Skip to main content

Debating the Power and Scope of Adaptation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Philosophy of Biology

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 1))

Abstract

How often should we invoke adaptation to explain the features of the biological world? Ideally, just as often as a history of natural selection explains the form and function of those features. This is partly an empirical question about evolutionary history. But it is also partly a question about the methods we should use to investigate evolutionary history. And the answers to the question have consequences for our views about our place in the biological world. Controversy over these issues is at least as old as Darwin. In contemporary evolutionary biology this controversy continues as the debate over adaptationism, raising a number of deep issues about the science of evolutionary biology and our philosophical understanding of the science. This makes adaptationism particularly relevant to science education, for the controversy provides traction on large scale questions about the nature of evidence and explanation, the plurality of scientific methods, and how science should guide our views about our biological nature. In this chapter I will investigate some of the issues about evidence and methodology brought out by the controversy, and I will argue that the debate over adaptationism provides an excellent and informative example of science in action. This is more than a mere philosophical controversy, for it interacts with the practice of biology in fascinating and complex ways.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Indeed, Gould and Vrba (1982) found this phenomenon so prevalent in evolutionary history that they recommended a new term for adaptations co-opted to play a different role: exaptation.

  2. 2.

    Evolutionary biologists take fitness to be a measure of reproductive success, usually expected number of offspring. However, there are a variety of fitness measures available and determining the correct interpretation of fitness is notoriously complex (see, e.g., Ariew and Lewontin (2004) or Beatty (1992)).

  3. 3.

    Beatty (2004) and Beatty and Desjardins (2009) provide excellent discussion of this case in support of their analysis of why evolutionary history matters.

  4. 4.

    While the definitions are directly quoted from Godfrey-Smith (2001), I have changed to order to fit my exposition.

  5. 5.

    See Depew this volume on this topic.

  6. 6.

    For canonical defenses of optimality modeling see Parker and Maynard Smith (1990) and Seger and Stubblefield (1996).

  7. 7.

    Sober (2008) provides a precise analysis of testing in evolutionary biology that takes these model selection issues seriously.

  8. 8.

    Assume the fit is statistically rigorous. The protocol also assumes that sufficient evolutionary time has elapsed for selection to operate (Sober 2008, pp. 199–200).

  9. 9.

    Sober’s protocol is based on the law of likelihood and so can easily be extended to incorporate constraint hypotheses, so long as such hypotheses specify an appropriate likelihood function. Pigliucci and Kaplan (2000) have an alternative protocol for contrasting selection and constraint that compares the probabilities of transition between possible forms.

  10. 10.

    Lloyd (2005) makes an interesting argument of this kind about how methodological biases obscured evolutionary research on human female orgasms.

References

  • Amundson, R. 1988. Logical adaptationism. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11: 505–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. 1990. Doctor Dennett and Doctor Pangloss: Perfection and selection in psychology and biology. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13: 577–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. 1996. Historical development of the concept of adaptation. In Adaptation, ed. M.R. Rose and G.V. Lauder, 11–53. San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, A., and R.C. Lewontin. 2004. The confusions of fitness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55: 347–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. 1992. Fitness: Theoretical contexts. In Keywords in evolutionary biology, ed. E.F. Keller and E.A. Lloyd, 115–119. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. 2004. Chance variation: Darwin on orchids. Philosophy of Science 73: 629–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J., and E.C. Desjardins. 2009. Natural selection and history. Biology and Philosophy 24: 231–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. 1990. Adaptation and environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R., and M.D. Rausher. 1996. Testing adapationism: A comment on Orzack and Sober. American Naturalist 148: 189–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. 2005. The adapting mind: Evolutionary psychology and the persistent quest for human nature. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 1976. The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 1995. Darwin’s dangerous idea. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 2011. Homunculi rule: Reflections on Darwinian populations and natural selection by Peter Godfrey-Smith. Biology and Philosophy 26: 475–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, T. 1973. Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. The American Biology Teacher 35: 125–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downes, S. M. 2010. Evolutionary psychology. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, E.N. Zalta, ed. URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/evolutionary-psychology/.

  • Felsenstein, F. 1985. Phylogenies and the comparative method. The American Naturalist 125: 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forber, P. 2009. Spandrels and a pervasive problem of evidence. Biology and Philosophy 24: 247–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forber, P., and E. Griffith. 2011. Historical reconstruction: Gaining access to the deep past. Philosophy and Theory in Biology 3. URL:http://www.philosophyandtheoryinbiology.org.

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2001. Three kinds of adaptationism. In Adaptationism and optimality, ed. S.H. Orzack and E. Sober, 335–357. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2009. Darwinian populations and natural selection. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1980. The Panda’s thumb: More reflections in natural history. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J., and R.C. Lewontin. 1979. The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian paradigm: A critique of the adaptationist programme. Proceedings of the Royal Society London, Series B, Biological Sciences 205: 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J., and E.S. Vrba. 1982. Exaptation—a missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology 8: 4–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E. 2009. In what sense does ‘nothing makes sense except in the light of evolution’? Acta Biotheoretica 57: 11–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haig, D. 1997. The social gene. In Behavioral ecology: An evolutionary approach, ed. J.R. Krebs and N.B. Davies, 284–304. London: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, B.W., and M.K. Nishiguchi. 2004. Counterillumination in the Hawaiian bobtail squid, Euphrymnascolopes Berry (Mollusca: Cephalopoda). Marine Biology 144: 1151–1155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kampourakis, K. 2013. Teaching about adaptation: Why evolutionary history matters. Science & Education 22(2): 173–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1985. Vaulting ambition. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1993. The advancement of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K.N., and G.R. Brown. 2002. Sense and nonsense: Evolutionary perspectives on human behaviour. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. 2007. Adaptation. In The Cambridge companion to the philosophy of biology, ed. D.L. Hull and M. Ruse, 1–21. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. 2009. Seven types of adaptationism. Biology and Philosophy 24: 161–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E.A. 2005. The case of the female orgasm: Bias in the science of evolution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E.A. 2007. Units and levels of selection. In The Cambridge companion to the philosophy of biology, ed. D.L. Hull and M. Ruse, 44–65. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1983. How to carry out the adaptationist program? The American Naturalist 121: 324–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nyholm, S.V., and M.J. McFall-Ngai. 2004. The winnowing: Establishing the squid-vibrio symbiosis. Nature Reviews Microbiology 2: 632–642.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack, S. H., and P. Forber. 2010. Adaptationism. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, E.N. Zalta, ed. URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/adaptationism/.

  • Orzack, S.H., and E. Sober. 1994a. Optimality models and the test of adaptationism. American Naturalist 143: 361–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack, S.H., and E. Sober. 1994b. How (not) to test an optimality model. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 9: 265–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orzack, S.H., and E. Sober. 1996. How to formulate and test adaptationism. The American Naturalist 148: 202–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parker, G.A., and J. Maynard Smith. 1990. Optimality theory in evolutionary biology. Nature 348: 27–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., and J. Kaplan. 2000. The fall and rise of Dr. Pangloss: Adaptationism and the spandrels paper 20 years later. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 15: 66–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. 2009. Optimality modeling in a suboptimal world. Biology and Philosophy 24: 183–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queller, D. 1995. The spaniels of St. Marx and the Panglossian paradox: A critique of a rhetorical programme. The Quarterly Review of Biology 70: 485–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reeve, H.K., and P.W. Sherman. 1993. Adaptation and the goals of evolutionary research. The Quarterly Review of Biology 68: 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, M.R., and G.V. Lauder. 1996. Adaptation. San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seger, J., and J. Stubblefield. 1996. Optimization and adaptation. In Adaptation, ed. M.R. Rose and G.V. Lauder, 93–124. San Diego: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S. 2010. Never pure: Historical studies of science as if it was produced by people with bodies, situated in time, space, culture, and society, and struggling for credibility and authority. Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 1984. The nature of selection. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 1996. Evolution and optimality: Feathers, bowling balls, and the thesis of adaptationism. Philosophic Exchange 26: 41–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 2008. Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 2003. Thought in a hostile world. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. 2012. The evolved apprentice: How evolution made humans unique. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J., and P. Godfrey-Smith. 2009. Adaptationism and the adaptive landscape. Biology and Philosophy 24: 199–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G.C. 1966. Adaptation and natural selection: A critique of some current evolutionary thought. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Forber .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Forber, P. (2013). Debating the Power and Scope of Adaptation. In: Kampourakis, K. (eds) The Philosophy of Biology. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6537-5_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics