Skip to main content

Epistemological Scepticism and Religious Belief

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Hume's Critique of Religion: 'Sick Men's Dreams'

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 72))

  • 735 Accesses

Abstract

Even a cursory examination of the Treatise and the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding suffices to uncover a large number of passages that indicate that Hume is committed to an extremely wide-ranging and radical form of epistemological scepticism. Unlike some alleged sceptics, Hume is not merely calling into question our ability to know things for certain: his target is rather our supposed capacity to have beliefs that possess any positive degree of epistemic justification. Classical Pyrrhonean sceptics of the kind exemplified by Sextus Empiricus denied that any belief, no matter how seemingly straightforward and initially plausible, possessed more epistemic justification than any other belief (see Bailey 2002, 135–7). And in the case of the overwhelming majority of beliefs, Hume seems content to embrace this Pyrrhonean attitude.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The only beliefs that might possibly be viewed by Hume as wholly immune to Pyrrhonean doubt are a person’s beliefs about the content of his or her present perceptions. In the Treatise (1739, 1.4.2.7/190), Hume declares, ‘for since all actions and sensations of the mind are known to us by consciousness, they must necessarily appear in every particular what they are, and be what they appear. Every thing that enters the mind, being in reality a perception, ’tis impossible any thing shou’d to feeling appear different. This were to suppose, that even where we are most intimately conscious, we might be mistaken’.

  2. 2.

    As Philo is specifically engaging with Cleanthes at the level of what beliefs are acceptable by everyday, non-philosophical standards when these are applied with the care and precision found in the most compelling scientific reasoning, Tweyman (1986, 9–10) is mistaken in interpreting Philo’s arguments in Parts 2–11 as Pyrrhonean arguments intended to persuade an initially dogmatic Cleanthes to embrace mitigated scepticism. Philo’s arguments are intended rather to answer the charge that even a mitigated sceptic should, if he is to act in good faith, embrace various religious beliefs.

  3. 3.

    Hume is not objecting here to the imagination playing a crucial role in our philosophical and everyday deliberations. By Hume’s own admission, we would have no beliefs about any matter of fact beyond the content of our present perceptions without the assistance of the imagination (see 1739, 1.4.4.1/225; 1.4.7.3/265). Hume’s strictures are directed solely towards the human tendency to form beliefs in an indiscriminate and promiscuous fashion even when prompted by weak rather than strong associative links.

  4. 4.

    This analysis of the conception of veritic epistemic luck is taken from Duncan Pritchard’s highly illuminating discussion of the relationship between the epistemic standing of beliefs and different varieties of epistemic luck. See Pritchard 2005, 145–52, 173–8.

References

  • Bailey, A. 2002. Sextus empiricus and pyrrhonean scepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T. 1999. Introduction to David Hume. In An enquiry concerning human understanding, ed. T. Beauchamp. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1739. A treatise of human nature, ed. D.F. Norton and M.J. Norton. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1772a. An enquiry concerning human understanding, ed. T.L. Beauchamp. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1779. Dialogues concerning natural religion. In Hume’s dialogues concerning natural religion, 2nd ed, ed. N. Kemp Smith. Edinburgh: Thomas Nelson, 1947.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1932. The letters of David Hume, 2 vols., ed. J.Y.T Greig. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemp Smith, N. 1947. Introduction. In Hume’s dialogues concerning natural religion, ed. N. Kemp Smith. Edinburgh: Thomas Nelson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noxon, J. 1968. Hume’s agnosticism. In Hume: A collection of critical essays, ed. V.C. Chappell, 361–383. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. 2005. Epistemic luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pyle, A. 2006. Hume’s dialogues concerning natural religion. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tweyman, S. 1986. Scepticism and belief in Hume’s dialogues concerning natural religion. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bailey, A., O’Brien, D. (2014). Epistemological Scepticism and Religious Belief. In: Hume's Critique of Religion: 'Sick Men's Dreams'. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 72. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6615-0_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics