Skip to main content

Rousseau on Poverty

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Economic Justice

Part of the book series: AMINTAPHIL: The Philosophical Foundations of Law and Justice ((AMIN,volume 4))

Abstract

This paper presents Rousseau’s account of poverty as a means of demonstrating the connection between economic and political justice in his political writings. After briefly presenting some of the causes of poverty that he identifies, I look at three key features of poverty. Poverty is relative in nature, it adversely affects the virtue of the individual and the security of the state, and it demands both individual and collective response informed by equity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is contrary to the critique Proudhon and other nineteenth century readers of Rousseau offered. Proudhon argued that Rousseau provided no insight into the economic organization of society whatsoever, that Rousseau was concerned only with political rights rather than economic rights, and that Rousseau ignored labor relations and the rules for wealth acquisition. The view I present attempts to make the connection between Rousseau’s discussion of politics and his discussion of economics more explicit. For a careful study and analysis of Proudhon’s reading of Rousseau, see Noland 1967, 33–54.

  2. 2.

    Rousseau proposes spontaneous festivals as the appropriate entertainment for a virtuous republic. See Letter to D’Alembert (1960).

  3. 3.

    Sharon Vaughan conflates being poor and poverty in her account (2008, Chapter 4). In contrast, I argue that Rousseau distinguishes what Vaughan and others call “the noble poor” from those who become impoverished and oppressed by the luxuries and wealth of others. The difference, as I show, is most evident in the virtue of the poor and the lack of virtue or the diminishment of virtue in those who are impoverished by economic disparities. It is also worth noting that Rousseau had firsthand experience of poverty and, in both autobiographical works and political essays, valorizes the life and virtue of the poor.

  4. 4.

    Jeff Noonan argues that Rousseau articulates a needs-based social morality distinct from the rights-based social morality of the other social contract theorists (Noonan 2006). The question of what constitutes appropriate needs, of course, is not really what is at stake in shifting the discussion from rights to needs. Each society creates its own set of needs based on social expectation for such things as labor, dress, housing, food, and entertainment.

  5. 5.

    Rousseau does not use natural law as the basis for the social contract in the manner that Locke does. Nevertheless, in his stronger communitarian moments, he appeals to “the law of nature” and, more prominently, natural virtue. These appeals help to explain the nature and character of the citizens of the social contract rather than the origin of right or law. These latter emerge from the social contract, or, more specifically, from the workings of the general will.

  6. 6.

    Nancy Hirschmann discusses the effects of poverty in the form of the exclusion of the lower classes (and women) from civil and political freedom (Hirschmann 2007, 124–127). Cohen, too, presents the problem of inequality for political freedom in his discussion of what he calls “the fundamental problem” (Cohen 2010, 24–32).

  7. 7.

    Cohen also provocatively mentions that Rawls “once said in passing that his two principles of justice could be understood as an effort to spell out the content of the general will” (Cohen 2010, 2).

  8. 8.

    It might also be worth noting that Rousseau is revealing some of his affinity for Hobbes here. Hobbes metaphorically links money to the blood of the body politic in Chapter 24 of the Leviathan. Rousseau, according to Richard Tuck, was aware of his similarity to Hobbes (Tuck 1996, xxxvi).

  9. 9.

    Both Hirschmann (2007) and Cohen (2010) make similar arguments. Hirshmann focuses on freedom and Cohen focuses on common good and the general will.

References

  • Akoma, Chiji, and Sally Scholz. 2009. Virtuous Bacchanalia: Creolizing Rousseau’s festival. C.L.R. James Journal 15(1): 206–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cladis, Mark. 2003. Public vision, private lives: Rousseau, religion, and 21st century democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua. 2010. Rousseau: A free community of equals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cranston, Maurice. 1982. Jean-Jacques: The early life and work of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 1712–1754. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellison, Charles. 1991. The moral economy of the modern city: Reading Rousseau’s Discourse on Wealth. History of Political Thought 12(2): 253–261.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschmann, Nancy. 2007. Gender, class, and freedom in modern political theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1988. Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noland, Aaron. 1967. Proudhon and Rousseau. Journal of the History of Ideas 28(1): 33–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, Jeff. 2006. Democratic society and human needs. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1960. Letter to M. D’Alembert. In Politics and the Arts. Trans Allan Bloom. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1967 (Cited in text as Second Discourse). In The social contract and discourse on the origin of inequality, ed. Crocker Lester. New York: Washington Square Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. [1762] 1993. Émile. Trans. Barbara Foxley. London: J. M. Dent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1997a (Cited in text as Government of Poland). Considerations on the government of Poland and on its projected reformation. In The social contract and other later political writings, ed. Gourevitch Victor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1997b (Cited in text as Political Economy). Political economy. In The social contract and other later political writings, ed. Gourevitch Victor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1997c (Cited in text as Social Contract). Social contract. In The social contract and other later political writings, ed. Gourevitch Victor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1997d. Discourse on the sciences and arts. In The discourses and other early political writings, ed. Gourevitch Victor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques.2005a. On wealth. In Collected writings, vol. 11. pp. 6–17. Ed. Christopher Kelly; Trans Christopher Kelly and Judith Bush. Hanover, New Hampshire: Dartmouth College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 2005b. The State of War. In Collected writings vol. 11. pp. 60–63. Ed. Christopher Kelly; Trans. Christopher Kelly and Judith Bush. Hanover, New Hampshire: Dartmouth College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 2005c. Universal chronology or general history of times from the creation of the world up to the present. In Collected writings, vol. 11. pp. 1–5. Ed. Christopher Kelly; Trans Christopher Kelly and Judith Bush. Hanover, New Hampshire: Dartmouth College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scholz, Sally. 2001. On Rousseau. Belmont: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuck, Richard. 1996. Introduction. Leviathan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaughan, Sharon. 2008. Poverty, justice, and western political thought. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Scholz, S.J. (2013). Rousseau on Poverty. In: Stacy, H., Lee, WC. (eds) Economic Justice. AMINTAPHIL: The Philosophical Foundations of Law and Justice, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4905-4_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics