Skip to main content

Moral Intuition in Philosophy and Psychology

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbook of Neuroethics

Abstract

Ethicists often appeal to moral intuitions in defending a theory. In this practice, the contents of intuitions are taken to support moral beliefs in a way that is often compared to the way the contents of perception support empirical beliefs. Philosophers have defended a variety of positions about the nature of such states. Intuitionists believe intuitions are either self-evident beliefs or intellectual appearances, while Coherentists think of them as considered judgments that need to be balanced against each other in a process of reflective equilibrium. Intuition skeptics reject either kind of justificatory role. Such skepticism has recently received support from psychological studies of moral intuition. In contrast to philosophers, psychologists typically think of intuitions as snap judgments that result from automatic, nonconscious, and often affective processing. Some argue that they are likely to be responsive to morally irrelevant factors. Yet even if this is true of snap judgments, it is not clear what follows for the epistemic standing of the kind of states that philosophers talk about. The aim of this chapter is to clarify the various philosophical and psychological conceptions of moral intuition in order to bring them in closer contact and help researchers in different disciplines to avoid talking past each other. In the final section, a sentimentalist account of moral intuition that may offer some hope of reconciling the philosophical and psychological approaches is quickly sketched.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 999.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 999.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Sometimes the term “intuition” is also used for the proposition that is the content of the psychological state. I will leave aside this use here. The adverb “intuitively” and the adjective “intuitive” are used much more broadly and shouldn’t be taken to entail that anyone has an intuition (pace Cappelen 2012).

References

  • Allman, J., & Woodward, J. (2008). What are moral intuitions and why should we care about them? A neurobiological perspective. Philosophical Issues, 18, 164–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (2004). The good in the right. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bealer, G. (2000). A theory of the a priori. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 81, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedke, M. (2009). Intuitive non-naturalism meets cosmic coincidence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 90, 188–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2010). The intellectual given. Dissertation, University of Texas at Austin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2013). Experimental attacks on intuitions and answers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86(3), 495–532

    Google Scholar 

  • Berker, S. (2009). The normative insignificance of neuroscience. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 37(4), 293–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. (2012). Philosophy without intuitions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chudnoff, E. (2011). What intuitions are like. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82(3), 625–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (1979). Wide reflective equilibrium and theory acceptance in ethics. Journal of Philosophy, 76(5), 256–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, S. (1999). Moral competence. In K. Murasugi & R. Stainton (Eds.), Philosophy and linguistics (pp. 169–190). Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2008). The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology (Vol. 3, pp. 35–80). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Cushman, F. A., Stewart, L. E., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2009). Pushing moral buttons: The interaction between personal force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition, 111(3), 364–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M. (2006). Moral minds. New York: Harper Collins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2005). Ethical intuitionism. New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins, C. (2008). Grounding concepts: An empirical basis for arithmetical knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Klein, G. (2009). Conditions for intuitive expertise: A failure to disagree. American Psychologist, 64(6), 515–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2011). Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs, 45(1), 103–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2013). The armchair and the trolley. Philosophical Studies, 162(2), 421–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2013). Ethics and empirical psychology. In M. Christen, J. Fischer, M. Huppenbauer, C. Tanner & C. van Schaik (eds.) Empirically informed ethics. New york:Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (forthcoming). Intuition and belief in moral motivation. In Gunnar Björnsson et al. (eds.) Motivational internalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, G. (1998). Sources of power. How people make decisions. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2011). The dual track theory of moral decision-making: A critique of the neuroimaging evidence. Neuroethics, 4, 143–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mikhail, J. (2011). Elements of moral cognition: Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive science of moral and legal judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prichard, H. A. (2002). Moral writings. Ed. Jim MacAdam. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2007). The emotional construction of morals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1974). The independence of moral theory. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48, 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Roojen, M. (forthcoming), Moral intuitionism, experiments, and skeptical arguments. In A. Booth and D. Rowbottom (eds.) Intuitions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1930/2002). The right and the good. Ed. Philip Stratton-Lake. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A defence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. (1907). Methods of ethics (7th ed.). London: MacMillan & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2005). Ethics and intuitions. The Journal of Ethics, 9, 331–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2006). Moral intuitionism meets empirical psychology. In T. Horgan & M. Timmons (Eds.), Metaethics after Moore. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology I: Apt belief and reflective knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Valdesolo, P., & DeSteno, D. (2006). Manipulations of emotional context shape moral judgment. Psychological Science, 17(6), 476–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. D. (2002). Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (2011). Humanity as an end in itself. In D. Parfit (Ed.), On what matters (Vol. 2, pp. 58–82). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antti Kauppinen .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this entry

Cite this entry

Kauppinen, A. (2015). Moral Intuition in Philosophy and Psychology. In: Clausen, J., Levy, N. (eds) Handbook of Neuroethics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4707-4_163

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4707-4_163

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-4706-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-4707-4

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics