PE without its recognition. Moreover, whether the avowed economic, democratic, epistemic, “social-learning” goals, etc. (as they have been historically articulated for the field) can be “balanced” as Duschl simply assumes is by no means obvious—PE debates show quite the opposite (Egan 1997; Levinson 2010; Schulz 2009a).

  62. 62.

    To name just some in the Western tradition; Eastern and other traditions have of course their own major philosophers who have concerned themselves with education.

  63. 63.

    A classic source of material for this orientation are the essays in Henry (1955).

  64. 64.

    As those in the SocioScientific Issues (SSI), reform movement today insists (Zeidler and Sadler 2008).

  65. 65.

    See DeBoer (2000), Fensham (2002), Gaskell (2002), Jenkins (1994), and Roberts and Oestman (1998), for responses to such questions.

  66. 66.

    Recall the ongoing past disputes between “science for scientists” and “science for all” perspectives on curriculum, goals, and policy (ByBee and DeBoer 1994; DeBoer 1991). The most recent STEM reform movement in the USA can be justifiably accused of redefining science education as “science for engineers.”

  67. 67.

    So that it may “engage in explorations of what [science] education might be or might become: a task which grows more compelling as the ‘politics of the obvious’ grow more oppressive. This is the kind of thing that Plato, Rousseau and Dewey are engaged in on a grand scale” (Blake et al. 2003, p. 15).

  68. 68.

    Carr holds that educational theory might be better suited to ethics (moral reasoning) than with any sort of empirical science, which is not to dismiss the worth of some empirical work: “On closer scrutiny, it seems that many modern social scientific theories of some educational influence are often little more than normative or moral accounts in thin empirical disguise” (2010, pp. 51–2). This deduction leaves unanswered the important question as to what the proper role and value of empirical research for educational theorizing is to be. The topic is controversial and engenders debate in PE. See Egan (2002) and Hyslop-Margison and Naseem (2007) for a negative assessment and Phillips (2005, 2007, 2009) for a positive view.

  69. 69.

    “We have suffered from tenuous inferences drawn from insecure psychological theories for generations now, without obvious benefit” (Egan 2002, pp. 100–101).

  70. 70.

    Phillips (2002, p. 233) terms these “classic theories of teaching and learning.”

  71. 71.

    It should be noted that Dewey’s aim is among the least predetermined of the others, although it could reasonably be argued that Kant’s ideal is also dynamic insofar as he allows for education’s dual aim, the “perfecting” of man qua man plus the improvement of society and “the human race.” In addition, Frankena (1965, p. 156) also notes that such a dual aim in Dewey could considerably conflict—that the expected growth of the individual and society may clash—in anticipation of Egan’s critique, which claims the clash is inevitable insofar as modern schooling is molded according to progressivist precepts. Alternatively, for Dewey, but also for Aristotle and Kant, such a possible conflict was thought to be reconcilable in principle.

  72. 72.

    Such questions are actually the purview of what is demanded of an educational theory. Philosophy of education properly understood is a much broader field of inquiry that encompasses an analysis of such theories and questions (Peters 1966), which today usually overlaps with curriculum studies. Frankena seems to have been working with a constricted conception solely at the level of theory.

  73. 73.

    Smeyers (1994) identifies the same quandary for Western European education.

  74. 74.

    In brief, socialization conflicts with the “Platonic” (knowledge-focused) project because the former seeks the conformity to values and beliefs of society while the latter encourages the questioning of these; socialization also conflicts with the “Rousseauian project” since the latter argues that personal growth must conflict with social norms and needs. It sees growth and hence education in intrinsic terms instead of as utility for other socially defined ends. (Here exists the principal tension between the Bildung tradition and the dominating utility view of education and science literacy of the English-speaking world.) The Platonic and Rousseauian projects conflict because the former assumes an epistemological model of learning and development and the latter a psychological one. In the former “mind” is created and the aim is knowledge; in the latter it develops naturally, requiring only proper guidance, and the aim is self-actualization.

  75. 75.

    No one normally holds exclusively to one or the other, although usually one or the other is emphasized over the other two at a given time (depending upon the defined “crisis” at hand and under influence of respective social group interests), and the modern school and indeed many “standards” documents aim at a sort of balance between them. Roberts (1988), too, holds that “balance” is both desirable and achievable during public policy curriculum deliberations. Egan though insists that the attempts to achieve “balance” are illusory and must undermine the strengths of any one at the cost of the others.

  76. 76.

    The term itself first came into use in the late 1950s. Initially broadly framed in terms of science, culture, and society relationships, it soon came however to mean learning technical, subject-specific knowledge: “This emphasis on disciplinary knowledge, separated from its everyday applications and intended to meet a perceived national need, marked a significant shift in science education in the post-war years. The broad study of science as a cultural force in preparation for informed and intelligent participation in a democratic society lost ground in the 1950s and 1960s to more sharply stated and more immediate practical aims” (DeBoer 2000, p. 588). By the 1980s the phrase had become commonplace: “Yet despite the problems of definition, by the 1980s scientific literacy had become the catchword of the science education community and the centerpiece of virtually all commission reports deploring the supposed sad state of science education” (Shamos 1995, p. 85).

  77. 77.

    As can the seven “curriculum emphases” behind science curricula, identified by Roberts (1988)

  78. 78.

    Shamos has insightfully argued that its common conception tied to citizenship is fundamentally flawed, that the community is chasing a utopia, that it continues to refuse to accept the grounds why it has failed in achieving it, and finally that many rationales typically put forth to justify it are a myth.

  79. 79.

    Option two although seemingly attractive on the surface does not seem viable, and one can imagine numerous problems associated with it. Just mentioning one, it assumes a degree of autonomy for schools and teachers which they generally lack and which in the climate of “accountability” and standardized testing and under the influence of powerful outside social groups would seem to check their ability to make the kind of choices DeBoer would like. A reversion to option one would in all likelihood result, namely, the default traditionalist position.

  80. 80.

    A series of papers presented at a recent conference attempting to articulate “a more expansive notion of scientific literacy” illustrate the problems associated with this deadlock once more and why the sought-after solutions remain so elusive; discussions including educational theory and philosophy are conspicuously absent (Linder et al. 2007).

  81. 81.

    “This borrowing can have the healthy effect of bringing new insights to bear on the problems of science education, but it can also lead to superficial descriptions that do not seem to be pushing for deeper understanding” (2004, p. 101). He fails to mention a third possibility that outside theories can do outright damage to education, as Egan (1983, 2002) argues for the cases of behaviorism, Piaget, and progressivism. The presumed relevance of cognitive science has lately come into question as well (Slezak 2007).

  82. 82.

    Reliance upon psychology is clearly predominant, primarily Bruner, Gagne, and Piaget in the 1960s and 1970s and the significant role they played marking the revolt against behaviorism.

  83. 83.

    This book, however, as is familiar today, is based on the psychologist Ausubel’s quasi-neural theory of meaningful learning in combination with Toulmin’s philosophy of science and principally restricted to learning theory.

  84. 84.

    It is admitted that Novak’s writings offered an important counter-theory in support of the growing dissatisfaction with the dominance of Piagetian theory arising in the late 1970s (although some science educators continue to hold neo-Piagetian views). With the growth of conceptual change and constructivist research in the 1980s and the influence of Kuhnian philosophy-of-science, this dominance was gradually displaced in the research community. On the other hand, Erickson (2000) cautions there is much common ground between Piaget and the newer constructivist theories. Egan’s cultural-linguistic metatheory (1997) is inclusive of learning theory but goes beyond it and outright rejects Piaget (Schulz 2009b).

  85. 85.

    Leaving aside questions if its individual educational claims are either warranted or empirically validated. Strong advocates for this kind of politico-social activist PSE (just naming some researchers) are Hodson (2009) and Roth and Desautels (2002). Criticisms leveled against it are provided by Hadzigeorgiou (2008) and Levinson (2010).

  86. 86.

    Does it fully take into consideration the three dimensions of the synoptic framework shown in Fig. 39.1?

  87. 87.

    Roberts (1988, p. 50) had earlier cautioned the research community about the “individual ideological preference of professors of science education” which can “indoctrinate science teachers into believing that what counts as science education is the ideology of a single curriculum emphasis (or perhaps a few emphases)” (original italics).

  88. 88.

    It seeks as well to address the common blurring of lines between “descriptive” and “normative” research work, the expectation that classroom research should change classroom teaching and learning, as Sherman (2005) points out, but strictly in accordance with a specified (ideological) program. This academic conflation may indeed be due to our culturally inherited situation, i.e., “if we can’t be objective, we’ll be openly ideological” (p. 205), but regrettably real “openness” is rare. The argument here in a nutshell is that science education avoids (c)overt ideology for candid philosophy.

  89. 89.

    Such a conversation can be considered an extension of one already discussing the difference between epistemology and psychology (Duschl et al. 1990; Matthews 2000; Southerland et al. 2001) or critiquing the assumed validity of cognitive science theories for science education (Slezak 2007).

  90. 90.

    For some time a major portion of science education research has in fact been focused on analyzing and critiquing the strengths and weaknesses of school science epistemology, whether of subject content, or of the student, or of the teacher.

  91. 91.

    This has also been referred to in the research literature as the “disciplinary view of knowledge” in contrast to “personal learner epistemology” and “social practice views of epistemology” (Kelly et al. 2012). The latter defers to science studies research and how knowledge is attained and justified through discourse practices within epistemic cultures (Knorr Cetina 1999). What is significant is that “within this perspective, knowledge is seen as competent action in a situation rather than as a correct, static representation of the world” (p. 286). What is not being acknowledged is that the two stated perspectives are themselves beholden to two different epistemological philosophies, namely, pragmatism and objectivism. While science education has traditionally been in the thrall of the second and is now expected to shift to the first, it could better take advantage of the respective benefits of each.

  92. 92.

    Even when basic science “subject matter” is taught, it is always accompanied by some context that may operate covertly (e.g., preparatory, socio-utility, etc.). Such contexts have been called “meta-lessons” (Schwab), “curriculum emphases” (Roberts 1988), and “companion meanings” (Roberts and Oestman 1998).

  93. 93.

    Also, what kind of science knowledge is of most worth (a key question of prioritizing subject content)?

  94. 94.

    A very informative discussion on such questions, including examining beliefs, learning, knowledge, and critical inquiry pertaining to the aims of science education, can be found in Nola and Irzik (2005). The comments which follow can be considered supplemental to their work.

  95. 95.

    Certainly the relatively recent research studies to enhance scientific argumentation in the classroom also aim towards resolution of the issues and questions raised here, but are not of present concern.

  96. 96.

    These will not be discussed here; instead see Siegel (2010) and Norris (1997).

  97. 97.

    Kuhn (1970) was skeptical about what science education could achieve in terms of developing independent thought and argued instead the conservative view of reinforcing the conventional paradigm—in part because this furthered “progress” and in part because students had no competence to do otherwise. Schwab held a different view and thought students could be educated to become “fluid inquirers” within and about a discipline. Siegel (1978) has admirably contrasted the two opposing positions.

  98. 98.

    Mason’s (2003) “Understanding understanding” is one of the few to explore the contrast.

  99. 99.

    Some researchers have ventured into this territory; see, for example, Wallace and Louden (2003).

  100. 100.

    “Current attitudes toward foundationalism, as they have been since Descartes, are sharply divided. The minoritarian conviction (Chisholm, Apel, Habermas, Haack, Swinburne, and others) that some version of foundationalism is or is at least potentially viable is outweighed by the majoritarian belief that in the debate since Descartes, foundationalism has died a natural death and cannot be revived” (Rockmore 2004, p. 56).

  101. 101.

    Rorty, of course, also surfaces representation, but he explicitly ties it to philosophy as a profession whose role as a foundational discipline (with its “theory of knowledge” being essentially a “general theory of representation”) was to adjudicate all cultural knowledge claims, eventually including scientific ones. His view is comparable to Taylor’s “To know is to represent accurately what is outside the mind; so to understand the possibility and the nature of knowledge is to understand the way in which the mind is able to construct such representation” (1979, p. 3).

  102. 102.

    Taylor links the success of “knowledge as correct representation” standpoint with two factors: its link with the rise of mechanistic science in the seventeenth century, whose mechanized worldview overthrew the Aristotelean one with its notion of “knowledge as participation” (“being informed by the same eidos, the mind participated in the being of the known object, rather than simply depicting it,” p. 467); secondly, the influence of Cartesian philosophy that insisted a new reliable “method” was required that could guarantee certainty of the representation. Yet this method entailed, unlike in philosophical antiquity, the reflective and critical cast of individual mind performing a subjectivist inward turn. Rorty’s view is similar (1979, p. 248).

  103. 103.

    He cites such authors as Rorty and Taylor (in philosophy), Gadamer (in language theory), and Kuhn and Hesse (in philosophy of science). Other philosophers of science endorsing hermeneutics are Heelan (1991) and Ihde (1998).

  104. 104.

    See especially Rorty (1979, Chap. 7) and Gadamer (1989, p. 235).

  105. 105.

    “Putnam now agrees with Goodman and Wittgenstein: to think of language as a picture of the world—a set of representations which philosophy needs to exhibit as standing in some sort of nonintentional relation to what they represent—is not useful in explaining how language is learned or understood” (1979, p. 295; original italics).

  106. 106.

    This hermeneutic perspective on learning and understanding corresponds with the newer epistemological perspectives of the field: “… increasingly, science education researchers are viewing meaning as public, interpreted by participants (and analysts) through interaction of people via discourse including signs, symbols, models, and ways of being” (Kelly et al. 2012, p. 288).

  107. 107.

    Hence his complaint that one can distinguish between “systematizers” (those engrossed in normal discourse) and “edifying” philosophers (anti-foundationalists like Dewey and hermeneutic thinkers like Heidegger, Gadamer, who disrupt it) within the tradition—the latter whose status as “true” philosophers is often questioned by academic professionals.

  108. 108.

    Rockmore (2004, p. 57) writes that Rorty maintains “a strict but wholly arbitrary distinction between epistemology and hermeneutics in order to equate the failure of foundationalism with a form of skepticism that cannot be alleviated through a hermeneutical turn.” He accuses Rorty of still clinging to a standard of knowledge that he admits cannot be met. Rorty freely concludes that one can no longer hope to bring the mind in contact with the real and that interpretation must be the alternative, but just denies this will lead to knowledge in the conventional sense. Alternatively, Rockmore argues that “the main strategy for knowledge is, and always has been, interpretation” (ibid), not to be taken as tantamount to skepticism.

  109. 109.

    This is not meant to imply this field of study is monolithic, and commentators commonly distinguish between “right-wing” (Gadamer) and “left-wing” (Derrida) factions. Yet such a categorization is equally overly simplified. Those in educational studies—see Gallagher (1992)—distinguish four separate schools: conservative (Dilthey; Hirsch), moderate (Gadamer; Ricoeur), radical (Derrida; Foucault), and critical (Habermas; Apel).

  110. 110.

    Rockmore maintains that the shift leads to a redefinition of epistemology, from “knowing the way the mind-independent world is” to “the interpretation of experience” which is justified by the standards in use in a given cognitive domain. In this reformulation “then epistemology as hermeneutics presents itself as a viable successor to the traditional view of epistemology—indeed as the most likely approach at the start of the new century” (p. 11). Westphal criticizes Rorty for failing to distinguish between classical epistemology and hermeneutics seen as a generic epistemological task, hence, to differentiate the replacement of only one type (foundationalism): “hermeneutics is epistemology, generically construed … it belongs to the same genus precisely because like them it is a meta-theory about how we should understand the cognitive claims of common sense, of natural and social sciences, and even metaphysics and theology” (p. 416; original italics).

References

  • Abell, S.K. and Lederman, N.G. (eds.) (2007). Handbook of research on science education. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abell, S.K, (2007). Research on science teacher knowledge. In: S.K. Abell and N.G. Lederman (eds), Handbook of research on science education (pp. 1105–45). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adler, J.E. (2002). Knowledge, truth and learning. In: R.R. Curren (ed.), A companion to the philosophy of education (pp. 285–303). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aikenhead, G. (2007). Humanistic perspectives in the science curriculum. In S.K. Abell & N.G. Lederman (Eds.), Handbook of research on science education (pp. 880–930). Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aikenhead, G. (2006). Science education for everyday life. Evidence-based practice. New York and London: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aikenhead, G. (2002). The educo-politics of curriculum development: A response to Fensham’s ‘time to change drivers for scientific literacy.’ Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics and Technology Education, 2(1), 49–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aikenhead, G. (1997). STL and STS: Common ground or divergent scenarios? In E. Jenkins (ed.), Innovations in scientific and technological education (pp. 77–93). (Vol. VI), Paris: UNESCO Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aikenhead, G. (1996). Science education: Border crossing into the sub-culture of science. Studies in Science Education, 27, 1–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aldridge, J., Kuby, P. & Strevy, D. (1992). Developing a metatheory of education. Psychological Reports, 70, 683–687.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2004). Should the sociology of science be rated X? Science Education, 88, 934–946.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allchin, D. (2001). Values in science: An educational perspective. In: F. Bevilacqua, E. Giannetto and M. Matthews (eds.), Science education and culture: The contribution of history and philosophy (pp. 185–196). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, R.N. (1992). Perspectives on complexity: an essay on curricular reform. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 29(8): 861–876.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J. (1980). Education and inquiry (edited by D.Z. Phillips). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apple, M. (1992). Educational reform and educational crisis. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 29(8): 779–789.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apple, M. (1990/1975). Ideology and curriculum. 2 nd ed. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1998). The metaphysics. (Translated and introduction by Hugh Lawson-Tancred). London: Penguin books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1962/1981). The politics. (Translated by T.A. Sinclair. Revised and re-presented by Trevor J. Saunders). London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atwater, M.M. (1996). Social constructivism: Infusion into the multicultural science education research agenda. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 33(8), 821–837.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (2009). Science education, religious toleration, and liberal neutrality toward the good. In: H. Siegel (ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of education (pp. 334–357). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayala, F.J. and Arp, R. (eds.) (2009). Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology. Malden, MA: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailey, R., Barrow, R., Carr, D. and McCarthy, C. (eds.) (2010). The SAGE handbook of the philosophy of education. London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailin, S. and Battersby, M. (2010). Reason in the balance: An inquiry approach to critical thinking. Toronto: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailin, S. and Siegel, H. (2003). Critical thinking. In: N. Blake, P. Smeyers, R. Smith and P. Standish (eds), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of education (pp. 181–193). UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bailin, S. (2002). Critical thinking and science education. Science & Education, 11, 361– 375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnard, F.M. (2003). Herder on nationality, humanity and history. Montreal & Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrow, R. (2010). Schools of thought in philosophy of education. In: R. Bailey, R. Barrow, D. Carr and C. McCarthy (eds.) The SAGE handbook of the philosophy of education (pp. 21–36). London: SAGE Publications Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrow, R. & Woods, R. (1975/2006). An introduction to philosophy of education, 4 th Ed., London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, H.H. (1992). Scientific literacy and the myth of the scientific method. Urbana and Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baynes, K., Bohman, J., & McCarthy, T. (eds.) (1987). After philosophy. End or transformation? Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beiser, F. (1998). A romantic education. The concept of Bildung in early German romanticism. In: Amelie O. Rorty (ed.), Philosophers on education. Historical perspectives (pp. 284–299).London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bencze, L. (2001). Subverting corporatism in school science. Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics and Technology Education, 1(3): 349–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benner, D. (1990). Wissenschaft und Bildung. Überlegungen zu einem problematischen Verhältnis und zur Aufgabe einer bildenden Interpretation neuzeitlicher Wissenschaft. (Science and education. Reflections on a problematic relationship and on the task of an educative interpretation of modern science). Zeitschriftfür Pädagogik, 36(4), 597–620.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, R.J. (1983). Beyond objectivism and relativism. Science, hermeneutics and praxis. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beyer, L.E. and Apple, M.W. (1998) (Eds.). The curriculum: Problems, politics and possibilities. Albany, NY: Suny. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blake, N., Smeyers, P., Smith, R. & Standish, P. (eds.) (2003). The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of education. UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blake, N. & Masschelein, J. (2003). Critical theory and critical pedagogy. In: The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of education (pp 38–56). UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boersma, K, Goedhart, M, De Jong, O, Eijkelhof, H. (eds.) (2005). Research and the quality of science education. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonjour, L. and Sosa, E. (2003). Epistemic justification. Internalism vs. externalism, foundations vs. values. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bontekoe, R. (1996). Dimensions of the hermeneutic circle. New Jersey: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borda, E.J. (2007). Applying Gadamer’s concept of dispositions to science and science education. Science & Education, 16(9–10), 1027–1041.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, H. (2009). Moral and political aims of education. In: H. Siegel (ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of education (pp. 35–51). Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J.R. (2001) Who rules in science? An opinionated guide to the wars. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burbules, N.C. & Linn, M.C. (1991). Science education and philosophy of science: Congruence or contradiction? International Journal of Science Education, 13, 227–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, D. P. and Norris, S.P. (2009). Open-minded environmental education in the science classroom. Paideusis: Journal of the Canadian Philosophy of Education Society, 18, 35–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bybee, R. & DeBoer, G.E. (1994). Research on goals for the science curriculum. In: D. Gabel (Ed.), Handbook of research on science teaching and learning (pp. 357–387). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (2010). The philosophy of education and educational theory. In: R. Bailey, R. Barrow, D. Carr and C. McCarthy (eds.) The SAGE handbook of the philosophy of education (pp. 37–54). London: SAGE Publications Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (2009). Curriculum and the value of knowledge. In: H. Siegel (ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of education (pp. 281–299). Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (2003). Making sense of education. London: Routledge Farmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (ed.) (1998). Education, knowledge and truth: Beyond the postmodern impasse. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carson, R.N. (1998). Science and the ideals of liberal education. In: B.J. Fraser & K.G. Tobin (eds.), International Handbook of Science Education. Part II (pp. 1001–1014). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambliss, J.J. (ed.) (1996a). Philosophy of education: An encyclopedia. New York: Garland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambliss, J.J. (1996b). Philosophy of education, history of. In: J.J. Chambliss (ed.), Philosophy of education: An encyclopedia. New York: Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clough, M., Berg, C. & Olson, N. (2009). Promoting effective science teacher education and science teaching: A framework for teacher decision-making. International Journal of Science and Mathematics Education, 7, 821847.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobern, W.W. (2004). Apples and oranges. A rejoinder to Smith and Siegel. Science & Education, 13, 583–589.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobern, W.W. (2000). The nature of science and the role of knowledge and belief. Science & Education, 9(3), 219–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, H. (2007). The uses of sociology of science for scientists and educators. Science & Education, 16, 217–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corrigan, D., Dillion, J. & Gunstone, D. (Eds.). (2007). The re-emergence of values in the science curriculum. Rotterdam, Holland: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curren, R.R. (ed.) (2003). A companion to the philosophy of education. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushing, J.T. (1998). Philosophical concepts in physics. The historical relation between philosophy and scientific theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darling, J. & Nordenbo, S.E. (2003). Progressivism. In: N. Blake, P. Smeyers, R. Smith and P. Standish (eds), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of education (pp. 288–308). UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davson-Galle, P. (2008a). Why compulsory science education should not include philosophy of science. Science & Education, 17, 667–716.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davson-Galle, P. (2008b). Against science education: The aims of science education and their connection to school science curricula. In: T. Bertrand & L. Roux (eds.), Education Research Trends (pp. 1–30), Nova Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davson-Galle, P. (2004). Philosophy of science, critical thinking and science education. Science & Education, 13(6), 503–517.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davson-Galle, P. (1999). Constructivism: A curate’s egg. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 31(2), 205–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davson-Galle, P. (1994). Philosophy of science and school science. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 26(1): 34–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeBoer, G.E. (2000). Scientific literacy: Another look at its historical and contemporary meanings and its relationship to science education reform. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 37(6): 582–601

    Google Scholar 

  • DeBoer, G.E. (1991). History of ideas in science education. Implications for practice. New York and London: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • deVries, M.J. (2005). Teaching about technology. An introduction to the philosophy of technology for non-philosophers. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. & Bentley, A.F. (1949). Knowing and the known. Boston: The Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1945). Method in science teaching. Science Education, 29, 119–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1938/1997). Experience and education. New York: Touchstone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1916/1944). Democracy and education. An introduction to the philosophy of education. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, J. (2006). The intellectual positioning of science in the curriculum, and its relationship to reform. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 38(6), 623–640.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, J. (2004). Humanizing science education. Science Education, 88, 762–784.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, J. (2001). Instrumentality, hermeneutics and the place of science in the school curriculum. In: F. Bevilacqua, E. Giannetto, and M. Matthews (eds.), Science education and culture: the contribution of history and philosophy (pp. 109–127). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, J. & Jenkins, E. (2001). Science education. Policy, professionalism and change, London: Paul Chapman Publishing, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver, R., Leach, J., Millar, R. & Scott, P. (1996). Young people’s images of science. Buckingham, UK: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R. & Hamilton, R.J. (eds.) (1992). Philosophy of science, cognitive psychology, and educational theory and practice. Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R., Hamilton, R. & Grady, R.E. (1990). Psychology and epistemology: match or mismatch when applied to science education? International Journal of Science Education, 12(3), 230243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R. (2008). Science education in three-part harmony: Balancing conceptual, epistemic, and social learning goals. Review of Research in Education, 32, 268–91

    Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R. (1994). Research on the history and philosophy of science. In: D. Gabel (ed.), Handbook of research on science teaching and learning (pp. 443–465). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R. (1990). Restructuring science education: the role of theories and their importance. Columbia University, New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duschl, R. (1988). Abandoning the scientistic legacy of science education. Science Education, 72(1), 51–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, K. (2005). Students’ development in theory and practice: the doubtful role of research. Harvard Educational Review, 75(1): 25–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, K. (2002). Getting it wrong from the beginning. Our progressivist inheritance from Herbert Spencer, John Dewey, and Jean Piaget. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, K. (1997). The educated mind. How cognitive tools shape our understanding. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, K. (1983). Education and psychology. Plato, Piaget, and scientific psychology. New York and London. Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eger, M. (1993a). Hermeneutics as an approach to science: Part I. Science & Education, 2, 129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eger, M. (1993b). Hermeneutics as an approach to science: Part II. Science & Education, 2, 303–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eger, M. (1992). Hermeneutics and science education: An introduction. Science & Education 1, 337–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisner, E. (1992). Curriculum ideologies. In: P. W. Jackson (ed.), Handbook of research on curriculum (pp. 302–326). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Englund, T. (1998). Problematizing school subject content. In: D.A Roberts and L. Oestman (eds.), Problems of meaning in science curriculum (pp. 13–24). New York and London: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erickson, G. (2007). In the path of Linnaeus: Scientific literacy re-visioned with some thoughts on persistent problems and new directions for science education. In: Linder et al. (eds.), Promoting scientific literacy: Science education research in transaction. Proceedings of the Linnaeus Tercentenary Symposium, Uppsala, Sweden (May 28–29; pp. 18–41). Uppsala: Geotryckeriet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erickson, G. (2000). Research programmes and the student science learning literature. In: R. Millar, J. Leach and J. Osborne (eds.), Improving science education. The contribution of research (pp. 271–292). Buckingham: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ernest, P.A. (1991). Philosophy of mathematics education. London: Routledge-Falmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fensham, P. (2004). Defining an identity. The evolution of science education as a field of research. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fensham, P. (2002). Time to change drivers for scientific literacy. Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics and Technology Education, 2(1): 9–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. (1975/1988). Against method. (Revised edn). London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1972/1989). The archaeology of knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1980). Power/knowledge. Selected interviews and other writings 1972-77. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankena, W.K. (1970). A model for analyzing a philosophy of education. In: J.R. Martin, Readings in the philosophy of education: A study of curriculum (pp. 15–22). Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankena, W.K. (1965). Three historical philosophies of education. Aristotle, Kant, Dewey. Chicago: Scott, Foresman and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, B.J., Tobin, K.G. and McRobbie, C.J. (eds.) (2012). 2 nd International handbook of science education. Springer international handbooks of education, 24, Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, B.J. and Tobin, K.G. (eds). (1998). International handbook of science education. Two volumes. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friere, P. (1970). Pedagogy of the oppressed. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabel, D. (ed). (1994). Handbook of research on science teaching and learning. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H. (1976). Philosophical hermeneutics. (Translated and edited by David Linge). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H. (1960/1975/1989). Truth and method. Second revised edition. (Translation revised by J. Weinsheimer and D.G. Marshall). New York & London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (1992). Hermeneutics and education. New York: State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrison, J.W. and Bentley, M. L. (1990). Science education, conceptual change and breaking with everyday experience. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 10(1), 19–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaskell, J. (2002). Of cabbages and kings: Opening the hard shell of science curriculum policy. Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics and Technology Education, 2(1), 59–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gay, P. (1969/1996). The enlightenment: An interpretation. The science of freedom. New York: Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geddis, A.N. (1993). Transforming subject-matter knowledge: The role of pedagogical content knowledge in learning to reflect on teaching. International Journal of Science Education, 15, 673–683.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, W.W. & Fox, D. (1999). The false crisis in science education. Scientific American, 281(4), 87–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N. (1999). Science without laws. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R.N. (1991). Understanding scientific reasoning. 3rded. Orlando, FL: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, J.K., Justi, R., Van Driel, J., De Jong, O. & Treagust, D.F. (2004). Securing a future for chemical education. Chemistry Education: Research and Practice, 5(1), 5–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilead, T. (2011). The role of education redefined: 18th century British and French educational thought and the rise of the Baconian conception of the study of nature. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 43(10), 1020–1034.

    Google Scholar 

  • Girod, M. (2007). A conceptual overview of the role of beauty and aesthetics in science and science education. Studies in Science Education, 43, 38–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, R. & Shymansky, J. (2001). Nature-of-science literacy in Benchmarks and Standards: post-modern/relativist or modern/realist? Science & Education, 10: 173–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, R., Herron, J., Lawson, A. & Renner, J. (1985). The domain of science education. Science Education, 69, 139–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grandy, R. (2009). Constructivisms, scientific methods, and reflective judgment in science education. In: H. Siegel (ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of education (pp. 358–380). Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, P.R., Levin, N., & Lewis, M.W. (Eds.). (1995). The flight from science and reason. Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gundem, B.B. & Hopmann, S. (eds.) (1998). Didaktik and/or curriculum. An international dialogue. Peter Lang: New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunstone, R. & White, R. (2000). Goals, methods and achievements of research in science education. In: R. Millar, J. Leach, J. Osborne (eds.), Improving science education: The contribution of research (pp. 293–307). Buckingham, UK: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. (2003). Defending science—within reason. Between scientism and cynicism. Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1987). The philosophical discourse of modernity. (F. G. Lawrence, trans.) Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1968). Knowledge and human interests. Oxford: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y. (2008). Rethinking science education as socio-political action. In: M. Tomase (Ed.), Science Education in Focus. New York: Nova Pubs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadzigeorgiou, Y., Klassen, S., and Klassen, C. (2011). Encouraging a “romantic understanding” of science: The effect of the Nikola Tesla story. Science & Education, 21(8), 1111–1138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, K.-H. and Olson J. (1996). How teachers construe curriculum integration: the Science, Technology, Society (STS) movement as Bildung. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 28(6), 669–682.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1977). Basic writings. (Edited and general introduction by David Krell). San Francisco: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, N.B. (Ed.) (1955). Modern philosophies and education: The Fifty-fourth yearbook of the national society for the study of education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hestenes, D. (1998). Who needs physics education research? American Journal of Physics, 66, 465–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, P. (2008a). In pursuit of reason. In: L.J. Waks (ed.), Leaders in philosophy of education. Intellectual self portraits (pp. 113–124). Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, P. (2008b). Philosophy of education in the UK In: L.J. Waks (ed.), Leaders in philosophy of education. Intellectual self portraits (Appendix B, pp. 305–310). Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, P. (2003). Foreword. In: Blake, N., Smeyers, P., Smith, R. & Standish, P. (eds.) The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of education (pp. xv–xvi). UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, P. (1974). Knowledge and the curriculum. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, P. (1966). Educational theory. In: J.W. Tibble (ed.), The study of education (pp. 29–58). New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heelan, P.A. (1991). Hermeneutical phenomenology and the philosophy of science. In: H.J. Silverman (ed.), Continental philosophy IV. Gadamer and Hermeneutics. Science, culture, literature (pp. 213–228). New York and London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. (1980). Revolutions and reconstructions in the philosophy of science. Brighton, Sussex: Harvester, Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hiley, D.R., Bohman, J.F. & Shusterman, R. (eds.) (1991). The interpretative turn. Philosophy, science, culture. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (2009). Teaching and learning about science. Language, theories, methods, history, traditions and values. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (2008). Towards scientific literacy. A teacher’s guide to the history, philosophy and sociology of science. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (1998). Science fiction: The continuing misrepresentation of science in the school curriculum. Curriculum Studies, 6(2), 191 – 216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (1994). Seeking directions for change: The personalisation and politicisation of science education. Curriculum Studies, 2(1), 71 – 98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodson, D. (1988). Experiments in science and science teaching. Educational Philosophy & Theory, 20, 53–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofer, B.K., & Pintrich, P.R. (1997). The development of epistemological theories: Beliefs about knowledge and knowing and their relation to learning. Review of Educational Research, 67(1), 88–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton, G. (2003). What historians of science and science educators can do for one another. Science & Education, 12, 603616.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyslop-Margison, E.J. & Naseem M.A. (2007). Philosophy of education and the contested nature of empirical research: A rejoinder to D.C. Phillips. Philosophy of Education, 310–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (1998). Expanding hermeneutics. Visualism in science. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G. and Nola, R. (2011). A family resemblance approach to the nature of science for science education. Science & Education, 20, 591–607.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G. and Nola, R. (2009). Worldviews and their relation to science. In: M.R. Matthews (Ed.), Science, worldviews and education. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, E. (2009). Reforming school science education: A commentary on selected reports and policy documents. Studies in Science Education, 45(1), 65–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, E. (2007). School science: A questionable construct? Journal of Curriculum Studies, 39(3), 265282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, E. (2001). Science education as a field of research. Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics and Technology Education, 1(1): 9–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, E. (2000). “Science for all”: time for a paradigm shift? In: R. Millar, J. Leach, J. Osborne (eds), Improving science education. The contribution of research (pp 207–226). Buckingham, UK: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, E. (1994). Public understanding of science and science education for action. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 26(6): 601– 611.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, W. (2012). Philosophy of science and education. Science & Education, 21(8).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalman, C. (2011). Enhancing student’s conceptual understanding by engaging science text with reflective writing as a hermeneutical circle. Science & Education, 20(2), 159–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalman, C. (2010). Enabling students to develop a scientific mindset. Science & Education, 19(2), 147–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalman, C. (2002). Developing critical thinking in undergraduate courses: A philosophical approach. Science & Education, 11, 83–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1784). “Beantwortung der Frage: Was ist Aufklärung?” In: E. Bahr (ed.) (1974), Was ist Aufklärung? Thesen und Definitionen. Stuttgart: Reklam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, G.J., McDonald, S., & Wickman, P. O. (2012). Science learning and epistemology. In: K. Tobin, B. Fraser, & C. McRobbie (Eds.), Second international handbook of science education (pp. 281–291). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, G., Carlsen, W. & Cunningham, C. (1993). Science education in sociocultural context: Perspectives from the sociology of science. Science Education, 77: 207–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, G.J. (1997). Research traditions in comparative context: A philosophical challenge to radical constructivism. Science Education, 81, 355–375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klafki, W. (1995). Didactic analysis as the core of the preparation for instruction (Didaktische Analyse als Kern der Unterrichtsvorbereitung). Journal of Curriculum Studies, 27 (1), 13–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klopfer, L.E. and Champagne, A.B. (1990). Ghosts of crisis past. Science Education, 74(2), 133–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • KnorrCetina, K. (1999). Epistemic cultures. How the sciences make knowledge. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (2000). The road since structure: Philosophical essays, 1970–1993 with an autobiographical interview. (Edited by J. Conant and J. Haugeland). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1977). The essential tension. Selected studies in scientific tradition and change. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyle, W.C. Jr., Abell, S.K, Roth, W-M., and Gallagher, J.J. (1992). Toward a mature discipline of science education. Journal of Research of Science Teaching, 29: 1015–1018.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2002). An introduction to the philosophy of physics. Cornwall: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1990). Science and relativism. Some key controversies in the philosophy of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. In: M. Curd and J. A. Cover (Eds.) (1998), Philosophy of science. The central issues (pp. 1114–1135). New York: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laugksch, R. (2000). Scientific literacy: A conceptual overview. Science Education, 84, 71–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, N.G. (2007). Nature of science: past, present and future. In: S.K. Abell and N.G. Lederman (eds.), Handbook of research on science education (pp. 831–879). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, M., Wu, Y, & Tsai, C. (2009). Research trends in science education from 2003 to 2007. A content analysis of publications in selected journals. International Journal of Science Education, 31(15), 1999–2020.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, R. (2010). Science education and democratic participation: An uneasy congruence? Studies in Science Education, 46(1), 69–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lijnse, P. (2000). Didactics of science: The forgotten dimension in science education research? In: R. Millar, J. Leach & J. Osborne (eds.), Improving science education: The contribution of research. Buckingham: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linder, C., Oestman, L. and Wickman P. (Eds.) (2007). Promoting scientific literacy: Science education research in transaction. Proceedings of the Linnaeus Tercentenary Symposium, Uppsala, Sweden (May 28–29). Uppsala: Geotryckeriet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Litt, T. (1963). Naturwissenschaft und Menschenbildung, 3rd ed. (Science and education) Heidelberg: Quelle und Meyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1693). Some thoughts concerning education. Reprinted in John Locke on education, edited by Peter Gay (1964). New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loving, C.C. (1997). From the summit of truth to its slippery slopes: Science education’s journey through positivist-postmodern territory. American Educational Research Journal, 34(3), 421–452.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, C. (1972). Our western educational heritage. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyotard, J-F. (1979/1984). The postmodern condition. A report on knowledge. (G. Bennington & B. Massumi, trans.). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mason, R. (2003). Understanding understanding. New York: Suny Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (ed.) (2009a). Science, worldviews and education. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (2009b). Book review of Fensham’s (2004) Defining an identity. Newsletter of the IHPST group, May 2009, pp. 21–39. http://ihpst.net/

  • Matthews, M.R. (2009c).The philosophy of education society of Australasia (PESA) and my intellectual growing-up. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 41(7), 777–781.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (2005). What can be rescued from the positivist bathwater? In: C. Higgins (ed.), Philosophy of education 2004 (pp. 223–232). Champaign IL: Philosophy of Education (POE) Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (2004). Reappraising positivism and education: The arguments of Philipp Frank and Herbert Feigl, Science & Education 13(1–2), 7–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (2003a). Thomas Kuhn’s impact on science education: What can be learned? Science Education, 88(2), 90–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (2003b). Data, phenomena, and theory: How clarifying the concepts can illuminate the nature of science. Philosophy of Education, 283–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (2002). Teaching science. In: R.R. Curren (ed.), A companion to the philosophy of education (pp. 342–353). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (2001). Learning about scientific methodology and the “big picture” of science: The contribution of pendulum motion studies. In: S. Rice (ed.) Philosophy of Education 2001 (pp. 204–213). Champaign, IL.: Philosophy of Education Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (2000). Appraising constructivism in science and mathematics education. In: D.C. Phillips (ed.), Constructivism in education. Opinions and second opinions on controversial issues (161–192). NSSE: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1998a). The nature of science and science teaching. In: B.J. Fraser and K.G. Tobin (Eds.), International handbook of science education. Part II (pp. 981–999). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (Ed.). (1998b). Constructivism in science education: A philosophical examination. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (1997). Scheffler revisited on the role of history and philosophy of science in science teacher education. In: H. Siegel (ed.), Reason and education: Essays in honor of Israel Scheffler (pp. 159–173). Dordrecht: Kluwer Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (1996). Charles Darwin. In: J.J. Chambliss (ed.), Philosophy of education: An encyclopedia, (pp. 135–137). New York: Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1994a/2014). Science teaching: The role of history and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (1994b). Philosophy of science and science education. In: T. Husen & T.N. Postlethwaite (eds.) The international encyclopedia of education, Second Edition (pp. 4461–4464). London: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1990a). History, philosophy and science teaching. What can be done in an undergraduate course? Studies in Philosophy and Education, 10, 93–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1990b). Ernst Mach and contemporary science education reforms. International Journal of Science Education, 12(3), 317–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1988). A role for history and philosophy in science teaching. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 20(2), 67–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (1987). Galileo’s pendulum and the objects of science. In: B. & D. Arnstine (eds.), Philosophy of education (pp. 309–319). Normal, IL: POE Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M. R. (1980). Knowledge, action and power. In: R. Mackie (ed.), Literacy and revolution: The pedagogy of Paulo Freire (pp. 82–92). London: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (ed.). (1989). The scientific background to modern philosophy. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, C.L. (2007). Meaning, mind, and knowledge. A pragmatic view. In: C. Higgins (ed.), Philosophy of education 2007 (pp. 421–433). Champaign IL: Philosophy of Education (POE) Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • McComas, W.F. & Olson, J.K. (1998). The nature of science in international science education standards documents. In: W.F. McComas (Ed.), The nature of science in science education: Rationales and strategies (pp. 41–52). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntyre, L. (2007). The philosophy of chemistry: ten years later. Synthese, 155, 291–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Medina, J. (2005). Language. Key concepts in philosophy. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercan, F.C. (2012). Epistemic beliefs about justification employed by physics students and faculty in two different problem contexts. International Journal of Science Education, 34, 8, 1411–1441.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadeau, R. and Désautels, J. (1984). Epistemology and the teaching of science. Ottawa: Science Council of Canada.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nejadmehr, R. (2009). Education, science and truth. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noddings, N. (2011). Philosophy of education. 3rd ed. Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nola, R. and Irzik, G. (2005). Philosophy, science, education and culture. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nola, R. (1994). Post-modernism, a French cultural Chernobyl: Foucault on power/knowledge. Inquiry, 37: 3–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, C. (1997). Against relativism. Philosophy of science, deconstruction and critical theory. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. and Burnes, D.P. (2009). (See Burnes and Norris).

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P., Falk, H., Federico-Agrasso, M., Jiménez-Aleixandre, M.P., Phillips, L.M., and Yarden, A. (2009). Reading science texts—epistemology, inquiry, authenticity—a rejoinder to Jonathan Osborne. Research in Science Education, 39, 405–410.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P., Phillips, L.M., & Osborne, J.F. (2008). Scientific inquiry: The place of interpretation and argumentation. In: J. Luft, R.L. Bell, & J. Gess-Newsome (Eds.), Science as inquiry in the secondary setting (pp. 87–98). Arlington, VA: NSTAPress.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. and Korpan, C.A. (2002). Philosophy or science: A response to Matthews. Philosophy of Education 2001, 56, 214–216.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. & Korpan, C.A. (2000). Science, views about science, and pluralistic science education. In R. Millar, J. Leach, & J. Osborne (Eds.), Improving science education: The contribution of research (pp. 227–244). Buckingham, UK: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. and Kvernbekk, T. (1997). The application of science education theories. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 34, 977–1005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. (1997). Intellectual independence for non-scientists and other content-transcendent goals of science education. Science Education, 81, 239–258.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. (1995). Learning to live with scientific expertise: Towards a theory of intellectual communalism for guiding science teaching. Science Education, 79, 201–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. (1992). Practical reasoning in the production of scientific knowledge. In: R. Duschl and R. Hamilton (Eds.), Philosophy of science, cognitive psychology, and educational theory and practice (pp. 195–225). Albany, NY: NYU State Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. (1988). How the laws of physics lie and other value issues. Philosophy of Education, 43, 321–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. (1985). The philosophical basis of observation in science and science education. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 22, 817-833.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. (1984a). Cynicism, dogmatism, relativism, and scepticism: Can all these be avoided? School Science and Mathematics, 84, 484-495.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. (1984b). Defining observational competence. Science Education, 68, 129-142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norris, S.P. (1982). A concept of observation statements. Philosophy of Education, 37, 132-142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Novak, J. (1977). A theory of education. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogborn, J. (1995). Recovering reality. Studies in Science Education, 25, 3–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olesko, K.M. (2006). Science pedagogy as a category of historical analysis: past, present and future. Science & Education, 15, 863–880.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pedretti, E.G. and Nazir, J. (2011). Currents in STSE education: Mapping a complex field, 40 years on. Science Education, 95, 601–626.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pedretti, E.G., Bencze, L., Hewitt, J., Romkey, L., & Jivraj, A. (2008). Promoting issues-based STSE perspectives in science teacher education: problems of identity and ideology. Science & Education, 17, 941960.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, R. S. (1966). The philosophy of education. In: Tibble, J.W. (ed), The study of education (pp 59–89). New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D.C. (2010). What is philosophy of education? In: R. Bailey, R. Barrow, D. Carr and C. McCarthy (eds.) The SAGE handbook of the philosophy of education (pp. 3–19). London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D.C. (2009). Empirical educational research: Charting philosophical disagreements in an undisciplined field. In: H. Siegel (ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of education (pp. 381–408). Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D.C. (2008). Philosophy of education. In: Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/education-philosophy/

  • Phillips, D.C. (2007). Getting it wrong from the beginning, but maybe (just maybe) it’s a start. Philosophy of Education, 319–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D.C. (2005). The contested nature of empirical research. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 39 (4): 577–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D.C. (2002). Theories of teaching and learning. In: R.R. Curren (ed.), A companion to the philosophy of education (pp. 233–237). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D.C. (ed.), (2000). Constructivism in education. Opinions and second opinions on controversial issues. NSSE: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D.C. (1997). Coming to terms with radical social constructivisms. Science & Education, 6(1/2), 85–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1975). Protagoras and Meno. (Translated by W.K.C. Guthrie). Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1974). The Republic. 2nd Ed. (Translated by Desmond Lee). Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1970). The Laws. (Translated by Trevor Saunders). Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polito, T. (2005). Educational theory as theory of culture: A Vichian perspective on the educational theories of John Dewey and Kieran Egan. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 37(4), 475494.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, G.J. (1998). Models of curriculum planning. In: L.E. Beyer & M.W. Apple (Eds.), The curriculum: Problems, politics and possibilities. (2nd ed., pp. 79–100). Albany, NY: Suny. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pring, R. (2010). The philosophy of education and educational practice. In: R. Bailey, R. Barrow, D. Carr and C. McCarthy (eds.) The SAGE handbook of the philosophy of education (pp. 56–66). London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, D., Kariotoglou, P., Tselfes, V., Hatzikraniotis, E., Fassoulopoulos, G. & Kallery, M. (eds.) (2003). Science education research in the knowledge-based society, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, D.A. & Oestman, L. (eds.) (1998). Problems of meaning in science curriculum. New York and London: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, D.A. (2007). Scientific literacy/science literacy. In: S.K. Abell and N.G. Lederman (eds.), Handbook of research on science education (pp 729–780). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, D.A. (1988). What counts as science education? In: P. Fensham (ed.), Development and dilemmas in science education (pp. 27–54). Philadelphia: Falmer

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, D.A. (1982). Developing the concept of “curriculum emphases” in science education. Science Education, 66, 243–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, D.A. and Russell, T.L. (1975). An alternative approach to science education: drawing from philosophical analysis to examine practice. Curriculum Theory Network, 5(2): 107–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robertson, E. (2009). The epistemic aims of education. In: H. Siegel (ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of education (pp. 11–34). Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rockmore, T. (2004). On foundationalism. A strategy for metaphysical realism. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield, Publishers, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, A.O. (ed.) (1998). Philosophers on education. Historical perspectives. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1984). Habermas and Lyotard on Postmodernity. In Hoesterey, I. (Ed.) (1991). Zeitgeist in babel. The postmodernist controversies (pp. 84–97). Indiana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, W-M. & Barton, A. (2004). Rethinking scientific literacy. NY: Routledge-Falmer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, W-M. and Desautels, J. (Eds.) (2002). Science education as/for sociopolitical action. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, W-M. & McGinn, M. (1998). Knowing, researching and reporting science education: Lessons from science and technology studies. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 35(2), 213–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacque. (1762/1979). Emile. (Translated and an introduction by Allan Bloom). Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, S., Graham, T. & Berry, J. (2011). Problems with fallibilism as a philosophy of mathematics education. Science & Education, 20 (7–8), 625–686.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudolph, J.L. (2002). Portraying epistemology: school science in historical context. Science Education, 87, 64–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudolph, J.L. (2000). Reconsidering the ‘nature of science’ as a curriculum component. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 32(3), 403–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1990). Making use of creationism. A case study for the philosophy of science classroom. Studies in Philosophy of Education, 10(1), 81–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Säther, J. (2003). The concept of ideology in analysis of fundamental questions in science education. Science & Education, 12, 237–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E. (2003). Philosophical confusion in chemical education research. Journal of Chemical Education, 80(5), 468194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scerri, E. (2001). The new philosophy of chemistry and its relevance to chemical education. Chemistry Education: Research and Practice in Europe, 2(2), 165–170

    Google Scholar 

  • Scharff, R.C. (ed.) (2002). Philosophy of technology: the technological tradition. An anthology. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, I. (1973/1989). Reason and teaching. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, I. (1970/1973). Philosophy and the curriculum. In: Reason and teaching. London: Routledge, 1973 (pp. 31–44). Reprinted in Science & Education 1992, 1(4), 384–394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiller, F. (1795/1993). Letters on the aesthetic education of man. In: F. Schiller Essays. (Edited by W. Hinderer and D. O. Dahlstrom; pp. 86–178). New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, R.M. (2011). Developing a philosophy of science education. In: F. Seroglou, V. Koulountzos, & A. Siatras (Eds.), Science and Culture: Promise, Challenge and Demand – Proceedings of the 11thIHPST & 6thGreek History, Philosophy & Science Teaching Joint Conference, July 2011, Thessaloniki, Greece (pp. 672–677). Thessaloniki: Epikentro Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, R.M. (2009a). Reforming science education: part I. The search for a philosophy of science education. Science & Education, 18, 225–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, R.M. (2009b). Reforming science education: part II. Utilizing Kieran Egan’s educational metatheory. Science & Education, 18, 251–273.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, R.M. (2007). Lyotard, postmodernism and science education. A rejoinder to Zembylas. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 39(6), 633–656.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwab, J.J. (1978). Science, culture and liberal education. Selected essays. (Edited by In Westbury and Neil J. Wilkof). Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, D. (2008). Critical essays on major curriculum theorists. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selley, N.J. (1989). The philosophy of school science. Interchange, 20 (2), 24–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shamos, M.H. (1995). The myth of scientific literacy. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherman, W. (2005). A reply to Roth.Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics and Technology Education, 5(2), 199–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherman, W. (2004). Science studies, situatedness, and instructional design in science education. A summery and critique of the promise. Canadian Journal of Science, Mathematics and Technology Education, 4, 443–465.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shulman, L.S. (1987). Knowledge and teaching: Foundations of the new reform. Harvard Educational Review, 57 (1), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (2010). Knowledge and truth. In: R. Bailey, R. Barrow, D. Carr and C. McCarthy (eds.) The SAGE handbook of the philosophy of education (pp. 283–295). London: SAGE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (ed.) (2009). The Oxford handbook of philosophy of education. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (2007). Philosophy of education. In: Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved from http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/179491/philosophy-of-education

  • Siegel, H. (2004). The bearing of philosophy of science on science education, and vice-versa: the case of constructivism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 35: 185–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (2003). Cultivating reason. In: R.R. Curren (ed.), A companion to the philosophy of education (pp. 305–319). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (2002). Multiculturalism, universalism, and science education: In search of common ground. Science Education, 86(6), 803–820.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (2001). Incommensurability, rationality, and relativism: in science, culture and science education. In: P. Hoyningen-Huene & H. Sankey (eds.), Incommensurability and related matters (pp. 207–24). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (ed.) (1997). Reason and education: Essays in honor of Israel Scheffler. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (1992). Two perspectives on reason as an educational aim: the rationality of reasonableness. Philosophy of Education, 225–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (1989). The rationality of science, critical thinking, and science education. Synthese, 80(1): 9–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (1988). Educating reason: Rationality, critical thinking and education. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (1987a). Farewell to Feyerabend. Inquiry, 32, 343–369.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (1987b). Relativism refuted. A critique of contemporary epistemological relativism. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (1978). Kuhn and Schwab on science texts and the goals of science education. Educational Theory, 28(4), 302–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siemsen, H. and Siemsen, K.H. (2009). Resettling the thoughts of Ernst Mach and the Vienna Circle in Europe: The cases of Finland and Germany. Science & Education, 18, 299–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slezak, P. and Good, R. (eds.) (2011). Thematic special issue: Pseudoscience in society and schools. Science & Education, 10 (5/6).

    Google Scholar 

  • Slezak, P. (2007). Is cognitive science relevant to teaching? Journal of Cognitive Science, 8, 171–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slezak, P. (1994a). Sociology of scientific knowledge and scientific education: Part I. Science & Education, 3(3): 265–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slezak, P. (1994b). Sociology of scientific knowledge and science education. Part II: Laboratory life under the microscope. Science & Education, 3(4): 329–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smeyers, P. (1994). Philosophy of education: Western European perspectives. In: T. Husen & T. Postlethwaite (eds.), The international encyclopedia of education, 2nded., Vol. 8 (pp. 4456–4461). London: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. & Siegel, H. (2004). Knowing, believing and understanding. Science and Education, 13(6), 553–582.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolicz, J.J. and Nunan, E.E. (1975). The philosophical and sociological foundations of science education: The demythologizing of school science. Studies in Science Education, 2, 101–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snook, I.A. (Ed.). (1972). Concepts of indoctrination. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokal, A. and Bricmont, J. (1998). Fashionable nonsense. Postmodern intellectuals’ abuse of science. New York: Picador.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokal, A. (1996a). Transgressing the boundaries: Toward a transformative hermeneutics of quantum gravity. Social Text, 46/7. (14.1–2): 217–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokal, A. (1996b). A physicist experiments with cultural studies. Lingua Franca. (July/August): 62–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, J. (1999). Meta-scientific criticisms, curriculum innovation and the propagation of scientific culture. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 31(1), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Southerland, S.A., Sinatra, G.M., and Matthews, M.R. (2001). Belief, knowledge, and science education. Educational Psychology Review, 13(4), 325–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stinner, A. (1989). Science, humanities and society—the Snow-Leavis controversy. Interchange, 20(2), 16–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suchting, W. (1992). Constructivism deconstructed. Science & Education, 1(3), 223–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suchting, W.A. (1995). Much ado about nothing: Science and hermeneutics. Science & Education, 4(2), 161–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullenger, K., Turner, S., Caplan, H., Crummey, J., Cuming, R., Charron, C., and Corey, B. (2000). Culture wars in the classroom: Prospective teachers question science. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 37(9), 895–915.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1991). The malaise of modernity. Toronto: Anansi Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1987). Overcoming epistemology. In: K. Baynes, J. Bohman, & T. McCarthy (Eds.), After philosophy. End or transformation? (pp. 464–485). London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, G. (1997). What’s the use of theory? Harvard Educational Review, 67, 75–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tibble, J.W. (ed.), (1966) The study of education. New York: Routledge and Kegan Paul Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S.E. (1972). Human understanding. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, S. & Sullenger, K. (1999). Kuhn in the classroom, Latour in the lab: science educators confront the nature-of-science debate. Science, Technology and Human Values, 24 (1), 5–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Driel, J.H. and Abell, S. (2010). Science teacher education. In: Peterson, D., Baker, E. and McGraw, B. (Eds.), International encyclopedia of education (pp. 712–718). Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Driel, J.H., Verloop, N. & de Vos, W. (1998). Developing science teachers’ pedagogical content knowledge. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 35 (6), 673–695.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vásquez-Levy, D. (2002). Essay review. Bildung-centred Didaktik: a framework for examining the educational potential of subject matter. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 34 (1), 117–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waks, L.J. (ed.) (2008). Leaders in philosophy of education. Intellectual self-portraits. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, D.F. (2003). Fundamentals of curriculum. Passion and professionalism. 2nd ed. Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum and Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, J. and Louden, W. (2003). What we don’t understand about teaching for understanding: Questions from science education. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 35(5), 545–566.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, S. (1992). Dreams of a final theory. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westaway, F.W. (1929). Science Teaching. Blackie and Son: London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westphal, M. (1999). Hermeneutics as epistemology. In: J. Greco and E. Sosa (eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 415–435). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A.N. (1929/1957). The aims of education and other essays. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winch, C. and Gingell, J. (1999). Key concepts in the philosophy of education. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953/1958). Philosophical investigations, 3rded. (Translated by G.E.M. Anscombe). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witz, K. and Lee, H. (2009). Science as an ideal: Teacher’s orientations to science and science education reform. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 41(3), 409–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witz, K. (2000). OP-ED The ‘academic problem’. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 32(1), 9–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witz, K. (1996). Science with values and values for science education.Journal of Curriculum Studies, 28(5), 597612.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yager, R.E. (Ed.) (1996). Science/technology/society as reform in science education. New York: New York State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeidler, D.L., & Sadler T.D. (2008). Social and ethical issues in science education: A prelude to action. Science & Education, 77(8–9), 799–803.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeidler, D.L, Sadler, T.D., Simmons, M.L. & Howes, E.V. (2005). Beyond STS: A research-based framework for socioscientific issues education. Science Education, 89, 357–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zembylas, M. (ed.) (2006). Special issue: Philosophy of science education. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 38(5).

    Google Scholar 

  • Zembylas, M. (2002). Constructing genealogies of teachers’ emotions in science teaching. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 39, 79–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zembylas, M. (2000). Something ‘paralogical’ under the sun: Lyotard’s postmodern condition and science education. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 32, 159–184.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roland M. Schulz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schulz, R.M. (2014). Philosophy of Education and Science Education: A Vital but Underdeveloped Relationship. In: Matthews, M. (eds) International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7654-8_39

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics