Skip to main content

General Introduction to the Handbuch Richard Rorty

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Handbuch Richard Rorty
  • 545 Accesses

Abstract

Richard Rorty is first introduced as both the best known and the most controversial neopragmatist. This introduction then offers a sketch of Rorty’s version of pragmatism that focuses on his democratic anti-authoritarianism, whose transformative aspiration must be taken seriously. The introduction then outlines the main themes of Rorty scholarship for users of the Handbuch, e.g. the questions of truth, realism, relativism, and religion. The debates in the scholarship revolve around Rorty’s transformative aspiration and around what are taken to be the (too rigid) key distinctions he draws: argumentation/redescription, causation/justification, and private/public.

One goal of this companion is to continue the conversation among researchers about Rorty. However, it is primarily intended to provide a systematic and comprehensive overview. The presentation of a systematic and comprehensive overview of Rorty’s work informs the resulting structure and individual parts of the volume. The introduction concludes with acknowledgments and general remarks about Rorty’s neopragmatism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 149.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As an assistance for the use of the Handbuch reference is made in the brackets to the contributions relevant to the respective topic (in the case of authors with two contributions, indicating the section). All chapters are briefly introduced individually in the introductions to the individual sections of the volume.

  2. 2.

    In neopragmatism, the focus is on language or linguistic practice and no longer, as with the classics of pragmatism Peirce, James, and Dewey, on (experimental) experience. Unfortunately, hardened fronts still exist between the adherents of both “waves” of pragmatism. For a creative proposal of their reconciliation, see Koopman 2009.

  3. 3.

    On the renaissance of pragmatism, see in particular Bernstein 2010 and already Dickstein 1998.

  4. 4.

    This Rorty can be seen at work in Brandom 2000, among others.

  5. 5.

    For a brilliant overview of the different dimensions of Rorty’s neopragmatism, see the contribution by Jeffrey Stout in this volume.

  6. 6.

    Rorty defends the high social utility of natural science and also its exemplary character as a model of communicative solidarity. At the same time, he opposes with vehemence and belligerence its scientistic worship as a kind of Enlightenment version of religion. Thereby it is only tried to inherit the expert authority of the priest by that of the natural scientist, for example, in the figure of the neuroscientist. See on this, among others, Rorty 1991b, pp. 35–39, 1998b, p. 289, 2007, pp. 40, 103.

  7. 7.

    According to Hilary Putnam (1995, p. 21), the complex basic idea of fallibilism without relativism is perhaps the fundamental insight of the pragmatists.

  8. 8.

    For more on the meaning of “romanticism” in Rorty, see Müller 2014a, pp. 109–113.

  9. 9.

    Rorty adapts the notion of “strong poet” from the literary scholar Harold Bloom and expands its meaning (Rorty 1989, pp. 24, 53).

  10. 10.

    This interpretation is developed in Müller 2014a.

  11. 11.

    See, e.g., Schaper 1994. In his project of linguistic self-creation, however, the ironist is dependent on others. Taking this as a starting point, renowned Rorty interpreters try to derive the ethical-political character of irony in Rorty, see, e.g., Bacon 2007; Ramberg 2014; Voparil 2010. At the same time, these three texts each offer an excellent introduction to Rorty and to Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity.

  12. 12.

    The critique of the figure of the liberal ironist has to take into account that it is the product of a contextualist utopian thinking, see Müller 2014b.

  13. 13.

    Support could be provided by practical policy measures alone, such as government concern for security and prosperity (Rorty 1989, p. xiv).

  14. 14.

    On Rorty’s view of the constitutive importance of this level for philosophy as a whole, see also the early text Philosophy as Ethics (Rorty 2020, pp. 13–24).

  15. 15.

    On the relationship to the neutral antifundamentalism of John Rawls’ political liberalism, see Müller 2014, Chap. V.3.

  16. 16.

    Rorty also provokes there with the thesis that Mill’s theory is the “pretty much the last word” to political theory.

  17. 17.

    According to Christopher Voparil (2010, p. 52), it is perhaps this melioristic adherence to social hope even in adverse times that constitutes Rorty’s greatest legacy. On the meliorism of all pragmatists as distinguished from (metaphysical) pessimism and optimism, see esp. Koopman 2009, pp. 16–28.

  18. 18.

    Rorty tirelessly promoted a social democratic politics of reform within liberal democracy. As early as 1997, he warned against neglecting increasing social inequality by limiting oneself to identity politics. This would make the rise of right-wing populism and the election of a “strong man” increasingly likely (Rorty 1998a, pp. 87–88)!

  19. 19.

    Alluding to Karl Marx’s 11th Feuerbach thesis, Rorty emphasizes the primacy of action over contemplation (Rorty 1995, p. 198). With Marx, Rorty is concerned with changing the social world, but unlike Marx, he believes this can be achieved through transformative redescription (of concepts).

  20. 20.

    According to Rorty, the theoretical benefit of his neopragmatism lies in particular in the dismissal of skepticism. Moreover, it makes it possible to finally reconcile our moral self-image with Darwinism (e.g., Rorty 1999, p. 66).

  21. 21.

    See in this regard in particular Rorty 2021.

  22. 22.

    See esp. House 1994. The ironist and humanist Rorty does not shy away from pathetic formulations either: “In the end, […] what matters is our loyalty to other human beings clinging together against the dark, not our hope of getting things right” (Rorty 1982, p. 166). See also Rorty 1991b, p. 205.

  23. 23.

    Rorty has corrected and clarified his position over the years, most notably in discussion with Donald Davidson. To his “mature position” see above all Pragmatism, Davidson and Truth (Rorty 1991b, pp. 126–150).

  24. 24.

    Again and again, reference is made to the casual formulation in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature that truth is not “more than what our peers will, ceteris paribus, let us get away with saying” (Rorty 1979, p. 176). This formulation was one of the provocations from which Rorty (2010c, p. 45) later distanced himself. It is part of his emancipatory project of turning the focus toward our practice of justification.

  25. 25.

    For Rorty, the absoluteness of the concept of truth in contrast to the relative concept of justification does not imply the necessity of a consensus theory that operates with the idea of idealized justification. This way leads again into a metaphysical dead end. On the longstanding “family dispute” between Rorty and his neopragmatist counterparts Hilary Putnam and especially Jürgen Habermas over this question, see Müller 2014, Chap. IV.

  26. 26.

    Michael Bacon rightly points out that this juxtaposition, owed to rhetoric, includes: “Objectivity is solidarity, agreement with one’s peers in the light of our interaction with the world” (Bacon 2007, p. 21, emphasis added).

  27. 27.

    Most prominently Putnam 1992, pp. 18–29. Hilary Putnam and the Relativist Menace (Rorty 1998b, pp. 63–91) can be considered the preliminary culmination and conclusion of the debate between the two pioneers of neopragmatism.

  28. 28.

    In terms of content, Rorty’s ethnocentrism accordingly also places itself in the universalist tradition of its own liberal justificatory community (see above). For the communitarian dimension of Rorty’s thinking see Müller 2019.

  29. 29.

    Bernstein thus pointedly alludes to Rorty’s use of Sellars’s critique of empiricism.

  30. 30.

    On the German-language debate on Rorty and religion, see esp. Reder 2013 and Kleemann 2007.

  31. 31.

    On the motivation and also assessment of this transformative turn, see Müller 2017.

  32. 32.

    According to Rorty, no universal concept of rationality can be reconstructed from language either. For the debate on this with Jürgen Habermas, see Müller 2014a, Chap. IV u. V.2.

  33. 33.

    Bernstein also rightly points out there that Rorty’s own redescription of liberalism in Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, for example, works with arguments, contrary to the announcement there (Rorty 1989, p. 9).

  34. 34.

    This thesis refers primarily to Rorty’s talk there of a “general turn against theory and toward narrative” (Rorty 1989, p. xvi).

  35. 35.

    Rorty’s “pragmatism without method” (Rorty 1991b, p. 63) rejects the idea of a neutral philosophical method across vocabulary boundaries. On this skepticism of method, see, e.g., Rorty 2007, p. 143. On the diagnosis of a kind of methodophobia and hostility to theory in Rorty, see Müller 2014a, pp. 147–148, 555–559.

  36. 36.

    Brandom also points out there the irony that Rorty, as an anti-Kantian, uses a Kantian distinction to undermine representationalism.

  37. 37.

    According to Rorty, it is not realism and anti-realism that confront each other in contemporary philosophy, but atomistic representationalism and holistic anti-representationalism (e.g., Rorty 2007, pp. 134–135, 143). Disregarding his transformative claim, Rorty has been interpreted not only as a representative of idealism, but also of reductive realist naturalism. In this respect, it happens to him like his hero John Dewey.

  38. 38.

    On this criticism, see, e.g., Blackburn 2006, pp. 151–161. There Blackburn also criticizes that the opposition of coping and copying cannot be maintained on closer examination.

  39. 39.

    Again, Rorty has often been misinterpreted; for a first overview, see Erez 2013 and Curtis (2015, pp. 100–112). Not only Curtis, but also other leading Rorty interpreters see here at the same time an important weakness to be corrected (e.g., Bacon 2007, pp. 91–96; Voparil 2010, pp. 37–41).

  40. 40.

    In substance, this insight is already present in Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. There, for example, the importance of socialization is vehemently emphasized (e.g., Rorty 1989, p. 185). Also, the cultural significance of the figure of the strong poet presupposes the connection between the private and the public (e.g., Rorty 1989, pp. 24–26, 37, 1991a, pp. 72, 121).

  41. 41.

    See esp. Janack 2010. This volume also documents that Rorty was the only known representative of the liberal “malestream” to seek dialogue with feminist thinkers himself.

  42. 42.

    Of course, the claim to comprehensive exposition can only be realized approximately. Unfortunately, some contributions did not reach the editor in time or had to be cancelled due to illness of the author.

  43. 43.

    On the history of the misunderstanding between German thought and American pragmatism, see Joas 1992.

  44. 44.

    Richard Bernstein sadly passed away on July 4, 2022.

  45. 45.

    For more about the individual Handbuch sections and the contributions of the volume, see the respective section introductions.

  46. 46.

    My special thanks go to Marianne Janack for her careful proof reading of this English version of the introduction.

References

  • Bacon, Michael. 2007. Richard Rorty. Pragmatism and political liberalism. Lanham: Lexington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, Michael. 2012. Pragmatism. An introduction. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, Richard J. 1987. One step forward, two steps backward: Richard Rorty on liberal democracy and philosophy. Political Theory 15(4): 538–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, Richard J. 2010. The pragmatic turn. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, Richard J. 2016. Ironic life. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, Simon. 2006. Truth: A guide for the perplexed. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bobbio, Noberto. 1989. The great dichotomy: Public/private. In Democracy and dictatorship. The nature and limits of state power, 1–21. Oxford: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boffetti, Jason. 2004. How Richard Rorty found religion. First Things 143(May): 24–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert, ed. 2000. Rorty and his critics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 2000a. Introduction. In Rorty and his critics, ed. Robert Brandom, ix–xx. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 2000b. Vocabularies of pragmatism: Synthesizing naturalism and historicism. In Rorty and his critics, ed. Robert Brandom, 156–182. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curtis, William M. 2015. Defending Rorty. Pragmatism and liberal virtue. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 1984. The quest for certainty. In The later works, 1925–1953: Volume 4: 1929, ed. Jo Ann Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickstein, Morris. 1998. Introduction: Pragmatism then and now. In The revival of pragmatism: New essays on social thought, law, and culture, ed. Morris Dickstein, 1–18. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erez, Lior. 2013. Reconsidering Richard Rorty’s private-public distinction. Humanities 2: 193–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haack, Susan. 2006. Introduction. In Pragmatism, old & new. Selected writings, eds. Susan Haack and Robert Lane, 15–67. Amherst: Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1992. Postmetaphysical thinking: Philosophical essays. Trans. William M. Hohengarten. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1999. Wahrheit und Rechtfertigung. Philosophische Aufsätze. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2003. Truth and justification. Trans. Barbara Fultner. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2008. Richard Rorty und das Entzücken am Schock der Deflationierung. In Ach, Europa. Kleine politische Schriften XI, 15–23. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2009. ‘…And to define America, her athletic Democracy’: In Memory of Richard Rorty. In Europe. The faltering project. Trans. Ciaran Cronin, 3–16. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • House, D. Vaden. 1994. Without god or his doubles: Realism, relativism, and Rorty. Leiden/New York: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • James, William. 1975. Pragmatism: In The works of William James, vol. 1, eds. Frederick H. Burkhardt, Fredson Bowers, and Ignas K. Skruskelis. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janack, Marianne, ed. 2010. Feminist interpretations of Richard Rorty. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joas, Hans. 1992. Amerikanischer Pragmatismus und deutsches Denken. Zur Geschichte eines Mißverständnisses. In Pragmatismus und Gesellschaftstheorie, 114–145. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleemann, Georg M. 2007. Private Götter, öffentlicher Glaube. Richard Rorty und die Religion. Theologie und Philosophie 82(1): 21–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, Colin. 2009. Pragmatism as transition. Historicity and hope in James, Dewey, and Rorty. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Misak, Cheryl. 2013. The American pragmatists. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Martin. 2014a. Private Romantik, öffentlicher Pragmatismus? Richard Rortys transformative Neubeschreibung des Liberalismus. Bielefeldt: transcript.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Martin. 2014b. Richard Rortys Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (1989). Die begründungstheoretische Verbindung von Utopie und Ironie. In Idealstaat oder Gedankenexperiment? Zum Staatsverständnis in den klassischen Utopien, ed. Thomas Schölderle, 287–304. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Martin. 2017. From irony to robust serenity – Pragmatic politics of religion after Rorty. Contemporary Pragmatism 14(3): 334–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Martin. 2019. Richard Rorty und das kommunitarische Denken. In Handbuch Kommunitarismus, ed. Walter Reese-Schäfer, 301–318. Wiesbaden: Springer VS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagl, Ludwig. 2007. Die unerkundete Option: Pragmatistische Denkansätze in der Religionsphilosophie. Anmerkungen zur Habermas’schen Skizze nachkantianischer Religionsbegriffe (Hegel, Schleiermacher, Kierkegaard). In Glauben und Wissen. Ein Symposium mit Jürgen Habermas, eds. Rudolf Langthaler and Herta Nagl-Docekal, 186–215. Wien: Oldenburg/Akademie.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 1992. Realism with a human face, ed. James Conant. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, Hilary. 1995. Pragmatism: An open question. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramberg, Bjørn T. 2000. Rorty und die Werkzeuge der Philosophie. In Die Renaissance des Pragmatismus. Aktuelle Verflechtungen zwischen analytischer und kontinentaler Philosophie, ed. Mike Sandbothe, 127–168. Weilerswist: Velbrück.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramberg, Bjørn T. 2014. Irony’s commitment: Rorty’s Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. The European Legacy. Toward New Paradigms 19(2): 144–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reder, Michael. 2013. Religion in säkularer Gesellschaft. Über die neue Aufmerksamkeit für Religion in der politischen Philosophie. Freiburg: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1961/2014. Pragmatism, categories, and language. In Mind, language, and metaphilosophy: Early philosophical papers, eds. Stephen Leach and James Tartaglia, 16–38. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1982. Consequences of pragmatism. Essays: 1972–1980. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1989. Contingency, irony, and solidarity. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1991a. Essays on Heidegger and others. Philosophical papers. Vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1991b. Objectivity, relativism, and truth. Philosophical papers. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1993. Eine Kultur ohne Zentrum. Vier philosophische Essays. Übers. v. Joachim Schulte. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1995. Philosophy & the future. In Rorty and pragmatism: The philosopher responds to his critics, ed. Hermann J. Saatkamp, Jr., 197–205, 230. Nashville/London: Vanderbilt University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1997. Truth, politics, and “post-modernism”. Spinoza lecture 1: Is it desirable to love truth? Spinoza lecture 2: Is “post-modernism” relevant to politics? Assen: Van Gorcum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1998a. Achieving our country: Leftist thought in twentieth-century America. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1998b. Truth and progress: Philosophical papers. Vol. 3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1999. Philosophy and social hope. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2000. Response to Bjørn Ramberg. In Rorty and his critics, eds. Robert B. Brandom, 370–377. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2004. Philosophy as a transitional Genre. In Pragmatism, critique, judgment: Essays for Richard J. Bernstein, eds. Seyla Benhabib and Nancy Fraser, 3–28. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2005. Anticlericalism and atheism. In Richard Rorty and Gianni Vattimo. The future of religion, ed. Santiago Zabala, 29–41. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2006. Take care of freedom and truth will take care of itself: Interviews with Richard Rorty, ed. Eduardo Mendieta. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2007. Philosophy as cultural politics: Philosophical papers. Vol. 4. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2010a. Intellectual autobiography. In The philosophy of Richard Rorty, eds. Randall E. Auxier and Lewis Edwin Hahn, 3–24. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2010b. Religion in the public square: A reconsideration. In The Rorty reader, eds. Christopher J. Voparil and Richard J. Bernstein, 456–462. Malden/Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2010c. Reply to Cheryl Misak. In The philosophy of Richard Rorty, eds. Randall E. Auxier and Lewis E. Hahn, 44–45. Chicago/La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2011. An ethics for today: Finding common ground between philosophy and religion. Introduction by Gianni Vattimo. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2016. Philosophy as poetry. Introduction by Michael Bérubé. Afterword by Mary V. Rorty. Charlottesville/London: University of Virginia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2020. On philosophy and philosophers. Unpublished papers, 1960–2000, eds. Christopher Voparil and W. P. Malecki. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 2021. Pragmatism as Anti-Authoritarianism (ed. Eduardo Mendieta. Preface by Robert B. Brandom). Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandbothe, Mike. 2000. Die pragmatische Wende des linguistic turn. In Die Renaissance des Pragmatismus. Aktuelle Verflechtungen zwischen analytischer und kontinentaler Philosophie, ed. Mike Sandbothe, 96–126. Weilerswist: Velbrück.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaper, Susanne. 1994. Ironie und Absurdität als philosophische Standpunkte. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talisse, Robert B., and Scott F. Aikin. 2008. Pragmatism. A guide for the perplexed. London/New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tartaglia, James. 2007. Rorty and the mirror of nature. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voparil, Christopher J. 2010. General introduction. In The Rorty reader, eds. Christopher J. Voparil and Richard J. Bernstein, 1–52. Malden/Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Recommended Literature for Further Reading

  • Bacon, Michael. 2007. Richard Rorty. Pragmatism and political liberalism. Lanham: Lexington; the best introduction to Rorty’s thinking and its basic anti-authoritarian motivation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curtis, William M. 2015. Defending Rorty. Pragmatism and liberal virtue. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press; an excellent overview of the major debates and an original interpretation of Rorty as virtue liberal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malachowski, Alan, ed. 2020. A companion to Rorty. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell. The insightful research contributions of leading Rorty interpreters collected here are an excellent addition to this volume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Martin. 2014. Private Romantik, öffentlicher Pragmatismus? Richard Rortys transformative Neubeschreibung des Liberalismus. Bielefeldt: transcript. This comprehensive account of Rorty’s transformative neopragmatism as a combination of romanticism and pragmatism simultaneously applies the pragmatic test to it.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, Martin. 2022. Richard Rorty: A short introduction. Wiesbaden: Springer VS; a brief, albeit systematic introduction that emphasizes the transformative character exemplified by Rorty’s Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramberg, Bjørn T. 2007. Richard Rorty. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rorty. Accessed 29 Nov 2020; a very brief but very thorough overview of Rorty’s life and work.

  • Reese-Schäfer, Walter. 2006. Richard Rorty zur Einführung. Hamburg: Junius; the best German-language introduction to Rorty.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rondel, David, ed. 2021. The Cambridge companion to Richard Rorty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press The contributions of the distinguished authors in Rondel’s companion are also must-reads for Rorty scholars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voparil, Christopher J. 2010. General introduction. In The Rorty reader, ed. Christopher J. Voparil and Richard J. Bernstein, 1–52. Malden/Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. Voparil’s introduction in this standard reader provides an excellent overview of Rorty’s path of thought.

    Google Scholar 

  • Website of the Richard Rorty Society. https://richardrortysociety.org. Accessed 29 Nov 2020. This most important website for Rorty research provides, among other things, event information and valuable links.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden GmbH, ein Teil von Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Müller, M. (2023). General Introduction to the Handbuch Richard Rorty. In: Müller, M. (eds) Handbuch Richard Rorty. Springer VS, Wiesbaden. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-16253-5_80

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-16253-5_80

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer VS, Wiesbaden

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-658-16252-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-658-16253-5

  • eBook Packages: Social Science and Law (German Language)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics