Skip to main content

Mathematics as the Art of Abstraction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Argument of Mathematics

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 30))

Abstract

Mathematics, like the sciences, proceeds by a process of abstraction, so that mathematical claims like scientific claims are neither true nor false, but only true or false in an application of the theory to which they belong. A proof in mathematics is meant to show that a claim follows from the assumptions of a particular mathematical theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Appendix 1 for a further discussion of this.

  2. 2.

    We recognize this in English with the distinction between count and non-count (mass) terms. See (Epstein, 1994) for a discussion of the concept of ‘thing’ in our reasoning.

  3. 3.

    Benjamin Lee Whorf says: Our tongue makes no distinction between numbers counted on discrete entities and numbers that are simply ‘counting itself.’ Habitual thought then assumes that in the latter the numbers are just as much counted on ‘something’ as in the former. This is objectification. (Whorf, 1941, 140)

    In a similar vein, Aristotle says:

    Whether if soul did not exist time would exist or not, is a question that may fairly be asked; for if there cannot be some one to count there cannot be anything that can be counted, so that evidently there cannot be number; for number is either what has been, or what can be, counted. (Aristotle, 1930, Book IV, 223a)

  4. 4.

    Reuben Hersh (2006) discusses this issue from a similar perspective.

  5. 5.

    See the presentation by Carnielli and me in (Epstein and Carnielli, 1989)

  6. 6.

    Compare the presentation of Euclidean geometry in (Epstein, 2006). Albert Einstein says:

    Geometry sets out from certain conceptions such as ‘plane,’ ‘point,’ and ‘straight line,’ with which we are able to associate more or less definite ideas, and from certain simple propositions (axioms) which, in virtue of these ideas, we are inclined to accept as ‘true.’ Then, on the basis of a logical process, the justification of which we feel ourselves compelled to admit, all remaining propositions are shown to follow from those axioms, i.e., they are proven. A proposition is then correct (‘true’) when it has been derived in the recognised manner from the axioms. The question of the ‘truth’ of the individual geometrical propositions is thus reduced to one of the ‘truth’ of the axioms. Now it has long been known that the last question is not only unanswerable by the methods of geometry, but that it is in itself entirely without meaning. We cannot ask whether it is true that only one straight line goes through two points. We can only say that Euclidean geometry deals with things called ‘straight lines,’ to each of which is ascribed the property of being uniquely determined by two points situated on it. The concept ‘true’ does not tally with the assertions of pure geometry, because by the word ‘true’ we are eventually in the habit of designating always the correspondence with a ‘real’ object; geometry, however, is not concerned with the relation of ideas involved in it to objects of experience, but only with the logical connection of these ideas among themselves.

    It is not difficult to understand why, in spite of this, we feel constrained to call the propositions of geometry ‘true.’ Geometrical ideas correspond to more or less exact objects in nature, and these last are undoubtedly the exclusive cause of the genesis of these ideas. (Einstein, 1915, 1–2).

  7. 7.

    Though I criticize Hersh here, there is much good in his book, and reading it stimulated me to write this paper.

  8. 8.

    See the axiomatization due to Lesław Szczerba of Euclidean plane geometry in (Epstein, 2006). Szczerba assures me that no one has a simpler independent axiomatization.

  9. 9.

    See (Davies, 2005) for fuller discussions of these and more examples of methods of proof that are currently in debate in the mathematical community.

  10. 10.

    Or in the case of David Isles (1981, 2004) that arithmetical functions such as multiplication or exponentiation do not obviously lead to places on the list of numbers we can count to by 1’s.

  11. 11.

    The picture comes from (Nelsen, 1993, 69). Martin Gardner, in (Gardner, 1973) from which Nelsen takes this example, says:

    The first n consecutive positive integers can be depicted by dots in triangular formation. Two such triangles fit together to form a rectangular array containing n(n + 1) dots. Because each triangle is half of the rectangle, we see at once that the formula for the number of dots in each triangle is \(n(n + 1)/2\). This simple proof goes back to the ancient Greeks (Gardner, 1973, 114).

  12. 12.

    A colleague said that the picture is convincing for n = 6 but not for any larger numbers. But then why not say it is good only for circles colored and laid out in this manner? See (Sherry, 2009) for a fuller discussion of this point.

  13. 13.

    We can easily see that the method does not depend on these specific triangles and rectangles. Indeed, in ancient times often just one example, such as using ‘5’ and ‘8’ here (which is the ratio as close as the printer or computer monitor can manage), was given and the reader was expected to see that the method of proof or calculation was quite general. See (Bashmakova and Smirnova, 2000).

    The issue of when we are justified in understanding specific parts of a diagram as variable is examined in (Kulpa, 2009). The counterpart in reasoning with formulas is given a precise answer in classical predicate logic by the theorem on constants: if a name appears in a theorem but does not appear in the axioms, then it can be replaced by a variable that is quantified universally (Epstein, 2006, Lemma 10.b). Kulpa’s paper also surveys recent work on formalizing reasoning with diagrams.

  14. 14.

    See (Breger, 2000) for a discussion of this point and more on the nature of abstraction in mathematics.

  15. 15.

    As I show with examples in (Epstein, 2006), first-order logic is rarely appropriate because much mathematics requires second-order assumptions. Second-order logic and set-theory give no unique standard because there are many systems of those that differ too much. Further, all those systems are based on a metaphysics that denies a mathematics of process as distinct from things (see Epstein, 2010). Moreover, it is quite common to establish a theorem in a formalized theory by semantic means rather than with a syntactic proof, as can be seen in (Epstein, 2006).

  16. 16.

    The translation here comes from (Dauben, 1979, 128–129).

  17. 17.

    Frege (1980, 39–40). Frege strongly disputes Hilbert’s view (op. cit., 43–47).

  18. 18.

    This issue in historical context is discussed in (Detlefsen, 2005).

  19. 19.

    This is how I developed the general framework for semantics in (Epstein, 1990). Rather than viewing propositional logics as about abstract things called ‘propositions,’ I saw them as ways to reason using ordinary language and abstractions of that. Rather than looking for the ‘right’ logic that captures exactly the properties of such abstract things, I saw that what we pay attention to in our abstracting, what aspects of ordinary language claims we deem important, determines the appropriateness of the logic we choose. As we vary the aspect we deem important, we vary the logic. That variation, I saw, can be described by devising an abstraction of our propositional logics—an abstraction of our abstractions. The general structures that arise are then worth investigating, not only for their own interest but for the relations among logics they illuminate and for the assumptions about how to reason well they uncover. I did not deny the abstract, for how could I show that there are no such things as abstract propositions? Rather, I focused on the process of abstracting, and that gave rise to new mathematics that is grounded in experience. See (Epstein, 1988) for a summary.

    This is also what I do in (Epstein, 2006). I present formal logic as an abstraction of reasoning. By considering propositions as actual utterances or inscriptions rather than making the abstraction to treat different utterances as the same thing, I give a formal logic that resolves the liar paradox. By considering how we assign truth-values to atomic propositions rather than assuming that they come with truth-values, I develop a simple modification of classical mathematical logic that deals with names that do not refer.

  20. 20.

    Walter Carnielli and I (Epstein and Carnielli, 1989) use the historical development of the theory of computable functions to recapitulate the path of abstraction in that subject. This is the ‘genetic’ method of teaching, long favored by George Pólya, as discussed in (Pólya, 1963).

  21. 21.

    For a comprehensive discussion of current views of mathematics see the excellent survey in the introduction to (Ferreirós and Gray, 2006).

  22. 22.

    In (Putnam, 1967) he says that his view of mathematics as modal logic is equivalent to taking mathematics as based on set theory. In (Putnam, 1975, 72) he says: The main question we must speak to is simply, what is the point? Given that one can either take modal notions as primitive and regard talk of mathematical existence as derived, or the other way around, what is the advantage to taking the modal notions as the basic ones?

  23. 23.

    John Skorupski (2005) discusses Mill’s views and suggests a program for empiricists that is similar to what I have done here.

References

  • Aristotle (1930). Physics (R. P. Hardie & R. K. Gaye, Trans.). In W. D. Ross (Ed.), The works of Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bashmakova, I. G, & Smirnova, G. S. (2000). Geometry: The first universal language of mathematics. In E. Grosholz & H. Breger (Eds.), The growth of mathematical knowledge (pp. 331–340). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bôcher, M. (1904). The fundamental conceptions and methods of mathematics. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 11, 115–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breger, H. (2000). Tacit knowledge and mathematical progress. In E. Grosholz & H. Breger (Eds.), The growth of mathematical knowledge (pp. 221–230). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L. E. J. ([1983] 1912). Intuitionism and formalism (Trans. by A. Dresden of ‘Intuitionisme en formalisme’, Inaugural Address at the University of Amsterdam). In P. Benacerraf & H. Putnam (Eds.), Philosophy of mathematics: Selected readings (pp. 77–89). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bryant, P., & Nuñes, T. (2002). Children’s understanding of mathematics. In U. Goswami (Ed.), Blackwell handbook of childhood cognitive development (pp. 412–439). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cantor, G. (1883). Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. Leipzig: Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dauben, J. W. (1979). Georg Cantor: His mathematics and philosophy of the infinite. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, E. B. (2005). Whither mathematics? Notices of the American Mathematical Society, 52, 1350–1356.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H., & Smedt, J. D. (2010). The innateness hypothesis and mathematical concepts. Topoi, 29, 3–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Detlefsen, M. (2005). Formalism. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic (pp. 236–317). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. ([1961] 1915). Relativity: The special and general theory (R. Lawson, Trans.). New York: Crown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. L. (1988). A general framework for semantics for propositional logics. Text of invited address to the VII Latin American Symposium on Mathematical Logic. Contemporary Mathematics, 69, 149–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. L. (1990). Propositional logics. Dordrecht: Kluwer. (2nd ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995. 2nd ed. with corrections, Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. L. (1994). Predicate logic. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. (Reprinted, 2000, Belmont, CA: Wadsworth)

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. L. (1999). The metaphysical basis of logic. Manuscrito, 22(2), 133–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. L. (2006). Classical mathematical logic. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. L. (2010). The internal structure of predicates and names with an analysis of reasoning about process. Typescript available at www.AdvancedReasoningForum.org

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. L. (2012). Valid inferences. In J.-Y. Béziau & M. E. Coniglio (Eds.), Logic without frontiers: Festschrift for Walter Alexandre Carnielli on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 105–112). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. L., & Carnielli, W. A. ([2008] 1989). Computability: Computable functions, logic, and the foundations of mathematics. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth & Brooks/Cole. (3rd ed., ARF, 2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fallis, D. (1998). Review of Hersh, 1993 et al. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 63, 1196–1200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferreirós, J., & Gray, J. J. (Eds.). (2006). The architecture of modern mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980). Gottlob Frege: The philosophical and mathematical correspondence. Edited by G. Gabriel, H. Hermes, F. Kambartel, C. Thiel & A. Veraart. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, M. (1973). Mathematical games. Scientific American, 229(October), 114–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, G. H. (1928). Mathematical proof. Mind, 38, 11–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hersh, R. (1997). What is mathematics, really? London: Jonathan Cape.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hersh, R. (2006). Inner vision, outer truth. In R. Hersh (Ed.), 18 unconventional essays about the nature of mathematics (pp. 320–326). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Isles, D. (1981). Remarks on the notion of standard non-isomorphic natural number series. In F. Richman (Ed.), Constructive mathematics, proceedings of the New Mexico State University Conference, Vol. 873 of Lecture notes in mathematics (pp. 111–134). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Isles, D. (2004). Questioning articles of faith: A re-creation of the history and theology of arithmetic. Bulletin of Advanced Reasoning and Knowledge, 2, 51–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1975). Bolzano’s ideal of algebraic analysis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 6, 229–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kulpa, Z. (2009). Main problems of diagrammatic reasoning. Part I: The generalization problem. Foundations of Science, 14(1–2), 75–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Núñez, R. E. (2000). Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into being. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. ([1981] 1765). New essays on human understanding (Trans. and edited by Peter Remnant and Jonathan Bennett). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (1996). Philosophy of mathematics and mathematical practice in the seventeenth century. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (2000). On mathematical explanation. In E. Grosholz & H. Breger (Eds.), The growth of mathematical knowledge (pp. 103–119). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1874). A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive, being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation (8th ed.). New York: Harper & Brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (1977). Logicism revisted. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 28, 90–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World. (Reprinted by Hackett Publishing Company, Indianapolis, IN, 1979)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelsen, R. B. (1993). Proofs without words. Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nidditch, P. H. (1960). Elementary logic of science and mathematics. Glencoe, IL: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931). Collected papers (Vol. I). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1921). The foundations of science (G. B. Halstead, Trans.). New York: The Science Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pólya, G. ([1977] 1963). Mathematical methods in science, Vol. IX of Studies in mathematics. Revised edition edited by Leon Bowden. Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Mathematics without foundations. Journal of Philosophy, 64(1), 5–22. (Reprinted in Putnam, Mathematics, matter, and method: Philosophical papers, (Vol. 1, pp. 43–59). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). What is mathematical truth? In Mathematics, matter and method: Philosophical papers (Vol. 1, pp. 60–78). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M., & Kushner, D. (1987). Explanation, independence, and realism in mathematics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38, 141–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. ([1901] 1986). Mathematics and the metaphysicians. In Mysticism and logic (pp. 75–95). London: Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer, W. W. (1943). Mathematician’s delight. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherry, D. (2009). The role of diagrams in mathematical arguments. Foundations of Science, 14(1–2), 59–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skorupski, J. (2005). Later empiricism and logical positivism. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic (pp. 51–80). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (2000). Penrose and platonism. In E. Grosholz & H. Breger (Eds.), The growth of mathematical knowledge (pp. 133–141). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Dantzig, D. (1956). Is \(1{0}^{1{0}^{10} }\) a finite number? Dialectica, 9, 273–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whorf, B. L. (1941). The relation of habitual thought to language. In L. Spier (Ed.), Language, culture, and personality: Essays in memory of Edward Sapir (pp. 75–93). Menasha, WI: Sapir Memorial Publication Fund. (Reprinted in Carroll J. B. (Ed.). (1956). Language, thought, and reality: Selected writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf (pp. 134–159). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications on Pure and Applied Mathematics, 13(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilder, R. L. (1944). The nature of mathematical proof. The American Mathematical Monthly, 51(6), 309–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

A previous version of this chapter was published as ‘On Mathematics’ in Richard L. Epstein, Logic as the Art of Reasoning Well, Advanced Reasoning Forum, 2008, 411–441. I am grateful to Fred Kroon, Charlie Silver, Carlo Cellucci, Jeremy Avigad, David Isles, Reuben Hersh, Ian Grant, Paul Livingston, and Andrew Aberdein for their comments on earlier versions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard L. Epstein .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Epstein, R.L. (2013). Mathematics as the Art of Abstraction. In: Aberdein, A., Dove, I. (eds) The Argument of Mathematics. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 30. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6534-4_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics