Skip to main content

Challenges of Developing Coherent Probabilistic Reasoning: Rethinking Randomness and Probability from a Stochastic Perspective

  • Chapter
Probabilistic Thinking

Part of the book series: Advances in Mathematics Education ((AME))

Abstract

The concept of probability plays a vital role in mathematics and scientific research, as well as in our everyday lives. It has also become one of the fastest growing segments of high school and college curricula, yet learning probability within school contexts has proved more difficult than many in education realize.

This chapter is in two broad parts. The first part synthesizes a discussion of randomness and probability that is situated at the nexus of bodies of literature concerned with the ontology of stochastic events and epistemology of probabilistic ideas held by people. Our synthesis foregrounds philosophical, mathematical, and psychological debates about the meaning of randomness and probability that highlight their deeply problematic nature, and therefore raises the equally problematic question of how instruction might support students’ understanding of them. We propose an approach to the design of probability instruction that focuses on the development of coherent meanings of randomness and probability—that is, schemes composed of imagery and conceptual operations that stand to support students’ coherent thinking and reasoning about situations that we see as entailing randomness and probability. The second part of the chapter reports on aspects of a sequence of classroom teaching experiments in high school that employed such an instructional approach. We draw on evidence from these experiments to highlight challenges in learning and teaching stochastic conceptions of probability. Our students’ challenges centered on re-construing given situations as idealized random experiments involving the conceptualization of an unambiguous and essentially repeatable trial, as a basis for conceiving of the probability of an event as its anticipated long-run relative frequency.

Research reported in this chapter was supported by National Science Foundation Grant No. REC-9811879. Any conclusions and recommendations stated here are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect official positions of NSF. We wish to acknowledge the contribution of Patrick W. Thompson—dissertation advisor to both authors, and principal investigator of the research project on which this chapter is based.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 219.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 279.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 279.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Because of his background as a physicist, von Mises was more concerned with the link between probability theory and natural phenomena. von Mises regarded probability as “a scientific theory of the same kind as any other branch of the exact natural science” (ibid., p. 7).

  2. 2.

    A probability curriculum starting with the axiomatic approach to probability may prevent students from developing an understanding of probability that is rooted in their experience. It is like teaching the concept of circle as a set of points (x,y) that satisfies the condition (xa)2+(yb)2=c 2, \(a,b,c,\in \mathbb{R}\), c≥0. If this definition precedes the introduction of the concept of distance and measurement of length, students may experience difficulties in visualizing the image of a circle as a set of points having the same distance from a fixed point in a two-dimensional surface.

  3. 3.

    The failure of differentiating between possible and necessary as a developmental constraint was confirmed by later studies of Kahneman and Tversky (1982) and Konold (1989). They found that even when people overcame the developmental constraint, they might still fail, or rather refuse, to distinguish uncertain events from necessary ones due to a deterministic world view.

  4. 4.

    We note that there are two other potential sources of deviation from the standard solution for the taxi problem. If a subject conceptualizes the problem as P(Taxi is Blue|Witness says “blue”), then to give the standard solution, the subject must take the witness’ accuracy rate as his or her propensity to say “Blue,” and the subject might see no compelling reason to assume this because there is no information on the witness’ propensity to say “I’m unsure”. Second, if the subject takes it as a fact that the witness said “Blue”, then P(Witness says “blue”) is 1, and hence P(Taxi is Blue|Witness says “blue”) is equal to P(Taxi is Blue).

  5. 5.

    The term “probabilistic revolution” (Krüger 1987) broadly suggests a shift in world view within the scientific community from 1800 through 1930, from a deterministic reality where everything in the world is connected by necessity in the form of cause–effect relationships, to one in which uncertainty and probability have become central and indispensable.

  6. 6.

    Consider the example given by Gigerenzer (ibid., p. 17): A scenario in probability format: The probability that a person has colon cancer is 0.3 %. If a person has colon cancer, the probability that the test is positive is 50 %; if not, the probability that the test is positive is 3 %. What is the probability that a person who tests positive actually has colon cancer? In natural frequency format, 30 out of every 10,000 people have colon cancer. Of these 30 people, 15 will test positive. Of the remaining 9,970 people, 300 will still test positive. To solve the problem in probability format, one uses Bayes’ theorem: (0.3 % × 50 %)/(0.3 % × 50 % + 99.7 % × 3 %). In the natural frequency format, 15/(300+15) will suffice. However, to justify substituting numbers in place of the percentages requires understanding that the underlying proportional relationships will remain constant no matter the population’s size.

  7. 7.

    We relate an anecdote in anticipation of Bayesians’ objections to this statement: In a recent conversation with a prominent Bayesian probabilist, we asked “Suppose, at a given moment, and for whatever reason, you judge that the probability of an event is 0.4. At that moment, what does “0.4” mean to you?” He responded that it meant that he anticipates that this event will occur 40 % of the time.

  8. 8.

    The authors were members of the research team that conducted the project.

  9. 9.

    Part of this data was previously reported in Saldanha (2010, 2011).

  10. 10.

    Adapted from Konold (2002).

  11. 11.

    The following symbol key is used for discussion protocols: “Instr” denotes an utterance made by the instructor; “[…]” denotes text that is not included in the presented excerpt; “—” denotes that the word or statement immediately preceding it was abruptly halted in speech. Underlined words and statements denote that they were emphasized in speech. Statements enclosed in parentheses generally provide contextual information not captured by utterances, such as participants’ nonverbal actions or the duration of pauses or silences in a discussion.

  12. 12.

    The distinction between sampling with and without replacement had been established in classroom discussions prior to this point in the teaching experiment.

  13. 13.

    “Int” denotes an utterance made by the interviewer.

  14. 14.

    Our second teaching experiment consisted of 22 lessons, and eventually addressed the concepts of conditional probability, independence, and Bayes Theorem.

References

  • Biehler, R. (1994). Probabilistic thinking, statistical reasoning, and the search for causes—do we need a probabilistic revolution after we have taught data analysis? Paper presented at the 4th international conference on teaching statistics, July 2004, Minneapolis, Minnesota.

    Google Scholar 

  • David, F. N. (1962). Games, gods, and gambling: the origin and history of probability and statistical ideas from the earliest times to the Newtonian era. New York: Hafner.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti, B. (1970). Theory of probability: a critical introductory treatment. London: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doob, J. L. (1996). The development of rigor in mathematical probability. The American Mathematical Monthly, 3(7), 586–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, R., & Konold, C. (1992). The psychology of learning probability. In F. S. Gordon & S. P. Gordon (Eds.), Statistics for the twenty-first century (pp. 151–164). Washington: Math. Assoc. of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, T. L. (1973). Theories of probability: an examination of foundations. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischbein, E. (1975). The intuitive sources of probabilistic thinking in children. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fischbein, E., & Gazit, A. (1984). Does the teaching of probability improve probabilistic intuitions? Educational Studies in Mathematics, 15, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischbein, E., Nello, M. S., & Marino, M. S. (1991). Factors affecting probabilistic judgments in children and adolescents. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 22, 523–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischbein, E., & Schnarch, D. (1997). The evolution with age of probabilistic, intuitively based misconceptions. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 28, 96–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, J., & Ahlgren, A. (1988). Difficulties in learning basic concepts in probability and statistics: implications for research. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 19, 44–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (1994). Why the distinction between single-event probabilities and frequencies is relevant for psychology (and vice versa). In G. Wright & P. Ayton (Eds.), Subjective probability. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (1996). The psychology of good judgment: frequency formats and simple algorithms. Journal of Medical Decision Making, 16, 273–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (1998). Ecological intelligence: an adaptation for frequencies. In D. D. Cummins & C. Allen (Eds.), The evolution of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J. (1965). The estimation of probabilities: an essay on modern Bayesian methods. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1992). Bully for brontosaurus: further reflections in natural history. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, D. (1979). The chance and probability concepts project. Teaching Statistics, 1(3), 66–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, D. (1983). School pupils’ probability concepts. Teaching Statistics, 5(2), 34–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, D. (1987). Probability concepts: putting research into practice. Teaching Statistics, 9(1), 8–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, D. (1989). School pupils’ understanding of randomness. In R. Morris (Ed.), Studies of mathematics education: the teaching of statistics, Paris, UNESCO (pp. 27–39).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1975). The emergence of probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2001). An introduction to probability and inductive logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harel, G., & Confrey, J. (1994). The development of multiplicative reasoning in the learning of mathematics. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins, A., & Kapadia, R. (1984). Children’s conceptions of probability: a psychological and pedagogical review. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 15, 349–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendricks, V. F., Pedersen, S. A., & Jorgensen, K. F. (2001). Probability theory: philosophy, recent history and relations to science. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, R., & Gigerenzer, G. (1999). The “conjunction fallacy” revisited: how intelligent inferences look like reasoning errors. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 12, 275–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1972). Subjective probability: a judgment of representativeness. Cognitive Psychology, 3, 430–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1973). On the psychology of prediction. Psychological Review, 80, 237–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). Evidential impact of base rates. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases (pp. 153–160). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kolmogorov, A. N. (1950). Foundations of the theory of probability. New York: Chelsea.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konold, C. (1989). Informal conceptions of probability. Cognition and Instruction, 6(1), 59–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konold, C. (1995). Issues in assessing conceptual understanding in probability and statistics. Journal of Statistics Education, 3(1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Konold, C. (2002). Prob SIM user guide. Amherst: Author.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konold, C., & Miller, C. (1996). Prob Sim. Computer program, Amherst, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konold, C., Pollatsek, A., Well, A., Lohmeier, J., & Lipson, A. (1993). Inconsistencies in students’ reasoning about probability. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education, 24(5), 393–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krüger, L. (1987). The probabilistic revolution. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Y., & Thompson, P. W. (2007). Teachers’ understandings of probability. Cognition and Instruction, 25(2), 113–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metz, K. (1998). Emergent understanding and attribution of randomness: comparative analysis of the reasoning of primary grade children and undergraduates. Cognition and Instruction, 16(3), 285–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, D. (1990). Uncertainty. In L. A. Steen (Ed.), On the shoulders of giants: new approaches to numeracy (pp. 95–137). Washington: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nilsson, P. (2003). Experimentation as a tool for discovering mathematical concepts of probability. In Proceedings of the 3rd conference of the European Society for Research in Mathematics Education, Bellaria, Italy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1951/1975). The origin of the idea of chance in children. London: Routledge & Kagan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piatelli-Palmarini, M. (1994). Inevitable illusions: how mistakes of reason rule our minds. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinato, L. (1986). De Finetti’s logic of uncertainty and its impact on statistical thinking and practice. In P. K. Goel & A. Zellner (Eds.), Bayesian Inference and decision techniques: essays in honor of Bruno de Finetti. New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ritson, I. L. (1998). The development of primary school children’s understanding of probability. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Queen’s University, Belfast.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saldanha, L. A. (2004). “Is this sample unusual?”: an investigation of students exploring connections between sampling distributions and statistical inference. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Vanderbilt University, Nashville, TN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saldanha, L. (2010). Conceptual issues in quantifying expectation: insights from students’ experiences in designing sampling simulations. In Proceedings of the 8th international conference on teaching statistics (ICOTS-8), Ljubljana, Slovenia, July 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saldanha, L. (2011). Aspects of conceiving stochastic experiments. In B. Ubuz (Ed.), Proceedings of the 35th conference of the international group for the psychology of mathematics education (Vol. 4, pp. 97–104). Ankara: PME.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saldanha, L., & Thompson, P. W. (2002). Conceptions of sample and their relationship to statistical inference. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 51(3), 257–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saldanha, L., & Thompson, P. (2007). Exploring connections between sampling distributions and statistical inference: an analysis of students’ engagement and thinking in the context of instruction involving repeated sampling. International Electronic Journal of Mathematics Education, 2(3), 270–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, D. L., & Goldman, S. R. (1996). Why people are not like marbles in an urn: an effect of context on statistical reasoning. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 10, 99–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, D. L., Goldman, S. R., Vye, N. J., & Barron, B. J. (1998). Aligning everyday and mathematical reasoning: the case of sampling assumptions. In S. P. Lojoie (Ed.), Reflections on statistics: learning, teaching, and assessment in grades K-12 (pp. 233–274). Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedlmeier, P. (1999). Improving statistical reasoning: theoretical models and practical implications. Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaughnessy, J. M. (1977). Misconceptions of probability: an experiment with a small-group, activity-based, model-building approach to introductory probability at the college level. Educational Studies in Mathematics, 8, 295–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaughnessy, J. M. (1992). Research in probability and statistics: reflections and directions. In D. A. Grouws (Ed.), Handbook of research on mathematics teaching and learning (pp. 465–494). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Todhunter, I. (1949). A history of mathematical theory of probability: from the time of Pascal to that of Laplace. New York: Chelsea.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises, R. (1957). Probability, statistics, and truth. London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Plato, J. (1994). Creating modern probability: its mathematics, physics, and philosophy in historical perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luis Saldanha .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Saldanha, L., Liu, Y. (2014). Challenges of Developing Coherent Probabilistic Reasoning: Rethinking Randomness and Probability from a Stochastic Perspective. In: Chernoff, E., Sriraman, B. (eds) Probabilistic Thinking. Advances in Mathematics Education. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7155-0_20

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics