Skip to main content

The Limits of Reductionism: Thought, Life, and Reality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Wider den Reduktionismus

Zusammenfassung

What is the best question reductionists would have to answer but cannot, and why exactly is there no reductionist answer to that question? To answer this question, we need to identify the relevant question.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 29.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, for instance, Bratman (2014) for an attempt to understand group agency in terms of individual agency, and Rödl (2014a) for a non-reductive stance.

  2. 2.

    See Chalmers (1995)—I briefly return to Chalmers’ ‘easy’ and ‘hard’ problems shortly.

  3. 3.

    See Lewis (1986, pp. ix–x). The phrase comes from his formulation of the view he calls ‘Humean supervenience’.

  4. 4.

    For instance, supervenience claims do no more than state that supervening properties vary with their subven-ing property base (very roughly). They do not explain why that is so. And this is considered by most to be unsatisfactory. See, e.g., Kim (1998).

  5. 5.

    I mean to be echoing Wittgenstein here, who remarks in his Philosophical Investigations, regarding his own earlier Tractatus view, that “a picture held us captive” (Wittgenstein 1953, §15).

  6. 6.

    Indeed, Weisberg expresses a disarming enthusiasm towards this claim later in his book: “For my part, I think it’s super amazing that we might ‘just’ be a physical system. I find it incredibly inspirational to think of myself and the rest of humanity in this way.” (Weisberg 2014, p. 46).

  7. 7.

    Nonreductive physicalism is a curious phenomenon. It brings to light that, indeed, reductive physicalism is a picture holding those defending it captive: it holds them captive to such an extent that it is alright for them to grant it a self-cancelling name (‘nonreductive’ physicalism).—Another symptom of this situation is the following. In the face of the many difficulties that physicalists encounter in their attempts to formulate their distinctive, physicalist thesis, Alyssa Ney has come to defend physicalism as an “attitude”: “physicalism is an attitude one takes to form one’s ontology completely and solely according to what physics says exists” (Ney 2008, p. 9).

  8. 8.

    Color is a nice example; see Stroud (2000) for an excellent in-depth discussion. The issue whether classical genetics reduces to molecular biology is another fine instance—see, for an overview, Brigandt and Love (2017), and see also Sect. 4.3 below.

  9. 9.

    Is it really? What if I have reason to doubt C, won’t I then rather reject A or B, or suspend my judgment?—Sure. This is, however, no objection to the point under consideration; it rather illustrates that point. My judgments aren’t separate elements lying around in my awareness, unconnected. They are united, and their union is precisely my consciousness of their union. Famously, Kripke (1982) presented a reading of Wittgenstein on following a rule (‘Kripkenstein’) that does take note of problems such as the one concerning inference briefly outlined here. Kripke, however, fails to realize that the solution lies in the recognition of the self-consciousness of thought. That is why he ends up with his ‘skeptical solution’ (Kripke 1982, p. 66 ff.).

  10. 10.

    Perhaps there are such things as unconscious inferences. That is no objection to what I say here. At most, it is the mere observation that an account of such unconscious inferences is still lacking. See also Nagel (2012), esp. Chap. 4, and Kitcher (2011), esp. Chap. 15, §4.

  11. 11.

    The Anscombean tradition in contemporary philosophy of action makes the same point with regard to intentional action: my intentional action is not something independent of my knowledge of it. Anscombe expresses this, for instance, by saying that this knowledge, practical knowledge, is “the cause of what it understands”. See Anscombe (1957, §48), and also Rödl (2007, Chap. 2).

  12. 12.

    How do we know this to be the case, concerning science? Have we discovered it by empirical investigation? Obviously not; compare Rödl (2018, p. 16). The statement that science is concerned with comprehending given phenomena merely conveys the comprehension that is included in science. Science is self-conscious as well.—We will return to this in Sect. 4.4.

  13. 13.

    Notice that I do not thereby claim that cognitive science is a doomed project in its entirety. There might be very many processes that can be described using the ‘automatic’ sort of ‘cognitive systems’ one finds in cognitive science (early visual processing is a good example). But not thought.

  14. 14.

    The question what Gödel’s incompleteness theorems imply with regard to the philosophy of mind is, of course, a vexed one. See, for instance, the two essays by Putnam and Penrose on the topic in Baaz et al. (2011, Chaps. 15 and 16). For what it is worth: I do not think there is any route from Gödel’s incompleteness theorems to conclusions about thought. For one thing (and I owe this observation to Albert Visser), the tendency to traverse that route often results in a dispute over the claim whether the human mind is ‘more powerful’ than anything a mechanism could do (see the mentioned essays by Putnam and Penrose), where the notion of ‘power’ involved equivocates between the very abstract, theoretical concept of what lies within the ‘power’ of a given formal system on the one hand, and concrete mental abilities on the other.

    Instead, as I suggested here, the interesting project would be to try to comprehend the significance of Gödel’s results in the light of a proper understanding of thought, and that is, in the light of thought’s self-consciousness.

  15. 15.

    See especially Thompson (2008, Part I). For a much more detailed exposition and extension of the views Thompson puts forward, see Mulder (2016).

  16. 16.

    I ignore the fascinating question whether entropy itself can be reductively accounted for in terms of statistical mechanics. See, for a classical treatment, Sklar (1993, Chap. 9).

  17. 17.

    In this quotation, Thompson originally has ‘DNA’ instead of ‘entropy’. The point is in the end the same; con-sidering the hypothetical situation in which all and only living things turn out to contain DNA, Thompson writes: “The judgment about DNA, if it were true, would only show how resource-poor the physical world really is. It could make no contribution to the exposition of the concept of life [...]” (Thompson 2008, p. 37).

  18. 18.

    Dupré’s work is full of examples that illustrate the distinctiveness of life. He doesn’t take these observations all the way to a decidedly philosophical articulation of their ground—and therefore he ends with a rather generic insistence that we should shift to a ‘process metaphysics’ across the metaphysical board. See Dupré (2012, 2013, 2018).

  19. 19.

    It is interesting, in this light, to read in one of Gödel’s recently transcribed notebooks the following ‘philo-sophical remark’ on life:

    Life is obviously an imperfect structure, which therefore attracts matter from outside [...] and takes it up into its structure. The new structure obviously acts upon itself with a “destructive force”, resulting in the emission of urea and carbonic acid. Does this entire process result in a perfection of the original structure? (Our body only deteriorates over time and only our minds get better.) All of this shows, that life, continuously perfecting itself, comes from something that has no perfection. (Crocco et al. 2017, p. 7, my translation)

    It does not seem to occur to Gödel here that destruction may be an integral and crucial part of what it is to live. In any case, Gödel obviously granted life a sui generis position within his philosophical thought—as is also evi-dent from this quote: “Life force is a primitive element of the universe and it obeys certain laws of action.” (Wang 1997, p. 193). See also Kovac (218, §2.2.6) for discussion. For discussion of these and related issues see Mulder (2016).

  20. 20.

    For discussion of these and related issues see Mulder (2016).

  21. 21.

    Chalmers (2012) includes such “totality truths” as facts of a separate kind in his Carnap-inspired Constructing the World.

  22. 22.

    This insight, that the idea of reality is nothing other than the self-consciousness of thought, is central to Rödl’s (2018) Self-Consciousness and Objectivity—its title can be read accordingly.

  23. 23.

    This remark can be found in Gödel’s unpublished manuscript Max Phil VI, 404. I take the quote from Engelen (2016, p. 172), who also provided this English translation. (The Aristotelian proof Gödel here alludes to can be found in his De Anima III (Aristotle 1984, 429a18–29).) Of course, as the \(^*\)-footnote to this remark indicates, Gödel connects this Aristotelian insight with issues in set theory he was thinking about—Russell’s antinomy, the unlimited expansion of the set universe, the idea of proper classes. See Engelen (2016) for discussion.

  24. 24.

    Rödl (2014b, §2) discusses this argument extensively with the help of Plato’s version thereof in his Theaetetus.

  25. 25.

    Here, the traditional opposition between Erklären and Verstehen of course comes to mind.

  26. 26.

    This form of pluralism can be found in the work of philosophers belonging to the so-called ‘Stanford School’ in philosophy of science. See, e.g., Dupré (1993, 2018), and Galison and Stump (1996).

References

  • Anscombe, G. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Wiley & Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1984). On the soul (Trans. J.A. Smith). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1998). Metaphysics (Trans. H. Lawson-Tancred). London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baaz, M., Papadimitrou, C. H., Putnam, H. W., Scott, D. S., & Harper, C. L. (2011). Kurt Gödel and the foundation of mathematics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (2014). Shared agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt, I. & Love, A. (2017). Reductionism in biology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition).

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, S. B. (2005). The new science of evo devo—Endless forms most beautiful. New York: WW Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2, 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2012). Constructing the world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crocco, G., Van Atten, M., Cantu, P., & Engelen, E.-M. (2017). Kurt Gödel Maxims and philosophical remarks volume X. Available via HAL Archives Ouvertes: https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01459188. Accessed: 1. Sep. 2020.

  • Dupré, J. A. (1993). The disorder of things. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. A. (2012). Processes of life: Essays in the philosophy of biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. A. (2013). Living causes. Arist Soc P., 87(1), 19–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. A. (2018). A manifesto for a processual philosophy of biology. In D. J. Nicholson & A. Dupré (Eds.), Everything flows: Towards a processual philosophy of biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. L. (2011). Familiar objects and their shadows. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelen, E.-M. (2016). What is the link between Aristotle’s philosophy of mind, the iterative conception of set, Gödel’s incompleteness theorems and god?: About the pleasure and the difficulties of interpreting Kurt Gödel’s ’philosophical remarks’. Episteme. In G. Crocco (Ed.), Kurt Gödel: philosopher-scientist (pp. 171–188). Aix-en-Provence: Presses Universitaires de Provence.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galison, P., & Stump, D. J. (Eds.). (1996). The disunity of science: Boundaries, contexts, and power. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). The mind-body problem after fifty years. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Current issues in philosophy of mind (pp. 3–21). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2011). Kant’s thinker. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kovac, S. (2018). On causality as the fundamental concept of Gödel’s philosophy. Synthese, 197, 1803–1838.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1986). Philosophical papers (Vol. II). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1996). Mind and world. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulder, J. M. (2016). A vital challenge to materialism. Philosophy, 91(2), 153–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and cosmos. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A. (2008). Physicalism as an attitude. Philosophical Studies, 138(1), 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rödl, S. (2007). Self-consciousness. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rödl, S. (2014a). Intentional transaction. Philosophical Explorations, 17(3), 304–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rödl, S. (2014b). Review of transcendental philosophy and naturalism. European Journal of Philosophy, 22(3), S. 483–504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rödl, S. (2018). Self-consciousness and objectivity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (1994). Instrumental biology or the disunity of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sklar, L. (1993). Physics and chance: Philosophical issues in the foundations of statistical mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, B. (2000). The quest for reality: Subjectivism & the metaphysics of colour. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2008). Life and action: Elementary structures of practice and practical thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, H. (1997). A logical journey from Gödel to philosophy. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2014). Consciousness. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by the Dutch National Science Foundation NWO, VENI Grant (grant number 275-20-068). I am grateful to Albert Visser for valuable feedback on an early version.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jesse M. Mulder .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Der/die Autor(en), exklusiv lizenziert durch Springer-Verlag GmbH, DE, ein Teil von Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Mulder, J.M. (2021). The Limits of Reductionism: Thought, Life, and Reality. In: Passon, O., Benzmüller, C. (eds) Wider den Reduktionismus. Springer Spektrum, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-63187-4_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-63187-4_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer Spektrum, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-63186-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-63187-4

  • eBook Packages: Social Science and Law (German Language)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics