Skip to main content

The Pragma-Dialectical Theory of Argumentation

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbook of Argumentation Theory

Abstract

This chapter discusses the pragma-dialectical approach developed in the Netherlands by van Eemeren and Grootendorst between the 1970s and the late 1990s and extended by van Eemeren and Houtlosser at the end of the twentieth and the beginning of the twenty-first century. After a short expose about the origins and development of the theory in Sect. 10.1and a sketch of the normative pragmatic research carried out in pragma-dialectics in Sect. 10.2, in Sect. 10.3 the meta-theoretical starting points are discussed.

In Sect. 10.4 the model for critical discussion is introduced and explained, followed in Sect. 10.5 by a discussion of analysis as reconstruction of argumentative discourse in terms of a critical discussion. In Sect. 10.6 the rules for critical discussion associated with the model are introduced, and in Sect. 10.7 the fallacies that may occur in argumentative discourse are characterized as violations of these rules.

The extension of the standard pragma-dialectical theory with the inclusion of strategic maneuvering is introduced in Sect. 10.8. Sect. 10.9 deals with the conventionalization of argumentative discourse in communicative activity types that needs to be taken into account when analyzing and evaluating specimens of strategic maneuvering. In Sect. 10.10 the fallacies are revisited by characterizing them as derailments of strategic maneuvering in which in aiming for effectiveness one or more of the rules for critical discussion have been violated.

The next two sections are devoted to pragma-dialectical empirical research of argumentative reality. Sect. 10.11 reports about qualitative research, such as the research concerning indicators of argumentative moves in discourse by van Eemeren, Houtlosser, and Snoeck Henkemans and the research of dissociation by van Rees. Sect. 10.12 reports about quantitative research, such as, to mention the most prominent study, van Eemeren, Garssen, and Meuffels’s experimental research concerning the conventional validity of the pragma-dialectical discussion rules. In Sect. 10.13 various kinds of applications of pragma-dialectical insights to the analysis and evaluation of strategic maneuvering in specific communicative domains are discussed, such as those of Feteris to the legal domain and those of other pragma-dialecticians to the political, the medical, and the academic domain.

To conclude, Sect. 10.14 reports about various kinds of critical responses to the pragma-dialectical theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 549.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 799.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Some of the monographs mentioned were translated (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1984, into Russian (1994c) and Spanish (2013); van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1992a, into Bulgarian (2009b), Chinese (1991b), French (1996), Romanian (2010), Russian (1992b), and Spanish (2007); van Eemeren and Grootendorst 2004, into Bulgarian (2006), Chinese (2002), Italian (2008), and Spanish (2011); van Eemeren 2010, into Italian (2014) and Spanish (2013b) [Chinese and Japanese translations are in preparation]).

  2. 2.

    Since 2010 they are all part of the International Learned Institute for Argumentation Studies (ILIAS).

  3. 3.

    In hindsight, a potentially constructive move may not be constructive because it is fallacious. See Sect. 10.7.

  4. 4.

    van Eemeren et al. (2002a) is translated into Albanian (2006a), Armenian (2004), Chinese (2006b), Italian (2011a), Russian (2002b), and Spanish (2006c) [Japanese and Portuguese translations are in preparation].

  5. 5.

    For a more detailed exposition of the meta-theoretical starting points, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984).

  6. 6.

    For a well-articulated example of a structure-oriented logical approach to argumentation, see Fisher (2004).

  7. 7.

    The term disagreement space is introduced in Jackson (1992, p. 261).

  8. 8.

    For the distinction between identity conditions and correctness conditions, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1992a, pp. 30–31).

  9. 9.

    For a definition of the complex speech act of argumentation and its relationship with the speech act of advancing a standpoint, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984, pp. 39–46; 1992a, pp. 30–33) and for an analogous definition of the speech act of advancing a standpoint Houtlosser (1995).

  10. 10.

    For an articulated example of a product-oriented nonsocialized approach to argumentation, see Johnson (1995, 2003, especially p. 48).

  11. 11.

    For an articulated example of a non-externalized and psychologizing approach to argumentation, see Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca (1969).

  12. 12.

    This response can be viewed as the intended “perlocutionary” effect of argumentation. For a discussion of the relation between the illocutionary act complex of “argumentation” and the perlocutionary act of “convincing,” see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984, pp. 47–74), Jacobs (1987, pp. 231–233), and van Eemeren (2010, pp. 36–39).

  13. 13.

    See for an articulated example of a descriptive, “emic” approach Doury (2004, 2006). The pragma-dialectical take on Pike’s (1967) distinction between an “internal” emic approach to discourse, which is participant-centered, and an “external” etic approach, which is theory-driven, is discussed in van Eemeren (2010, pp. 137–138).

  14. 14.

    For the notions of objective (or problem-solving) validity and intersubjective (or conventional) validity, which are based on insights developed by Crawshay-Williams (1957), see Barth and Krabbe (1982, pp. 21–22). See also Sects. 3.7 and 3.9 of this volume.

  15. 15.

    A critical discussion reflects a critical rationalist interpretation of the dialectic ideal of testing rationally any form of conviction – not only descriptive statements of a factual kind but also value judgments and practical standpoints about action (Albert 1975). Starting from the idea that in principle all human standpoints are open to criticism, in the pragma-dialectical approach, the guiding principle in testing the acceptability of standpoints is that they are to be subjected to a critical discussion.

  16. 16.

    In line with the critical rationalist perspective, testing standpoints by means of a critical discussion involves in the first place trying to detect inconsistencies between these standpoints and the arguer’s other commitments (Albert 1975, p. 44).

  17. 17.

    Even in settling disputes and disagreements, it can be useful to conduct a critical discussion to find out to what extent a joint resolution is possible.

  18. 18.

    In spite of their different philosophical roots, the model of a critical discussion represents like Habermas’s (1971, 1981) “ideal speech situation ,” an idealized state of affairs which differs from existing reality. However, instead of being instruments in achieving the Habermasian ideal of consensus, intellectual doubt and criticism are in pragma-dialectics viewed as the driving forces of intellectual and cultural progress, fostering a continual flux of ever more advanced opinions. Achieving consensus is in this process in each particular case just one of the necessary intermediate steps on the way to the next difference.

  19. 19.

    A difference of opinion emerges when one’s standpoint is not shared by the other. This does not necessarily mean that the other takes an opposite standpoint, as is the case in a “mixed” difference of opinion. It can also be that the other merely has doubt concerning the acceptability of one’s standpoint. A presumption of doubt is already enough reason for advancing argumentation. See van Eemeren et al. (2002a, Chap. 1).

  20. 20.

    If there are more standpoints at issue, a participant in the discussion can take on the role of protagonist for some standpoints and the role of antagonist for other standpoints, so that the various standpoints may have different protagonists. Having the role of antagonist may (but need not) coincide with taking on the role of protagonist of another – contrary – standpoint. See for these distinctions van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a, pp. 13–25).

  21. 21.

    For an argumentative exchange in which this precondition has clearly not been fulfilled, see van Eemeren et al. (1993, pp. 142–169).

  22. 22.

    The different types of complex argumentation that can come into being vary from multiple argumentation to argumentation that is coordinatively compound or subordinatively compound and combinations of them. See for the different kinds of argumentation structure van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a, pp. 73–89) and Snoeck Henkemans (1992).

  23. 23.

    In spite of the use of the expression “I promise,” in this case the speech act performed amounts to a threat rather than a promise.

  24. 24.

    Like other indirect speech acts, expressives sometimes need to be reconstructed as standpoints or arguments. Even if they are just expressives they may be of influence by distracting attention from the discussion, as when a participant sighs to make clear that the discussion depresses her.

  25. 25.

    The subcategory of the usage declaratives is introduced in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984, pp. 109–110).

  26. 26.

    Viskil (1994, in Dutch) develops theoretical guidelines for the pragma-dialectical framing of definitions.

  27. 27.

    Due to their dependence on the authority of the speaker or writer in a certain institutional context, declaratives can sometimes lead to a settlement (but not a resolution) of a dispute, as when a judge pronounces a verdict.

  28. 28.

    See for of an explanation of these reasons van Eemeren (2010, p. 13).

  29. 29.

    From the observations that often the parties fail to identify what exactly their difference of opinion involves, that it is not always immediately clear who is to be convinced of the acceptability of the standpoints at issue, that the division of the discussion roles and the procedural and material starting points are as a rule only mentioned when they are not regarded as understood, that argumentation remains standardly partly unexpressed and criticisms implicit, and that conclusions are often just suggested, it can be concluded neither that the discourse is deficient nor that the model of critical discussion is not realistic. The former is contradicted by pragmatic insight concerning the conduct of ordinary discourse and the latter by dialectical insight concerning the process of resolving a difference of opinion on the merits (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1984, Chap. 4; 1992a, Chap. 5; van Eemeren et al. 1993, Chap. 3).

  30. 30.

    An argumentative discourse in which a standpoint is defended by means of a monologue is in pragma-dialectics viewed as an implicit discussion in which only one of the parties participates explicitly. Because such a discourse is also aimed at convincing potential critics, even though they may not be actually present, their views need to be taken into account, however implicit these views may be. Just like in explicit discussions, parties putting forward their case cannot just present their argumentation but need to cover in some way or the other the other discussion stages as well. A practical complication of analyzing implicit discussions is that the discussion stages are usually harder to identify.

  31. 31.

    The first question in reconstructing an oral or written discourse always is whether the discourse is indeed wholly or partly argumentative. Although in some cases the discourse is evidently not argumentative, more often than not a discourse that is not presented as argumentative all the same has an argumentative function. The demarcation criterion is whether the discourse is, directly or indirectly, aimed at overcoming the addressee’s doubts regarding the acceptability of a standpoint.

  32. 32.

    As explained in van Eemeren (2010, pp. 16–19), the analytic overview resulting from the analysis needs to satisfy requirements of economy, efficacy, coherence, realism, and well-foundedness.

  33. 33.

    The transformations are aimed at reconstructing the way in which the various parts of the discourse contribute to resolving a difference of opinion on the merits, which does not necessarily always correspond with the way in which they are viewed by the participants.

  34. 34.

    For a more elaborate account of the transformations executed in a pragma-dialectical reconstruction of argumentative discourse, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1990); van Eemeren et al. (1993, pp. 61–86); and van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, pp. 100–110).

  35. 35.

    All crucial concepts mentioned in Sect. 1.3 are represented in the analytic overview, except for the concept of fallacies, which plays a part in the evaluation of argumentative discourse. See Sect. 10.7.

  36. 36.

    Starting from an analytic overview (or a writing plan similar to an analytic overview), in pragma-dialectics also a method has been developed for writing and rewriting argumentative texts in such a way that their comprehensibility and acceptability are not diminished by redundancy, implicitness, disarrangement, or lack of clarity (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1999). In this method, four presentational transformation s are applied to the analytic overview (or writing plan) that roughly “mirror” the reconstruction transformations: presentational deletion (what can be left out?), presentational addition (what should be added?), presentational permutation (which rearrangements are to be made?), and presentational substitution (which rephrasings are necessary?).

  37. 37.

    For an explanation of these terms and concepts, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a) and van Eemeren et al. (2002a), a textbook based on to the pragma-dialectical method of analyzing, evaluating, and producing argumentative discourse.

  38. 38.

    For the pragma-dialectical reconstruction of unexpressed premises, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a, pp. 60–72). See also Gerlofs (2009).

  39. 39.

    For a more elaborate discussion of the pragma-dialectical argumentation structures, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a, pp. 73–89) and Snoeck Henkemans (1992).

  40. 40.

    For a more elaborate discussion of the pragma-dialectical argument schemes, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a, pp. 94–102). See also Garssen (1997, in Dutch).

  41. 41.

    A full explanation of the pragma-dialectical rules for critical discussion can be found in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, pp. 123–157).

  42. 42.

    This procedure, and other procedures mentioned in the rules, will be explained below.

  43. 43.

    The formulation of the code of conduct used in this section is based on its latest version in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, pp. 190–196).

  44. 44.

    It is worth noting that observance of these commandments can only be imposed on discussants as a requirement of reasonable acting if the higher-order conditions for conducting a critical discussion have been fulfilled, so that critical reasonableness can be fully realized. If the rules for critical discussion are viewed as the (first order) “rules of the game,” the higher-order conditions represent the various kinds of psychological, sociopolitical, and other preconditions stating the dispositions and attitudes of the discussants and the circumstances of the discussion that are required. The “internal” conditions relating to the state of mind of the discussants are called second-order condition s and the “external” conditions relating to the discussion situation third-order condition s. For the distinction between these higher-order conditions, see van Eemeren et al. (1993, pp. 30–35) and van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, pp. 36–37).

  45. 45.

    Advancing argumentation, i.e., the use of logos, may be combined with the use of ethos or pathos but should not be replaced by it. For the role of “ethical” (also called “ethotic”) and “pathetical” means of persuasion in classical rhetoric, in particular in Aristotle’s rhetoric, see Sect. 2.8, subsection The modes of persuasion, of this volume, and Kennedy (1994).

  46. 46.

    When exactly a piece of reasoning is to be considered invalid in a logical sense is dependent on the logical theory that is used as the standard of validity. This standard needs to be agreed upon (explicitly or implicitly) in the opening stage (van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1984, p. 163; 2004, p. 148).

  47. 47.

    We prefer this phrasing to the one used in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004), “reasoning that […] is presented as formally conclusive” (p. 193), because it is easier to understand.

  48. 48.

    This phrasing is clearer than the more complicated one in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, p. 194).

  49. 49.

    Cf. the stricter and more negative views of DeMorgan (1847) and Massey (1975).

  50. 50.

    For the notions of problem-solving validity (or problem-validity, or objective validity) and (semi)conventional validity (or intersubjective validity), see Sect. 3.9 of this volume. For a demonstration of the problem-solving validity of the rules for critical discussion, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1994a). To actually serve as tools for resolving differences of opinion on the merits in argumentative reality, next to being problem-solving valid, the rules for critical discussion also need to be intersubjectively accepted as standards by those involved in the evaluation process, so that they are conventionally valid. See Sect. 10.12.

  51. 51.

    In pragma-dialectics, the identification of fallacies is always conditional: an argumentative move may be regarded a fallacy only if the discourse in which it occurs may be viewed as aimed at resolving a difference of opinion. A discourse can only be fully and methodically screened for fallacies if it is first determined to what extent it can be reconstructed in terms of a critical discussion and has been adequately analyzed.

  52. 52.

    For the relationship between relative and structure-dependent properties and the fallacies of composition and division see van Eemeren and Garssen (2009).

  53. 53.

    For the notion of a zero standpoint, involving only doubt on the part of the antagonist and not a counterstandpoint, see van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984, pp. 78–81, 1992a, pp. 13–25).

  54. 54.

    When it comes to the detection of fallacies in argumentative discourse, a distinction needs to be made between the standards defining the various types of fallacies and the criteria that are to be applied in deciding whether a particular speech act conveying a certain argumentative move does or does not violate a certain standard and is therefore to be labelled as a particular type of fallacy. In detecting fallacies, pragmatic insights regarding implicitness and indirectness as well as contextual and background information are to be taken into account.

  55. 55.

    The inclusion of an account of strategic considerations in the theorizing should also be instrumental in developing more sophisticated methods for improving the quality of oral and written argumentative discourse.

  56. 56.

    The study of aiming for effectiveness in argumentative discourse is generally seen as part of the core business of rhetoric (Wenzel 1990; Hample 2007; van Eemeren 2010, pp. 66–80). In particular since the development of “Big Rhetoric,” however, the scope of rhetoric is restricted neither to effectiveness nor to argumentative discourse. See Foss et al. (1985), Lunsford et al. (2009), and Swearingen and Schiappa (2009).

  57. 57.

    See Wagemans (2009), who situates the pragma-dialectical proposal to combine the dialectical and the rhetorical perspectives against the background of antique dialectic and rhetoric.

  58. 58.

    The rapprochement between dialectical and rhetorical approaches to argumentation is also stimulated by argumentation scholars such as Wenzel (1990) and Tindale (2004).

  59. 59.

    The term strategic maneuver refers both to the process of making choices regarding the three aspects and to the product resulting from making these choices.

  60. 60.

    However, for an argumentative move to be characterized as a particular strategic maneuver, the way in which the two other constitutive aspects of strategic maneuvering manifest themselves in the move should not contradict this characterization.

  61. 61.

    For the notion of disagreement space and the notion of virtual standpoints, which is connected with it, see van Eemeren et al. (1993, pp. 95–96).

  62. 62.

    In the pragma-dialectical view, the “stock issues” pertinent to the kinds of attacks and defenses that can be developed depend, among other things, on the type of standpoint at issue.

  63. 63.

    For some examples of the various strategies, see van Eemeren (2010, pp. 46–47).

  64. 64.

    By suggesting that this is the end of the discussion, the father does not really give the boy a chance to draw his own conclusion, but forces him by means of emotional pressure more or less to accept his standpoint. In spite of what is implied by the use of “well then,” however, in agreeing that he loves his father, the son commits himself in no way to accepting the unexpressed premise that someone who loves someone else should never do something that the loved one does not like. Suggesting all the same, as the father does, that such a commitment exists is in pragma-dialectics viewed as fallacious. However, because the father pressures his son so strongly, a preliminary higher-order condition for conducting a critical discussion may be unfulfilled so that a fallacy judgment does not apply.

  65. 65.

    Pragma-dialecticians use the terms institutional and institutionalized in a broad sense, pertaining to all socially and culturally established communicative practices that are formally or informally conventionalized (see also Hall and Taylor 1996). Like Searle (1995), they see institutions as dealing with rights and duties by means of socially constructed rules and sanctions associated with these rules.

  66. 66.

    For a related meaning of the term activity type see Levinson (1992, p. 69).

  67. 67.

    Fairclough characterizes a “genre” of communicative activity broadly as “a socially ratified way of using language in connection with a particular type of social activity” (1995, p. 14). The term action schemes, defined by Rigotti and Rocci (2006, p. 173) as “culturally shaped ‘recipes’ for interaction congruent with more or less broad classes of joint goals and involving scheme-roles presupposing generic requirements,” has a similar meaning, but is used to refer both to genres of communicative activity and communicative activity types. According to Greco Morasso, an activity type corresponds with “an interaction scheme applied to a precise interaction field” (2009, note 169).

  68. 68.

    Certain communicative activity types are hybrids in the sense that they involve the activation of a combination of several genres of conventionalized communicative activity. Political interviews, for example, are communicative activity types in which the genres of deliberation and dissemination of information are prototypically combined.

  69. 69.

    The term deliberation is here used in the broad meaning given to this concept by Habermas (1994, p. 8; 1996, pp. 307–308) and other protagonists of “deliberative democracy.” In their view, intended to replace the traditional view of political deliberation as an activity conducted only in formal institutions such as parliaments, informal and less regulated communication among citizens are equally important to rational democratic politics.

  70. 70.

    The institutional point of the “interpersonal” communicative activity types generally is to keep the relationship going. However noncommittal some of these communicative activity types may seem, some implicit conventions always need to be observed, even if no well-defined institutional goals are pursued.

  71. 71.

    Unlike Hymes (1972), who uses the term speech event for communicative activity types as well as their actual manifestations, we restrict our use of this term to the latter.

  72. 72.

    See, for instance, Hietanen’s (2005) analysis of Paul’s argumentation in Galatians 3.1–3.5, in which pragma-dialectics is used in New Testament exegesis.

  73. 73.

    As van Eemeren et al. (2010) explain, the pragma-dialectical communicative activity types share some common ground with Walton and Krabbe’s (1995) “dialogue type s.” However, with dialogue types, it is not clear whether they are distinguished on the basis of analytic considerations or on the basis of empirical observation, so that it is not certain whether their status is normative or descriptive. Walton (1998, p. 30) maintains that each dialogue type constitutes a separate normative model of argumentation, but in describing the dialogue types, he refers continually to empirical observations. Because of their institutional and empirical orientation, Jacobs and Aakhus (2002), Aakhus (2003), and Jackson and Jacobs (2006), who view the conditions a specific context imposes on argumentative discourse in terms of “design,” come closer to the pragma-dialectical approach.

  74. 74.

    Using a critical discussion as the general point of reference in the argumentative characterization of all communicative activity types leads to consistent and coherent characterizations and creates possibilities for a unified comparison between communicative activity types.

  75. 75.

    In some communicative activity types the participants have different missions, depending on their role in the activity type. In Prime Minister’s Question Time, for instance, the parliamentarians’ mission is to hold the government to account for its policies and actions, whereas the Prime Minister’s mission is to justify them.

  76. 76.

    Besides official, usually formal, and often procedural primary preconditions, pragma-dialectics distinguishes secondary preconditions, which are unofficial, usually informal, and often substantial. In the communicative activity type of a general debate in the European parliament, for instance, the rules of order guarded by the Chair are primary preconditions while the “European predicament” that the parliamentarians need to combine serving the interests of Europe and those of their home countries is a secondary precondition (see Sect. 10.13).

  77. 77.

    Van Eemeren mentions in this connection the structuring of the discourse in accordance with what is considered topical or relevant at a particular point, the underexposure of what is considered evident or known, the overexposure of what is considered important or significant, and the lack of precision and elaboration that is deemed unnecessary (2010, p. 197).

  78. 78.

    Arguers may sometimes also neglect their interest in effectiveness – say for fear of being perceived as unreasonable. This can result in rhetorically bad strategic maneuvering, but not in a fallacy.

  79. 79.

    For the presumption of reasonableness, see Jackson (1995).

  80. 80.

    Referring to Woods and Walton (1989, pp. 15–24) and van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1992a, pp. 136–137), van Eemeren (2010) cites, for example, the following general criteria for judging authority arguments: the authority referred to should have indeed the professed authority, the authority’s judgment should be recognized as pertinent to the topic at issue in the difference of opinion, the parties in the difference of opinion should in principle agree on appealing to the authority in the discussion, and the authority should by quoted correctly and at a point where this is relevant (pp. 202–203).

  81. 81.

    In some cases it might be necessary to supplement the general criteria with specific criteria that are only relevant in a particular institutional macro-context.

  82. 82.

    Note that an argumentative move that is relevant in any of these three senses is not necessarily a successful move in the sense of being effective.

  83. 83.

    Cf. Pinto and Blair’s (1989) distinction between cumulative and complementary “premise sets.”

  84. 84.

    The dialectical profiles are inspired by the profiles of dialogue developed by Walton and Krabbe (Walton 1999, p. 53; Krabbe 2002). Cf. van Eemeren et al. (2010).

  85. 85.

    Dialectical profiles can also have a heuristic role in the analysis of strategic maneuvering. Because every dialectical move specified in a dialectical profile allows for rhetorical exploitation, the dialectical profile is an appropriate starting point for identifying the ways of strategic maneuvering the arguers can deploy to steer the critical resolution process into their own direction.

  86. 86.

    It is primarily for efficiency reasons that the profile allows the dialogue about the acceptance of Y to be part of the dialogue about the acceptance of X. This inclusion allows for cases in which the acceptance of Y by T1 has consequences for the argumentative value of X, that is to say, imposes restrictions on the argumentative use that T1 can make of Y in support of his standpoint. If it could not become clear as early as in the opening stage of the discussion that the acceptance of Y had these consequences, it could happen that T1 and T2 run through the whole discussion about the acceptability of T1’s standpoint and agree in the concluding stage that T1 is allowed to maintain his standpoint on the basis of the support he has provided with the use of X, while it would have been clear all the time that if T2 could have proposed Y as a starting point and T1 had accepted Y as such, T1’s support for his standpoint would have been overruled by an attack by T2 on the basis of Y, and T1 would therefore not be allowed to maintain his standpoint.

  87. 87.

    In addition, Verbiest (1987) describes from the same theoretical point of view how disputes arise in informal conversations. She shows that there is an important parallel between confrontation in conversations and the normative pragma-dialectical view of confrontation.

  88. 88.

    Van Rees (1991) examines whether descriptive models for problem-solving discussions can be used to investigate the extent to which such discussions conform to the normative ideal.

  89. 89.

    Earlier Slot (1993) discussed the problem of recognizing and interpreting rhetorical questions from a pragma-dialectical perspective.

  90. 90.

    From the same theoretical perspective, Tseronis (2009) investigated in Qualifying Standpoints the strategic function of “stance adverbs” in qualifying standpoints as a presentational device in strategic maneuvering.

  91. 91.

    Other pragma-dialectical case studies include the analysis of some of J. R. Reynolds’s tobacco advertorials by van Eemeren and Houtlosser (2000a; van Eemeren 2010, pp. 20–21, 47–50); van Eemeren et al. (2011b); and the doctoral dissertations on the strategic use of dissociation and definitions defended at the University of Bucharest by Cosoreci Mazilu (2010), concentrating on the abortion debate, and Muraru (2010), concentrating on mediation and diplomatic discourse regarding the Camp David agreements. For a detailed illustration of the advantages of an “extended” analysis of a press release by KLM compared to a “standard” analysis, see van Eemeren et al. (2012c).

  92. 92.

    Experimental pragma-dialectical empirical research concerning the production of argumentative moves (and texts) is still thin on the ground since it follows the development of the interpretation and evaluation research. See van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1999) for the pragma-dialectical (re)writing method.

  93. 93.

    Most reports about this research were published in Dutch (e.g., van Eemeren et al. 1984, 1985, 1987, 1990). For publications in English, see van Eemeren et al. (1989) and van Eemeren et al. (2000).

  94. 94.

    Van Eemeren et al. (1984) conducted first several feasibility studies to ensure that the respondents in the experiment understand “argumentation” in the intended way. In testing the suitability of their measuring instruments, they concentrated on “single” argumentation, in which just one reason in defense of a standpoint is articulated. The conceptual validity of their argumentation concept was proven by the fact that the items submitted to the respondents were in 95 % of the cases correctly identified as argumentation.

  95. 95.

    For experimental research concerning the role of standpoints preceding the argumentation in identifying argumentation, see Jungslager (1991).

  96. 96.

    Students follow in Dutch secondary school education different programs (from vocational to academic) according to their general cognitive skills and achievements.

  97. 97.

    This result seems to confirm van Dijk and Kintsch’s (1983) contention that in determining the communicative function (“force”) of verbal utterances, language users take refuge in “linguistic strategies.” All nonlinguistic factors Clark (1979) mentions as affecting the interpretation of indirect speech acts are incorporated in a well-defined context.

  98. 98.

    For experimental research concerning the identification of “nonmixed” and “mixed” differences of opinion, see Koetsenruijter (1993).

  99. 99.

    Experimental research carried out by Gerritsen (1999) indicates that clarified versions of argumentation with an unexpressed premise were better appreciated by the respondents only if the original versions were for them indeed difficult to understand.

  100. 100.

    See for the measurement of argumentative skills also Oostdam (1991).

  101. 101.

    This research is reported in English in Garssen (2002).

  102. 102.

    This means, for example, that next to cases of abusive argumentum ad hominem the test included also sound personal attacks and that other fallacies were in a similar way “accompanied” by representations of their sound counterparts.

  103. 103.

    In a number of cases, a replication study was carried out – sometimes to support interpretations, sometimes to exclude alternative explanations, and, in doing so guaranteeing the internal validity, sometimes to optimize the external validity.

  104. 104.

    The only exceptional case is the tu quoque variant of the argumentum ad hominem.

  105. 105.

    Going by the absolute size of the empirical averages obtained, there is a considerable variation as to the extent to which the fallacies studied are found unreasonable. A practical didactic implication is that, since it is now clear which are obviously the least complicated cases, these cases should in an introductory course on fallacies be dealt with first and the more complicated cases later.

  106. 106.

    According to van Eemeren (2010), the intersubjective validity of the rules for critical discussion, which is to lend the pragma-dialectical discussion procedure conventional validity, is likely to be based primarily on their problem-solving validity, i.e., their instrumentality in resolving a difference of opinion on the merits. One may surmise that the rules will be acceptable to people who are like members of Popper’s Open Society in the sense that they are antidogmatic, antiauthoritarian, and anti-foundationalist and reject monopolies of knowledge, pretensions of infallibility, and appeals to unfaltering principles.

  107. 107.

    It is worth noting that in the study the confrontation stage and the opening stage have been studied exhaustively in this regard.

  108. 108.

    The three hypotheses are closely connected with the theoretical views on the relationship between argumentation and effectiveness in the sense of convincingness that were expounded in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984).

  109. 109.

    This type of effectiveness research is a critically inspired pragma-dialectical complement to the prevailing (non-dialectical) persuasion research. The pragma-dialectical preference for the label “effectiveness research” rather than “persuasiveness research ” is in the first place motivated by the fact that the term effectiveness is, unlike the term persuasiveness, not exclusively connected with the argumentation stage but pertains also to argumentative moves made in other discussion stages, such as proposing starting points in the opening stage and stating the outcome of the discussion in the concluding stage.

  110. 110.

    See the analysis of “interactional” (perlocutionary) effects in van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984, pp. 63–74) and van Eemeren (2010, pp. 36–39).

  111. 111.

    In line with this research tradition, Amjarso (2010) tackled the question of whether in the context of a monologue simply mentioning arguments in support of a standpoint is more effective than also mentioning and refuting anticipated counterarguments.

  112. 112.

    Both in the original test and in the replication carried out to be better able to generalize the results, straightforward abusive attacks are consistently rejected as unreasonable discussion moves, and legitimate personal attacks are invariably considered reasonable. The “disguised” abusive attacks presented as responses to an abuse of authority however are judged as substantially less unreasonable than the overtly fallacious direct attacks.

  113. 113.

    In addition, a fruitful collaboration was realized with researchers of the University of Lugano who concentrate on argumentation in mediation, editorial meetings, financial communication, and health communication.

  114. 114.

    See Plug (1999, 2000a, 2002) for a discussion in English of some of the problems involved.

  115. 115.

    For a discussion in English of the use of a contrario reasoning in legal argumentation, see Jansen (2005).

  116. 116.

    Other pragma-dialectical research projects focus, for instance, on the peculiarities of argumentative discourse in Dutch Parliament (Plug 2010, 2011) and the use of pragmatic argumentation in lawmaking debates in British Parliament (Ihnen Jory 2010; 2012). See also Ieţcu-Fairclough (2009).

  117. 117.

    A revised version of Andone’s dissertation was published as a monograph (Andone 2013).

  118. 118.

    These patterns involve rephrasing the original standpoint in a way that (1) makes the politician’s support of the position at issue dependent on the fulfillment of certain specific conditions, (2) makes clear that the interviewer’s interpretation that there is an inconsistency is based on a misunderstanding, and (3) enables the politician to claim that the original standpoint concerned something else than the present standpoint (Andone 2010, pp. 88–89).

  119. 119.

    See Labrie (2012).

  120. 120.

    Both Pilgram at the University of Amsterdam and Labrie at the University of Lugano are engaged in doctoral research from a pragma-dialectical perspective concerning the use of authority in doctor-patient consultation.

  121. 121.

    In her doctoral research at the University of Amsterdam, Wierda focuses on the use of authority argumentation in medical advertising.

  122. 122.

    The use of pragmatic argumentation in health brochures was also the topic of van Poppel’s (2013) doctoral research at the University of Amsterdam.

  123. 123.

    Aimed at contributing to this project is Popa’s doctoral research concerning “thought experiments” at the University of Amsterdam.

  124. 124.

    Dissociating “a pragma-dialectical approach” to argumentation from “pragma-dialectics” as the theoretical enterprise of those who have coined the term is in our view just as awkward as it would be to dissociate “a new rhetoric approach” to argumentation from the “new rhetoric” of Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca. The term normative pragmatics, which van Eemeren (1986, 1990) introduced as a general label, is a more suitable starting point for further differentiations.

  125. 125.

    This discussion of criticisms is based on van Eemeren (2012).

  126. 126.

    In a review of Johnson’s (2000) Manifest Rationality, van Rees (2001) signals and corrects a whole series of misunderstandings of pragma-dialectics; that it is concerned only with spoken and not with written arguments being just one of them and that it is concerned only with dialogic and not with monolectical discourse another one.

  127. 127.

    Woods (2006) seems a case in point, but in other publications (e.g., Woods 2004) this critic’s conclusions are in the end more positive.

  128. 128.

    According to Wohlrapp (2009, p. 41), linguistic pragmatics is insufficient and Popper hardly understood anything of dialectic (2009, p. 41). Wohlrapp also regrets that pragma-dialectics does not account for differences of “frames” (but see van Eemeren 2010, pp. 126–127).

  129. 129.

    Bermejo-Luque (2011, pp. 58–72) also tackles the pragmatic dimension of pragma-dialectics, but Andone (2012) points out the weaknesses of Bermejo-Luque’s claims.

  130. 130.

    As her discussion of the Gulf Debate in American Congress makes clear, Goodwin (1999) uses the term argumentation in the general sense of “argument.” Her tentative definition of argumentation as “showing” that a standpoint is acceptable and her reference to the terms demonstrare and apodeixis, which are associated with logical proof, confirm this reading. Goodwin emphasizes that some politicians who advanced “argumentation” in Congress said explicitly that they did not want to convince and mentions “explaining” as one of the functions of “argumentation,” but in the pragma-dialectical usage “explaining” is a different function of “argument” than “argumentation.”

  131. 131.

    Gilbert suggests “moving away from the abstract to the actual, from the ideal to the real” (2001, p. 7). Although he presents this as a “continuation” of van Eemeren and Houtlosser’s inclusion of the rhetorical dimension of argumentation, what he seems to have in mind is something different: to continue by considering certain terminological and conceptual categories of pragma-dialectics merely as heuristic distinctions.

  132. 132.

    The principle of externalization promotes concentrating on traceable commitments in the analysis and evaluation“ of argumentative discourse (see Sect. 10.3). Application of this principle also creates an appropriate starting point for the examination of the cognitive processes involved in the production, perception, and appreciation of these commitments. For methodological reasons, pragma-dialecticians are reluctant to amalgamate argumentation theory completely with psychology, sociology, epistemology, communication theory, or any other discipline belonging to its intellectual resources.

  133. 133.

    In spite of the fact that generally rhetoricians themselves associate rhetoric primarily with aiming for effectiveness (see van Eemeren 2010, pp. 66–80), Kock (2007) criticizes the tendency among argumentation theorists to define “rhetorical” argumentation in this way. Arguers “speaking for opposite choices,” he also observes, are not “obliged” to resolve their difference of opinion. However, if they aim to convince others of their position, their argumentation must be aimed at resolving a difference of opinion with the audience they want to convince (which need not necessarily coincide with the opponents they address). Kock ignores that choosing from different options involves expressing a preference for a certain decision and that political argumentation is as a rule aimed at convincing others of the preferred option.

  134. 134.

    In a moralistic essay, in which he claims that Perelman “recognized the defining characteristic of totalitarian thought: the absolute commitment to the ‘cold logic’ of deductive reasoning” (p. 270), Frank (2004) reacts in the first place to criticisms in the handbook Fundamentals of argumentation theory (van Eemeren et al. 1996) and its predecessors of some aspects of Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca’s new rhetoric.

  135. 135.

    Leaving aside the wrong description of their soundness standard, and the fact that pragma-dialecticians in fact actively promote the democratic cause (e.g., van Eemeren 2002, 2010, pp. 2–4), the use of “good” is misleading, because pragma-dialecticians, being argumentation theorists, concentrate explicitly and exclusively on the argumentative quality (“soundness”) of advocacy, not on other qualities “good” may refer to.

  136. 136.

    In a more critical vein, Walton (2007) plays down the empirical scope of the pragma-dialectical theory by portraying a “critical discussion” as just one of the many dialogue types (or communicative activity types) used in argumentative reality, thus ignoring its status of a theoretical construct applying to all of them. See for the scope of pragma-dialectics, e.g., van Eemeren (Ed., 2009), and for a critical response to Walton, Garssen (2009, pp. 187–188).

  137. 137.

    Van Eemeren (2010) summarizes the pragma-dialectical position regarding the two dimensions of validity: “Granting that ‘conventional validity’ based in intersubjective agreement is indeed a prerequisite for reaching a conclusive judgment concerning the acceptability of argumentative moves, I would like to emphasize that, because of its overriding importance, determining their ‘problem-solving validity’ should come first” (p. 137). In agreement with this hierarchy, Tindale reaches in his discussion of the criticisms against pragma-dialectics eventually also the conclusion that “it is these rules (or the observance of them) which guarantee the reasonableness of the proceedings. So perhaps all along we have only needed to recognize these rules as the necessary objective conditions” (1999, p. 61). “The rules should have priority over the agreement of the discussants,” he acknowledges (p. 62).

  138. 138.

    This answers Tindale’s observation that, “in the shift to the new concept,” the pragma-dialecticians “appear to bring the old criteria of the traditional fallacies with them” (1999, p. 55).

  139. 139.

    Tindale (1999), who reaches on several points conclusions which do justice to the pragma-dialectical position, also recognizes the importance of problem-solving validity. It is indeed hard to imagine how one could embark on examining the fallacies from a normative perspective without having some kind of “etic” approach, involving external critical norms, because in an “emic” approach argumentative moves which are acceptable to the participants in the discussion do not require any further reflection as to their possible “fallaciousness.” See van Eemeren et al. (1993, pp. 50–51).

  140. 140.

    As a case in point, Woods (2004) claims erroneously that “the pragma-dialectical construal makes of ad baculum, ad hominem and ad misericordiam […] the same fallacy” (p. 156). He also observes that this construal of the traditional fallacies provides “brief caricatures straight out of the Standard Treatment” (p. 159, pp. 178–179), without mentioning that van Eemeren and Grootendorst precisely aim to show that pragma-dialectics can, in principle, accommodate the fallacies distinguished in the Standard Treatment.

  141. 141.

    Cummings (2005, p.178) reaches a negative judgment about pragma-dialectics based on the observations made by Woods. Striking in Wreen’s (1994) equally negative judgment are the basic assumptions that fallacies are intrinsically connected with inferences (whereas pragma-dialecticians put them in a broader communicative perspective) and have an objective ontological status (whereas pragma-dialecticians view them as impediments to resolving a difference of opinion on the merits whose identification depends on whether one shares this theoretical outlook on the discourse).

  142. 142.

    As Botting (2010) observes, from an epistemic perspective, critical discussion models “the critical rationalist procedure of conjecture and refutation” (p. 415).

  143. 143.

    Zenker concludes from his inventory of the (very few) changes the pragma-dialectical rules have undergone in the course of time that the most important material change is “the acknowledgement of non-deductive forms of validity” (2007a, p. 1588). Lumer (2010) asserts that van Eemeren and Grootendorst “originally” proposed “only one type of argumentation, namely deductive argumentation” and “more recently” included “some further argument schemes” (p. 65), “as a way to explain and justify non-deductive arguments” (p. 66). In reality, van Eemeren and Grootendorst distinguish already since 1978 argument(ation) schemes (van Eemeren et al. 1978, p. 20), next to (deductive and nondeductive) logical argument forms (e.g., van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1984, pp. 66–67).

  144. 144.

    Another critic who accuses pragma-dialectics of “some form of” deductivism is Kock (2003, p. 162).

  145. 145.

    Another critic who endorses this wrong characterization of pragma-dialectics is Lumer (2010). Botting (2010) indicates which basic characteristic of argumentative exchanges, captured in the model of a critical discussion, is probably the source of the consensualist misconception: a completed critical discussion “ends with consensus” (p. 416). However, in pragma-dialectics an unequivocal result of the process of resolving a difference of opinion is in a critical rationalist vein viewed as being only a temporary state of affairs in an ongoing flux of opinions. Unlike in consensualism, it does not represent a final point with a desired status, but a provisional outcome. See for a continuation of this discussion about the epistemic dimension of pragma-dialectics Lumer (2012) and Botting (2012).

  146. 146.

    Oddly, Zenker (2007b) ends up calling satisfaction of the preliminary higher-order conditions “a further necessary condition” for resolving differences of opinion. Ignoring that the pragma-dialecticians were the ones drawing attention to these preconditions for a legitimate application of the rules for critical discussion in evaluating the reasonableness of argumentative discourse, he correctly remarks that the nonfulfillment of certain higher-order conditions can explain seemingly unreasonable behavior (see van Eemeren et al. 1993, pp. 30–35). Without considering how far argumentation theorists should go in extending the boundaries of their efforts, he reproaches the pragma-dialecticians for their “apparent laxness” in not specifying the higher-order conditions “precisely and exhaustively.” It is doubtful whether it is really a proper task for argumentation theorists to examine whether in practice the psychological and sociopolitical higher-order conditions have been fulfilled.

  147. 147.

    Notions such as “pro argumentation” and “justificatory force” are in pragma-dialectics understood in a dialectical fashion and acquire a non-justificationist meaning. See also Garssen and van Laar (2010, p. 134).

  148. 148.

    In a paper marked by incomprehension, Lumer calls pragma-dialectics “a heterogeneous theory composed of unqualified and therefore unsatisfactory consensualism and an ill-conceived form of epistemic rationalism” (2010, p. 67) According to Lumer, pragma-dialectics relies on very problematic epistemologies, “namely Critical Rationalism and Dialogic Logic” (p. 67). However, “much could probably be improved by changing the epistemological basis of Pragma-Dialectics” (p. 58).

  149. 149.

    A similar point is made by Wreen (1994, p. 300).

  150. 150.

    Pragma-dialecticians, too, aim for the most rational outcome but leave room for the possibility that a definitive verdict about truth cannot be given in all cases because the necessary tools for doing so are lacking. In some cases we have to appeal to experts from the various disciplines, and if they cannot come to a unified verdict, we shall have to live with it. Some truths (e.g., non-flatness of the earth, global warming) were in limbo for some time. As Garssen and van Laar rightly ask (2010, p. 129): Who is to decide in such cases?

  151. 151.

    In this perspective, the addressees and their procedural and material starting points are of vital importance to argumentation theory. Siegel and Biro (2010, p. 467) may regret it, and perhaps Tindale (1999, p. 57) too, but as a consequence of argumentation’s involving not just reasoning but also trying to convince others, besides reaching a “problem-solving valid” conclusion, intersubjective agreement needs to be aimed for – and this makes it necessary to reach agreement between the parties. A consequence may be that (exceptionally, we hope) in practice (unlike, in epistemics, we hope) “good” arguments and standpoints are eventually rejected and “bad” arguments and standpoints accepted. This happens on reasonable grounds, however, only if the arguers have complied with all the required testing procedures. A “better” result can only be achieved if first the problem-solving validity of the testing methods for establishing truth, and for carrying out the other critical tests, is improved and the tests are made acceptable to would-be discussants.

  152. 152.

    Although assignment of truth values to such standpoints is not excluded, the disputants are not in the first place out to establish their truth but to determine their acceptability on reasonable grounds.

  153. 153.

    Siegel and Biro may claim that nothing in the epistemic view suggests that there cannot be arguments about moral, political, and legal matters (2010, p. 472), but the “justified beliefs” involved in dealing with evaluative and prescriptive issues can as a rule better be treated in terms of intersubjective acceptability than in terms of objective truth. Problem-solving validity and intersubjective validity have in pragma-dialectics a broader scope than these epistemologists seem to have in mind.

  154. 154.

    According to Biro and Siegel (2006b), the central difference between the two kinds of approaches lies in “the different ways they conceive of the role in argumentation and in argumentation theory of dispute resolution and epistemic seriousness, respectively” (p. 8). See also Biro and Siegel (2006a). We think however that the differences are a matter of how argumentation and argumentation theory are viewed rather than dispute resolution and epistemic “seriousness.”

  155. 155.

    See also Biro and Siegel (1992, p. 91).

  156. 156.

    As Tindale (disapprovingly) observes: the whole pragma-dialectical program “has been set up to be resolution-oriented and not audience-oriented (dialectical and not rhetorical)” (1999, p. 63).

  157. 157.

    Is it reasonable for participants to start from the best material and procedural starting points they have access to or only from starting points which epistemologists consider objectively true or valid? This is what the difference amounts to. As epistemologists, Biro and Siegel seem to be only interested in the assessment of argumentation by an external evaluator who judges the argumentation on “objective” grounds, independently of the particularities of the actual discussion in which it takes place and its intersubjective acceptability (see Siegel and Biro 2010, pp. 467–468). Apart from the question whether this is indeed a better view of what argumentation theory should be, the question arises to what extent in practice such an approach can lead to decisive results and is more suitable for dealing with argumentative discourse in the various communicative practices than the pragma-dialectical approach.

  158. 158.

    Establishing the acceptability of starting points is, according to pragma-dialecticians, not a proper task of argumentation theorists if it involves more than checking whether they are on the “list” of jointly accepted starting points. However, because of the critical rationalist rationale of their theory, it is understood that their acceptability is to be established in a problem-solving valid way.

  159. 159.

    According to Botting, “there is a way of testing a system of rules, showing that the rules pass these tests is a good way of arguing for their acceptance, and acceptance is, in the long run, a reliable indicator of verisimilitude” (p. 432). In his view, “the Normative Claim that standpoints that have the unqualified consensus of all participants in the dispute will generally be epistemically sound should be construed in the same way” (p. 432).

  160. 160.

    Interestingly, extremely different positions such as – bien etonnés de se trouver ensemble – Gerber’s and Frank’s pragmatic ethics and rhetorical moralism, on the one hand, and Biro and Siegel’s objectivist epistemics, on the other hand, have in common that they are out to include certain extrinsic requirements which, in the pragma-dialectical view, transcend argumentation and argumentation theory proper.

References

  • Aakhus, M. (2003). Neither naïve nor critical reconstruction. Dispute mediators, impasse and the design of argumentation. Argumentation, 17(3), 265–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (1975). Traktat über kritische Vernunft [Treatise on critical reason]. 2nd ed. Tübingen: Mohr. (1st ed. 1968, 5th improved and enlarged ed. 1991). (1st ed. 1968, 5th improved and enlarged ed. 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  • Amjarso, B. (2010). Mentioning and then refuting an anticipated counterargument. A conceptual and empirical study of the persuasiveness of a mode of strategic manoeuvring. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andone, C. (2010). Maneuvering strategically in a political interview: Analyzing and evaluating responses to an accusation of inconsistency. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andone, C. (2012). [Review of] Lilian Bermejo Luque. Giving reasons a linguistic-pragmatic approach to argumentation theory. Argumentation, 26(2), 291–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andone, C. (2013). Argumentation in political interviews. Analyzing and evaluating responses to accusations of inconsistency. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins (Revised version of Andone, 2010).

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. (1975). In J. O. Urmson & M. Sbisà (Eds.), How to do things with words (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barth, E. M., & Krabbe, E. C. W. (1982). From axiom to dialogue. A philosophical study of logics and argumentation. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermejo-Luque, L. (2011). Giving reasons. A linguistic-pragmatic approach to argumentation theory. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biro, J., & Siegel, H. (1992). Normativity, argumentation and an epistemic theory of fallacies. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Argumentation illuminated (pp. 85–103). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biro, J., & Siegel, H. (2006a). In defense of the objective epistemic approach to argumentation. Informal Logic, 26(1), 91–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biro, J., & Siegel, H. (2006b). Pragma-dialectic versus epistemic theories of arguing and arguments. Rivals or partners? In P. Houtlosser & A. van Rees (Eds.), Considering pragma-dialectics. A festschrift for Frans H. van Eemeren on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 1–10). Mahwah-London: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, J. A. (2006). Pragma-dialectics and pragma-dialectics. In P. Houtlosser & A. van Rees (Eds.), Considering pragma-dialectics. A festschrift for Frans H. van Eemeren on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 11–22). Mahwah-London: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonevac, D. (2003). Pragma-dialectics and beyond. Argumentation, 17(4), 451–459.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botting, D. (2010). A pragma-dialectical default on the question of truth. Informal Logic, 30(4), 413–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botting, D. (2012). Pragma-dialectics epistemologized. A reply. Informal Logic, 32(2), 266–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, H. (1979). Responding to indirect requests. Cognitive Psychology, 11, 430–477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosoreci Mazilu, S. (2010). Dissociation and persuasive definitions as argumentative strategies in ethical argumentation on abortion. Doctoral dissertation, University of Bucharest, Bucharest.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawshay-Williams, R. (1957). Methods and criteria of reasoning. An inquiry into the structure of controversy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummings, L. (2005). Pragmatics. A multidisciplinary perspective. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeMorgan, A. (1847). Formal logic. London: Taylor & Walton.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dijk, T. A., & Kintsch, W. (1983). Strategies of discourse comprehension. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doury, M. (2004). La position de l’analyste de l’argumentation [The position of the analyst of argumentation]. Semen, 17, 143–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doury, M. (2006). Evaluating analogy. Toward a descriptive approach to argumentative norms. In P. Houtlosser & A. van Rees (Eds.), Considering pragma-dialectics. A festschrift for Frans H. van Eemeren on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 35–49). Mahwah-London: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (1986). Dialectical analysis as a normative reconstruction of argumentative discourse. Text, 6(1), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (1987). Argumentation studies’ five estates. In J. W. Wenzel (Ed.), Argument and critical practices. Proceedings of the fifth SCA/AFA conference on argumentation (pp. 9–24). Annandale: Speech Communication Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (1990). The study of argumentation as normative pragmatics. Text, 10(1/2), 37–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (2002). Democracy and argumentation. Controversia, 1(1), 69–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (Ed.). (2009). Examining argumentation in context. Fifteen studies on strategic maneuvering. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (2010). Strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse. Extending the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins [trans. into Chinese (in preparation), Italian (2014), Japanese (in preparation), & Spanish (2013)].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (2012). The pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation in discussion. Argumentation, 26(4), 439–457.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (2013a). In what sense do modern argumentation theories relate to Aristotle? The case of pragma-dialectics. Argumentation, 27(1), 49–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (2013b). Maniobras estratégicas en el discurso argumentativo. Extendiendo la teoría pragma-dialéctica de la argumentación. Madrid-Mexico: Consejo Superior de Investigaciones Científicas (CSIC)/Plaza & Valdés. Theoria cum Praxi. [trans.: Santibáñez Yáñez, C. & Molina, M. E. of F. H. van Eemeren (2010), Strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse. Extending the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H. (2014). Mosse e strategie tra retorica e argomentazione. Naples: Loffredo. [trans.: Bigi, S., & Gilardoni, A. of F. H. van Eemeren (2010), Strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse. Extending the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Garssen, B. (Eds.). (2008). Controversy and confrontation. Relating controversy analysis with argumentation theory. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Garssen, B. (2009). The fallacies of composition and division revisited. Cogency, 1(1), 23–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Garssen, B. (2010). In varietate concordia – United in diversity. European parliamentary debate as an argumentative activity type. Controversia, 7(1), 19–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Garssen, B. (2011). Exploiting the room for strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse. Dealing with audience demand in the European Parliament. In F. H. van Eemeren & B. Garssen (Eds.), Exploring argumentative contexts. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F., Garssen, B., & Meuffels, B. (2009). Fallacies and judgments of reasonableness. Empirical research concerning the pragma-dialectical discussion rules. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Garssen, B., & Meuffels, B. (2012a). Effectiveness through reasonableness. Preliminary steps to pragma-dialectical effectiveness research. Argumentation, 26(1), 33–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Garssen, B., & Meuffels, B. (2012b). The disguised abusive ad hominem empirically investigated. Strategic maneuvering with direct personal attacks. Thinking & Reasoning, 18(3), 344–364.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Garssen, B., & Wagemans, J. (2012). The pragma-dialectical method of analysis and evaluation. In R. C. Rowland (Ed.), Reasoned argument and social change. Selected papers from the seventeenth biennial conference on argumentation sponsored by the National Communication Association and the American Forensic Association (pp. 25–47). Washington, DC: National Communication Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., de Glopper, K., Grootendorst, R., & Oostdam, R. (1995). Identification of unexpressed premises and argumentation schemes by students in secondary school. Argumentation and Advocacy, 31(Winter), 151–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1984). Speech acts in argumentative discussions. A theoretical model for the analysis of discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Dordrecht: Foris & Berlin: de Gruyter [trans. into Russian (1994c) & Spanish (2013)].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1990). Analyzing argumentative discourse. In R. Trapp & J. Schuetz (Eds.), Perspectives on argumentation. Essays in honor of Wayne Brockriede (pp. 86–106). Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1991a). The study of argumentation from a speech act perspective. In J. Verschueren (Ed.), Pragmatics at issue. Selected papers of the International Pragmatics Conference, Antwerp, August 17–22, 1987, I (pp. 151–170). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1991b). [Chinese title]. Beijing: Peking University Press. [trans.: Shi Xu of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (1992a), Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1992a). Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum (trans. into Bulgarian (2009), Chinese (1991b), French (1996), Romanian (2010), Russian (1992b), Spanish (2007)].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1992b). [Russian title]. St. Petersburg: St. Petersburg University Press. [trans.: Chakoyan, L., Golubev, V., & Tretyakova,T. of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (1992a), Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1994a). Rationale for a pragma-dialectical perspective. In F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (Eds.), Studies in pragma-dialectics (pp. 11–28). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1994b). Rechevye akty v argumentativnykh diskusiyakh. Teoreticheskaya model analiza diskussiy, napravlennyh na razresheniye konflikta mneniy. St. Petersburg: St. Petersburg University Press. [trans.: Bogoyavlenskaya, E., & Chakhoyan, L. (Ed.) of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst, Speech acts in argumentative discussions. A theoretical model for the analysis of discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Dordrecht: Foris & Berlin: de Gruyter].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1996). La nouvelle dialectique. Paris: Kimé. [trans.: Bruxelles, S., Doury, M., Traverso, V., & Plantin, C. of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (1992a), Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (1999). From analysis to presentation. A pragma-dialectical approach to writing argumentative texts. In J. Andriessen & P. Coirier (Eds.), Foundations of argumentative text processing (pp. 59–73). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2002). [Chinese title]. Beijing: Peking University Press. [trans.: Zhang Shuxue of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (2004), A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2004). A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (trans. into Bulgarian (2006), Chinese (2002), Italian (2008) & Spanish (2011)).

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2006). Sistemna teoria na argumentaciata (Pragmatiko-dialekticheski podhod). Sofia: Sofia University Press. [trans.: Pencheva, M. of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (2004), A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2007). Argumentación, comunicación y falacias. Una perspectiva pragma-dialéctica. 2nd ed. Santiago, Chile: Ediciones Universidad Católica de Chile. (1st ed. 1992). [trans: López, C., & Vicuña, A. M. of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst, A systematic theory of argumentation. A pragma-dialectical perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2008). Una teoria sistematica dell’argomentazione. L’approccio pragma-dialettico. Milan: Mimesis. [trans.: Gilardoni, A. of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (2004), A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2009). Kak da pechelim debati (Argumentacia, komunikacia I greshki. Pragma-dialekticheski podhod), II. Sofia: Sofia University Press. [trans: Alexandrova, D. of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (1992a), Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. The pragma-dialectical approach].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2010). Argumentare, comunicare şi sofisme. O perspectivă pragma-dialectică. Galati: Galati University Press. [trans:. Andone, C., & Gâţă, A. of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (1992a), Argumentation, communication, and fallacies. A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2011). Una teoría sistemática de la argumentación. La perspectiva pragmadialéctica. Buenos Aires: Biblos Ciencias del Lenguaje. [trans.: López, C., & Vicuña, A. M. of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (2004), A systematic theory of argumentation. The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2013). Los actos de habla en las discusiones argumentativas. Un modelo teórico para el análisis de discusiones orientadas hacia la resolución de diferencias de opinión. Santiago, Chile: Ediciones Universidad Diego Portales. [trans.: Santibáþez Yáñez, C. & Molina, M. E. of F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (1984). Speech acts in argumentative discussions. A theoretical model for the analysis of discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Dordrecht/Cinnaminson: Foris & Berlin: de Gruyter].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., Jackson, S., & Jacobs, S. (1993). Reconstructing argumentative discourse. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Kruiger, T. (1978). Argumentatietheorie [Argumentation theory]. Utrecht-Antwerpen: Het Spectrum. (2nd enlarged ed. 1981; 3rd ed. 1986). [English trans. 1984, 1987].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Meuffels, B. (1984). Het identificeren van enkelvoudige argumentatie [Identifying single argumentation]. Tijdschrift voor Taalbeheersing, 6(4), 297–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Meuffels, B. (1985). Gedifferentieerde replicaties van identificatieonderzoek [Differentiated replications of identification research]. Tijdschrift voor Taalbeheersing, 7(4), 241–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Meuffels, B. (1987). Identificatie van argumentatie als vaardigheid [Identifying argumentation as a skill]. Spektator, 16(5), 369–379.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Meuffels, B. (1989). The skill of identifying argumentation. Journal of the American Forensic Association, 25(4), 239–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Meuffels, B. (1990). Valkuilen achter een rookgordijn [Pitfalls behind a smokescreen]. Tijdschrift voor Taalbeheersing, 12(1), 47–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2002a). Argumentation. Analysis, evaluation, presentation. Mahwah, NJ: Routledge/Lawrence Erlbaum. [trans. into Albanian (2006a), Armenian (2004), Chinese (2006b), Italian (2011), Japanese (in preparation), Portuguese (in preparation), Russian (2002b), Spanish (2006c)].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2002b). Argumentaciya. Analiz, proverka, predstavleniye. St. Petersburg: Faculty of Philology, St. Petersburg State University. Student Library. [trans.: Chakhoyan, L., Tretyakova, T., & Goloubev, V. of F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst & A. F. Snoeck Henkemans (2002a), Argumentation. Analysis, evaluation, presentation. Mahwah, NJ:Routledge/Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2004). [Armenian title]. Yerevan: Academy of Philosophy of Armenia. [trans: Brutian, L. of F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst & A. F. Snoeck Henkemans (2002a), Argumentation. Analysis, evaluation, presentation. Mahwah, NJ: Routledge/Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2006a). Argumentimi. Analiza, Evaluimi, Prezentimi. Tetovo, Macedonia: Forum for Society, Science and Culture ‘Universitas’. [trans.: Memedi, V. of F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst & A. F. Snoeck Henkemans (2002a), Argumentation. Analysis, evaluation, presentation. Mahwah, NJ: Routledge/Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2006b). [Chinese title]. Beijing: New World Press. [trans.: Minghui Xiong, of F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst & A. F. Snoeck Henkemans (2002a), Argumentation. Analysis, evaluation, presentation. Mahwah, NJ: Routledge/Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2006c). Argumentación. Análisis, evaluación, presentación. Buenos Aires: Biblos Ciencias del Lenguaje. [trans: Marafioti, R. of F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst & A. F. Snoeck Henkemans (2002a), Argumentation. Analysis, evaluation, presentation. Mahwah, NJ: Routledge/Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2011a). Il galateo della discussione (Orale e scritta). Milan: Mimesis. [trans.: Gilardoni, A. of F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst & A. F. Snoeck Henkemans (2002a). Argumentation. Analysis, evaluation, presentation. Mahwah: Routledge/Lawrence Erlbaum].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Grootendorst, R., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F., with Blair, J. A., Johnson, R. H., Krabbe, E. C. W., Plantin, C., Walton, D. N., Willard, C. A., Woods, J., & Zarefsky, D. (1996). Fundamentals of argumentation theory. Handbook of historical backgrounds and contemporary developments. Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum. [trans. into Dutch (1997)].

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (1999). William the Silent’s argumentative discourse. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Proceedings of the fourth conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (pp. 168–171). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (2000a). Rhetorical analysis within a pragma-dialectical framework. The case of R. J. Reynolds. Argumentation, 14(3), 293–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (2000b). The rhetoric of William the Silent’s Apologie. A dialectical perspective. In T. Suzuki, Y. Yano, & T. Kato (Eds.), Proceedings of the first Tokyo Conference on argumentation (pp. 37–40). Tokyo: Japan Debate Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (2002a). Strategic maneuvering. Maintaining a delicate balance. In F. H. van Eemeren & P. Houtlosser (Eds.), Dialectic and rhetoric. The warp and woof of argumentation analysis (pp. 131–159). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (2002b). Strategic maneuvering with the burden of proof. In F. H. van Eemeren (Ed.), Advances in pragma-dialectics (pp. 13–28). Amsterdam-Newport News: Sic Sat/Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (2003a). A pragmatic view of the burden of proof. In F. H. van Eemeren, A. F. Snoeck Henkemans, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Anyone who has a view. Theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation (pp. 123–132). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (2003b). Strategic manoeuvring. William the Silent’s Apologie. A case in point. In L. I. Komlósi, P. Houtlosser, & M. Leezenberg (Eds.), Communication and culture. Argumentative, cognitive and linguistic perspectives (pp. 177–185). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (2007). Seizing the occasion. Parameters for analysing ways of strategic manoeuvring. In F. H. van Eemeren, J. A. Blair, C. A. Willard, & B. Garssen (Eds.), Proceedings of the sixth conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (pp. 375–380). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., & Houtlosser, P. (2008). Rhetoric in a dialectical framework. Fallacies as derailments of strategic manoeuvring. In E. Weigand (Ed.), Dialogue and rhetoric (pp. 133–151). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Houtlosser, P., Ihnen, C., & Lewiński, M. (2010). Contextual considerations in the evaluation of argumentation. In C. Reed & C. T. Tindale (Eds.), Dialectics, dialogue and argumentation. An examination of Douglas Walton’s theories of reasoning and argument (pp. 115–132). London: King’s College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Houtlosser, P., & Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2007). Argumentative indicators in discourse. A pragma-dialectical study. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Jackson, S., & Jacobs, S. (2011b). Argumentation. In T. A. van Dijk (Ed.), Discourse studies. A multidisciplinary introduction (pp. 85–106). Los Angeles: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F. H., Meuffels, B., & Verburg, M. (2000). The (un)reasonableness of the argumentum ad hominem. Language and Social Psychology, 19(4), 416–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fairclough, N. (1995). Critical discourse analysis. The critical study of language. London: Longman Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, E. T. (1989). Discussieregels in het recht. Een pragma-dialectische analyse van het burgerlijk proces en het strafproces als kritische discussie [Discussion rules in law. A pragma-dialectical analysis of civil lawsuits and criminal trials as a critical discussion]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, E. T. (1999). Fundamentals of legal argumentation. A survey of theories on the justification of judicial decisions. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, E. T. (2002). A pragma-dialectical approach of the analysis and evaluation of pragmatic argumentation in a legal context. Argumentation, 16(3), 349–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feteris, E. T. (2009). Strategic maneuvering in the justification of judicial decisions. In F. H. van Eemeren (Ed.), Examining argumentation in context. Fifteen studies on strategic maneuvering (pp. 93–114). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finocchiaro, M. (2006). Reflections on the hyper dialectical definition of argument. In P. Houtlosser & A. van Rees (Eds.), Considering pragma-dialectics. A festschrift for Frans H. van Eemeren on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 51–62). Mahwah-London: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, A. (2004). The logic of real arguments (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (1st ed. 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  • Foss, S., Foss, K., & Trapp, R. (1985). Contemporary perspectives on rhetoric. Prospect Heights: Waveland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, D. A. (2004). Argumentation studies in the wake of The New Rhetoric. Argumentation and Advocacy, 40(Spring), 267–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garssen. B. J. (1997). Argumentatieschema’s in pragma-dialectisch perspectief. Een theoretisch en empirisch onderzoek [Argument schemes in a pragma-dialectical perspective. A theoretical and empirical research]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garssen, B. (2002). Understanding argument schemes. In F. H. van Eemeren (Ed.), Advances in pragma-dialectics (pp. 93–104). Amsterdam-Newport News: Sic Sat/Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garssen, B. (2009). Book review of Dialog theory for critical argumentation by Douglas N. Walton (2007). Journal of Pragmatics, 41, 186–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garssen, B., & van Laar, J. A. (2010). A pragma-dialectical response to objectivist epistemic challenges. Informal Logic, 30(2), 122–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garver, E. (2000). Comments on rhetorical analysis within a pragma-dialectical framework. Argumentation, 14, 307–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerber, M. (2011). Pragmatism, pragma-dialectics, and methodology. Toward a more ethical notion of argument criticism. Speaker and Gavel, 48(1), 21–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerlofs, J. M. (2009). The use of conditionals in argumentation. A proposal for the analysis and evaluation of argumentatively used conditionals. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerritsen, S. (1999). Het verband ontgaat me. Begrijpelijkheidsproblemen met verzwegen argumenten [The connection escapes me. Problems of understanding with unexpressed premises]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam: Uitgeverij Nieuwezijds

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. A. (1997). Coalescent argumentation. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. A. (2001). Ideal argumentation. A paper presented at the 4th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation. Windsor, ON.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. A. (2005). Let’s talk. Emotion and the pragma-dialectical model. In F. H. van Eemeren & P. Houtlosser (Eds.), Argumentation in practice (pp. 43–52). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodnight, G. T., & Pilgram, R. (2011). A doctor’s ethos enhancing maneuvers in medical consultation. In E. Feteris, B. Garssen, & F. Snoeck Henkemans (Eds.), Keeping in touch with pragma-dialectics. In honor of Frans H. van Eemeren (pp. 135–151). Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, J. (1999). Good argument without resolution. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Proceedings of the fourth international conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (pp. 255–259). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco Morasso, S. (2009). Argumentation in dispute mediation. A reasonable way to handle conflict. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. (1995). What pragma-dialectics can learn from deductivism, and what deductivism can learn from pragma-dialectics. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Analysis and evaluation. Proceedings of the third ISSA conference on argumentation (University of Amsterdam, June 21–24, 1994) (Vol. II, pp. 138–145). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1971). Vorbereitende Bemerkungen zu einer Theorie der kommunikativen Kompetenz [Preparatory remarks on a theory of communicative competence]. In J. Habermas & H. Luhmann (Eds.), Theorie der Gesellschaft oder Sozialtechnologie. Was leistet die Systemforschung? [Theory of society or social technology: Where does system research lead to?] (pp. 107–141). Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1981). Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns [Theory of communicative action]. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1994). Postscript to Faktizität und Geltung [Postscript to between facts and norms]. Philosophy & Social Criticism, 20(4), 135–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms (trans. Rehg, W.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, P. A., & Taylor, R. C. R. (1996). Political science and the three new institutionalisms. Political Studies, 44, 936–957.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. L. (1970). Fallacies. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample, D. (2003). Arguing skill. In J. O. Greene & B. R. Burleson (Eds.), Handbook of communication and social interaction skills (pp. 439–477). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hample, D. (2007). The arguers. Informal Logic, 27(2), 163–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, H. (2003). Theories of presumption and burden of proof. Proceedings of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), Windsor, ON: OSSA. CD rom.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hietanen, M. (2005). Paul’s argumentation in Galatians. A pragma-dialectical analysis of Gal. 3.2-5.12. Doctoral dissertation, Abo Akademi University, Turku.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohmann, H. (2002). Rhetoric and dialectic. Some historical and legal perspectives. In F. H. van Eemeren & P. Houtlosser (Eds.), Dialectic and rhetoric. The warp and woof of argumentation analysis (pp. 41–52). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Houtlosser, P. (1995). Standpunten in een kritische discussie. Een pragma-dialectisch perspectief op de identificatie en reconstructie van standpunten [Standpoints in a critical discussion. A pragma-dialectical perspective on the identification and reconstruction of standpoints]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam: IFOTT

    Google Scholar 

  • Houtlosser, P. (2003). Commentary on H. V. Hansen’s ‘Theories of presumption and burden of proof’. Proceedings of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), Windsor, ON: OSSA. CD rom.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hymes, D. (1972). Foundations in sociolinguistics. An ethnographic approach. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ieţcu-Fairclough, I. (2009). Legitimation and strategic maneuvering in the political field. In F. H. van Eemeren (Ed.), Examining argumentation in context. Fifteen studies on strategic maneuvering (pp. 131–152). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihnen Jory, C. (2010). The analysis of pragmatic argumentation in law-making debates. Second reading of the terrorism bill in the British House of Commons. Controversia, 7(1), 91–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihnen Jory, C. (2012). Pragmatic argumentation in law-making debates. Instruments for the analysis and evaluation of pragmatic argumentation at the Second Reading of the British parliament. Amsterdam: Sic Sat/Rozenberg. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S. (1992). ‘Virtual standpoints’ and the pragmatics of conversational argument. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Argumentation illuminated (pp. 260–269). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S. (1995). Fallacies and heuristics. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Analysis and evaluation. Proceedings of the third ISSA conference on argumentation (Vol. II, pp. 257–269). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S., & Jacobs, S. (2006). Derailments of argumentation. It takes two to tango. In P. Houtlosser & A. van Rees (Eds.), Considering pragma-dialectics. A festschrift for Frans H. van Eemeren on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 121–133). Mahwah-London: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, S. (1987). The management of disagreement in conversation. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Argumentation. Across the lines of discipline. Proceedings of the conference on argumentation 1986 (pp. 229–239). Dordrecht-Providence: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, S., & Aakhus, M. (2002). How to resolve a conflict. Two models of dispute resolution. In F. H. van Eemeren (Ed.), Advances in pragma-dialectics (pp. 29–44). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, H. (2003). Van omgekeerde strekking. Een pragma-dialectische reconstructie van a contrario-argumentatie in het recht [Inverted purpose. A pragma-dialectical reconstruction of e contrario argumentation in law]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam: Thela Thesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, H. (2005). E contrario reasoning. The dilemma of the silent legislator. Argumentation, 19(4), 485–496.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. H. (1995). Informal logic and pragma-dialectics. Some differences. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Analysis and evaluation. Proceedings of the third ISSA conference on argumentation (Vol. 2, pp. 237–245). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. H. (2000). Manifest rationality. A pragmatic theory of argument. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, R. H. (2003). The dialectical tier revisited. In F. H. van Eemeren, J. A. Blair, C. A. Willard, & A. F. Snoeck Henkemans (Eds.), Anyone who has a view. Theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation. Dordrecht-Boston-London: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jungslager, F. S. (1991). Standpunt en argumentatie. Een empirisch onderzoek naar leerstrategieën tijdens het leggen van een argumentatief verband [Standpoint and argumentation. An empirical research concerning learning strategies in making an argumentative connection]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeld, F. (2006). Pragma-dialectic’s appropriation of speech act theory. In P. Houtlosser & A. van Rees (Eds.), Considering pragma-dialectics. A festschrift for Frans H. van Eemeren on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 149–160). Mahwah-London: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, G. A. (1994). A new history of classical rhetoric. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kloosterhuis, H. T. M. (2002). Van overeenkomstige toepassing. De pragma-dialectische reconstructie van analogie-argumentatie in rechterlijke uitspraken [Similar applications. The pragma-dialectical reconstruction of analogy argumentation in pronouncements of judges]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam: Thela Thesis

    Google Scholar 

  • Kloosterhuis, H. [T. M.] (2006). Reconstructing interpretative argumentation in legal decisions. A pragma-dialectical approach. Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kock, C. (2003). Multidimensionality and non-deductiveness in deliberative argumentation. In F. H. van Eemeren, J. A. Blair, C. A. Willard, & A. F. Snoeck Henkemans (Eds.), Anyone who has a view. Theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation (pp. 157–171). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kock, C. (2007). The domain of rhetorical argumentation. In F. H. van Eemeren, J. A. Blair, C. A. Willard, & B. Garssen (Eds.), Proceedings of the sixth conference of the International Society of the Study of Argumentation (pp. 785–788). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koetsenruijter, A. W. M. (1993). Meningsverschillen. Analytisch en empirisch onderzoek naar de reconstructie en interpretatie van de confrontatiefase in discussies [Differences of opinion. Analytical and empirical research concerning the reconstruction and interpretation of the confrontation stage in discussions]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam: IFOTT

    Google Scholar 

  • Krabbe, E. C. W. (2002). Profiles of dialogue as a dialectical tool. In F. H. van Eemeren (Ed.), Advances of pragma-dialectics (pp. 153–167). Amsterdam-Newport News: Sic Sat/Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kutrovátz, G. (2008). Rhetoric of science, pragma-dialectics, and science studies. In F. H. van Eemeren & B. Garssen (Eds.), Controversy and confrontation. Relating controversy analysis with argumentation theory (pp. 231–247). Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Laar, J. A. (2008). Pragmatic inconsistency and credibility. In F. H. van Eemeren & B. Garssen (Eds.), Controversy and confrontation. Relating controversy analysis with argumentation theory (pp. 163–179). Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Labrie, N. (2012). Strategic maneuvering in treatment decision-making discussions. Two cases in point. Argumentation, 26(2), 171–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1992). Activity types and language. In P. Drew & J. Heritage (Eds.), Talk at work. Interaction in institutional settings (pp. 66–100). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewiński, M. (2010). Internet political discussion forums as an argumentative activity type. A pragma-dialectical analysis of online forms of strategic manoeuvring with critical reactions. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lumer, C. (2010). Pragma-dialectics and the function of argumentation. Argumentation, 24(1), 41–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lumer, C. (2012). The epistemic inferiority of pragma-dialectics. Informal Logic, 32(1), 51–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lunsford, A., Wilson, K., & Eberly, R. (2009). Introduction. Rhetorics and roadmaps. In A. Lunsford, K. Wilson, & R. Eberly (Eds.), The Sage handbook of rhetorical studies (pp. xi–xxix). Los Angeles: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massey, G. (1975). Are there any good arguments that bad arguments are bad? Philosophy in Context, 4, 61–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mohammed, D. (2009). The honourable gentleman should make up his mind. Strategic manoeuvring with accusations of inconsistency in Prime Minister’s Question Time. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muraru, D. (2010). Mediation and diplomatic discourse. The strategic use of dissociation and definitions. Doctoral dissertation, University of Bucharest, Bucharest.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oostdam, R. J. (1991). Argumentatie in de peiling. Een aanbod- en prestatiepeiling van argumentatievaardigheden in het voortgezet onderwijs [Argumentation to the test. A test of material and achievements relating to argumentative skills in secondary education]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perelman, C., & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1969). The new rhetoric. A treatise on argumentation (trans. Wilkinson, J., & Weaver, P.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. (1st ed. published in French in 1958).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pike, K. L. (1967). Etic and emic standpoints for the description of behavior. In D. C. Hildum (Ed.), Language and thought. An enduring problem in psychology (pp. 32–39). Princeton: Van Norstrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, R. C., & Blair, J. A. (1989). Information, inference and argument. A handbook of critical thinking. Windsor, ON: University of Windsor (Internal publication).

    Google Scholar 

  • Plug, H. J. (1999). Evaluating tests for reconstructing the structure of legal argumentation. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Proceedings of fourth international conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (pp. 639–643). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plug, H. J. (2000a). Indicators of obiter dicta. A pragma-dialectical analysis of textual clues for the reconstruction of legal argumentation. Artificial Intelligence and Law, 8, 189–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plug, H. J. (2000b). In onderlinge samenhang bezien. De pragma-dialectische reconstructie van complexe argumentatie in rechterlijke uitspraken [Considered in mutual interdependence. The pragma-dialectical reconstruction of complex argumentation in pronouncements of judges]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam: Thela Thesis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plug, H. J. (2002). Maximally argumentative analysis of judicial argumentation. In F. H. van Eemeren (Ed.), Advances in pragma-dialectics (pp. 261–270). Amsterdam-Newport News: Sic Sat/Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plug, H. J. (2010). Ad-hominem arguments in Dutch and European parliamentary debates. Strategic manoeuvring in an institutional context. In C. Ilie (Ed.), Discourse and metadiscourse in parliamentary debates (pp. 305–328). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plug, H. J. (2011). Parrying ad-hominem arguments in parliamentary debates. In F. H. van Eemeren, B. J. Garssen, D. Godden, & G. Mitchell (Eds.), Proceedings of the 7th conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (pp. 1570–1578). Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat. CD-rom.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Poppel, L. (2011). Solving potential disputes in health brochures with pragmatic argumentation. In F. H. van Eemeren, B. J. Garssen, D. Godden & G. Mitchell (Eds.), Proceedings of the 7th conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (pp. 1559–1570). Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat. CD rom.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Poppel, L. (2013). Getting the vaccine now will protect you in the future! A pragma-dialectical analysis of strategic maneuvering with pragmatic argumentation in health brochures. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Poppel, L., & Rubinelli, S. (2011). Try the smarter way’. On the claimed efficacy of advertised medicines. In E. Feteris, B. Garssen, & F. Snoeck Henkemans (Eds.), Keeping in touch with pragma-dialectics. In honor of Frans H. van Eemeren (pp. 153–163). Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective knowledge. An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1974). Conjectures and refutations. The growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (1989). Het kritische gehalte van probleemoplossende discussies [The critical quality of problem-solving discussions]. In M. M. H. Bax & W. Vuijk (Eds.), Thema’s in de taalbeheersing [Themes in speech communication research] (pp. 29–36). Dordrecht: ICG Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (1991). Problem solving and critical discussion. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Argumentation illuminated (pp. 281–291). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (1992a). The adequacy of speech act theory for explaining conversational phenomena. A response to some conversation analytical critics. Journal of Pragmatics, 17, 31–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (1992b). Problem solving and critical discussion. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Argumentation illuminated (pp. 281–291). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (1994a). Analysing and evaluating problem-solving discussions. In F. H. van Eemeren & R. Grootendorst (Eds.), Studies in pragma-dialectics (pp. 197–217). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (1994b). Functies van herhalingen in informele discussies [Functions of repetitions in informal discussions]. In A. Maes, P. van Hauwermeiren, & L. van Waes (Eds.), Perspectieven in taalbeheersingsonderzoek [Perspectives in speech communication research] (pp. 44–56). Dordrecht: ICG.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (1995a). Argumentative discourse as a form of social interaction. Implications for dialectical reconstruction. In F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, & C. A. Willard (Eds.), Reconstruction and application. Proceedings of the third international conference on argumentation, III (pp. 159–167). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (1995b). Functions of repetition in informal discussions. In C. Bazanella (Ed.), Repetition in dialogue (pp. 141–155). Berlin-New York: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (2001). Review of Manifest Rationality of R. H. Johnson. Argumentation, 15(2), 231–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (2003). Within pragma-dialectics. Comments on Bonevac. Argumentation, 17(4), 461–464.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (2009). Dissociation in argumentative discussions. A pragma-dialectical perspective. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rigotti, E., & Rocci, A. (2006). Towards a definition of communicative context. Foundations of an interdisciplinary approach to communication. Studies in Communication Sciences, 6(2), 155–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts. An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1979). Expression and meaning. Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1995). The construction of social reality. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H., & Biro, J. (2010). The pragma-dialectician’s dilemma. Reply to Garssen and van Laar. Informal Logic, 30(4), 457–480.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slot, P. (1993). How can you say that? Rhetorical questions in argumentative texts. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam: IFOTT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, E. E., & Medin, D. L. (1981). Categories and concepts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (1992). Analysing complex argumentation. The reconstruction of multiple and coordinatively compound argumentation in a critical discussion. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam. Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2005). What’s in a name? The use of the stylistic device metonymy as a strategic manoeuvre in the confrontation and argumentation stages of a discussion. In D. L. Hitchcock (Ed., 2005a), The uses of argument. Proceedings of a conference at McMaster University 18–21 May 2005 (pp. 433–441). Hamilton: Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2009a). Manoeuvring strategically with rhetorical questions. In F. H. van Eemeren, B. Garssen, & B. Garssen (Eds.), Pondering on problems of argumentation. Twenty essays on theoretical issues (pp. 15–23). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2009b). The contribution of praeteritio to arguers’ confrontational strategic manoeuvres. In F. H. van Eemeren (Ed.), Examining argumentation in context. Fifteen studies on strategic maneuvering (pp. 241–255). Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snoeck Henkemans, A. F. (2011). Shared medical decision-making. Strategic maneuvering by doctors in the presentation of their treatment preferences to patients. In F. H. van Eemeren, B. J. Garssen, D. Godden, & G. Mitchell (Eds.), Proceedings of the 7th conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (pp. 1811–1818). Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat. CD rom.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swearingen, C. J., & Schiappa, E. (2009). Historical studies in rhetoric. Revisionist methods and new directions. In A. Lusford, K. Wilson, & R. Eberly (Eds.), The Sage handbook of rhetorical studies (pp. 1–12). Los Angeles: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tindale, C. W. (1999). Acts of arguing. A rhetorical model of argument. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tindale, C. W. (2004). Rhetorical argumentation. Principles of theory and practice. Thousand Oaks: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tonnard, Y. M. (2011). Getting an issue on the table. A pragma-dialectical study of presentational choices in confrontational strategic maneuvering in Dutch parliamentary debate. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. E. (1976). Knowing and acting. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tseronis, A. (2009). Qualifying standpoints. Stance adverbs as a presentational device for managing the burden of proof. Doctoral dissertation, Leiden University. Utrecht: LOT

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbiest, A. E. M. (1987). Confrontaties in conversaties. Een analyse op grond van argumentatie- en gesprekstheoretische inzichten van het ontstaan van meningsverschillen in informele gesprekken [Confrontations in conversations. An analysis based on insights from argumentation theory and conversation theory about the origin of differences of opinion in informal conversations]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viskil, E. (1994). Definiëren. Een bijdrage aan de theorievorming over het opstellen van definities [Defining. A contribution to the theorizing about the construction of definitions]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagemans, J. H. M. (2009). Redelijkheid en overredingskracht van argumentatie. Een historisch-filosofische studie over de combinatie van het dialectische en het retorische perspectief op argumentatie in de pragma-dialectische argumentatietheorie [Reasonableness and persuasiveness of argumentation. A historical-philosophical study on the combination of the dialectical and the rhetorical perspective on argumentation in the pragma-dialectical theory of argumentation]. Doctoral dissertation, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagemans, J. H. M. (2011). The assessment of argumentation from expert opinion. Argumentation, 25(3), 329–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1991a). Begging the question. Circular reasoning as a tactic of argumentation. New York: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1991b). Hamblin and the standard treatment of fallacies. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 24, 353–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1992). Plausible argument in everyday conversation. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1998). The new dialectic. Conversational contexts of argument. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (1999). Profiles of dialogue for evaluating arguments from ignorance. Argumentation, 13(1), 53–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N. (2007). Dialog theory for critical argumentation. Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. N., & Krabbe, E. C. W. (1995). Commitment in dialogue. Basic concepts of interpersonal reasoning. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenzel, J. W. (1990). Three perspectives on argument. Rhetoric, dialectic, logic. In R. Trapp & J. Schuetz (Eds.), Perspectives on argumentation. Essays in the honor of Wayne Brockriede (pp. 9–26). Prospect Heights: Waveland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wohlrapp, H. (2009). Der Begriff des Arguments. Über die Beziehungen zwischen Wissen, Forschen, Glauben, Subjektivität and Vernunft [The notion of argument. On the relations between knowing, researching, believing, subjectivity and rationality]. 2n ed. supplemented with a subject index. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (1991). Pragma-dialectics. A radical departure in fallacy theory. Communication and Cognition, 24(1), 43–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2004). The death of argument. Fallacies in agent-based reasoning. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2006). Pragma-dialectics. A retrospective. In P. Houtlosser & A. van Rees (Eds.), Considering pragma-dialectics. A festschrift for Frans H. van Eemeren on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 301–311). Mahwah-London: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J., & Walton, D. (1989). Fallacies. Selected papers 1972–1982. Berlin: de Gruyter/Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wreen, M. J. (1994). Look, Ma! No Frans! Pragmatics & Cognition, 2(2), 285–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zemplén, G. A. (2008). Scientific controversies and the pragma-dialectical model. Analysing a case study from the 1670s, the published part of the Newton-Lucas correspondence. In F. H. van Eemeren & B. Garssen (Eds.), Controversy and confrontation. Relating controversy analysis with argumentation theory (pp. 249–273). Amsterdam-Philadelphia: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zenker, F. (2007a). Changes in conduct-rules and ten commandments. Pragma-dialectics 1984 vs. 2004. In F. H. van Eemeren, J. A. Blair, C. A. Willard, & B. Garssen (Eds.), Proceedings of the sixth conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (pp. 1581–1489). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zenker, F. (2007b). Pragma-dialectic’s necessary conditions for a critical discussion. In J. A. Blair, H. Hansen, R. Johnson, & C. Tindale (Eds.), Proceedings of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA). Windsor, ON: OSSA. CD rom.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frans H. van Eemeren .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this entry

Cite this entry

van Eemeren, F.H., Garssen, B., Krabbe, E.C.W., Henkemans, A.F.S., Verheij, B., Wagemans, J.H.M. (2014). The Pragma-Dialectical Theory of Argumentation. In: Handbook of Argumentation Theory. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9473-5_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9473-5_10

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-9472-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-90-481-9473-5

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics