Skip to main content

Between Belief and Disbelief

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Believing in Accordance with the Evidence

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 398))

Abstract

Sometimes instead of believing or disbelieving a proposition one does not take a stand on it. This essay explores that middle ground. We begin by distinguishing a variety of different attitudes or cognitive relations one might have to a proposition that one does not believe or disbelieve. We argue that identifying all of them as suspending judgment or withholding judgment neglects important differences. We then discuss epistemic evaluations of these attitudes and relations. Finally, we examine the implications of our findings for the attitudes that a philosopher might take toward contentious philosophical theses. Evidentialism, our preferred view of epistemic justification, is helpful in clarifying the issues and addressing the problems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See her (2013a, b, c), and (2017).

  2. 2.

    In that work this formulation of evidentialism was referred to as “EJ”.

  3. 3.

    It might seem that one’s evidence could favor a proposition that one is currently unable to grasp. Yet one cannot take any attitude toward such a proposition. In light of that inability it might seem doubtful that belief is justified merely by having supporting evidence. In our view this support cannot occur. Part of any evidence that supports or opposes a proposition for anyone is the content of the proposition. So the person must grasp the proposition to have such evidence.

  4. 4.

    Friedman denies this requirement. She holds that suspending judgment on a proposition is an attitude that is compatible with both believing the proposition and knowing it (2017). Her view as we understand it is that suspending judgment on a proposition is much like wondering whether the proposition is true or being inclined to inquire into its truth. We concur that one can have attitudes like that while believing. For a common sort of example, one can believe a fairly likely proposition while having some such interest in whether it is really true. We do not see, however, that any such attitude toward a proposition’s truth-value is best counted as a suspension of judgment on the proposition. Friedman argues (Sect. 6.3) that inquiring entails suspending judgment. The argument seems unsuccessful. The argument addresses the complaint that her view allows a strange possibilty: inquiring while knowing. The response Friedman gives is that although this is possible, it violates an epistemic norm to the effect that one ought not to inquire into P if one knows P. Friedman suggests that the explanation of why this norm holds includes that inquiring implies suspending judgment. She offers this explanatory function as a reason to accept that inquiring implies suspending judgment. But inquiring’s purported implication of suspending judgment would not explain the negative character of the evaluations of the norm. Why is both knowing and inquiring something one ought not to do? The rest of the explanation would have to cite something that is always bad about the combination of knowing and inquiring. Friedman does not complete the explanation. We do not think that it could be done. The compossibility of knowing and inquiring makes available objections to the norm. One might have good reason to inquire while knowing (and thus to suspend while knowing if suspending were entailed by inquiring). For example, one might inquire further into a known proposition’s truth in order to gain greater confidence, or one might inquire in order to enable one to know that one knows. In any event, suspending as we understand it clearly entails not believing. Believing is judging. If one believes a proposition, then one judges it in an affirmative way. It follows that one has not suspended judgment or withheld judgment. One can do something that is similar to suspending. One can refrain from using the belief in one’s investigation, as though one does not have the belief, in order not to rely on it in the inquiry. But if that is what one does with the proposition, then during the inquiry one believes it. The judgment has been made, not suspended.

  5. 5.

    On the general possibility of justified inconsistent beliefs, see Foley (1979).

  6. 6.

    If your suspending judgment on P2–P4 under the circumstances is taken to be anything more positive than your not adopting an attitude toward P2–P4 – in particular, if suspending is anything like your also having an inquiring frame of mind about them, then your meeting that further condition may be unreasonable and not worthwhile for you, for the same reasons that your believing may be unreasonable and not worthwhile.

  7. 7.

    It is also possible that the availability relation is a natural kind and that our uses of “have” and “available” are causally related to it sufficiently to make reference to it. If there is any such unique relation, though, it is not clear from our current evidence what it is. The reasonable specifications that we make are as close to identifying its extension as our evidence about it currently supports.

  8. 8.

    Of course, intellectual honesty would require acknowledging the objection. But it does not require ceasing to find sufficient plausibility in the proposition to seek support for it and to seek a refutation of the objection.

References

  • Barnett, Z. (forthcoming). Philosophy without belief. Mind.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (1985). Evidentialism. Philosophical Studies, 48, 15–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Afterword. In E. Conee & R. Feldman (Eds.), Evidentialism: Essays in epistemology (pp. 101–107). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1979). Justified inconsistent beliefs. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16, 247–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2013a). Question-directed attitudes. Philosophical Perspectives, 27, 145–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2013b). Rational agnosticism and degrees of belief. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology volume 4 (pp. 57–81). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2013c). Suspended judgment. Philosophical Studies, 162, 165–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, J. (2017). Why suspend judging? Nous, 51, 302–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg, S. (2013). Disagreement, defeat, and assertion. In D. Christensen & J. Lackey (Eds.), The epistemology of disagreement : New essays (pp. 167–189). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2012). A puzzle about withholding. The Philosophical Quarterly, 62, 355–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Earl Conee .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

John Turri (2012) develops an epistemic puzzle. He offers an example in which the subject has no evidence for or against a proposition and yet, Turri argues, withholding judgment is not epistemically justified for the subject. We have been defending the evidentialist view that withholding judgment on a proposition is always epistemically justified for anyone whenever a person grasps a proposition and it is a determinate fact that the person’s evidence supports neither the proposition nor its negation. So we should address Turri’s argument.

Here is an example very much like Turri’s, with a couple of small changes that are intended to strengthen its challenge to our evidentialist view.

P is a mathematical proposition that S understands. S has no evidence for or against P. S is polling 100 people about P, people who S knows to be both mathematicians and epistemologists who have studied the literature on epistemic justification. (We have added to Turri’s example that the polled mathematicians have this epistemological expertise.) S polls the 100 about P as they leave a meeting room in which they have engaged in a discussion of P’s truth value. In answer to S’s inquiry about P each of the 100 tells S that S’s withholding judgment on P is not epistemically justified (We have changed Turri’s example so that the 100 assert that S’s withholding is unjustified, where Turri has them saying that the withholding “is not the thing to do.”) The mathematicians say nothing more to S about either P’s truth value or the justification of any attitude toward P.

It is clear that after S’s polling S still has no evidence for or against P. So in our evidentialist view neither believing nor disbelieving is justified for S. In our view under such circumstances S’s withholding judgment on the proposition is epistemically justified.

Turri argues against the justification of S’s withholding judgment:

I find it difficult to accept that in a case where all the evidence directly indicates that withholding is not the thing to do, withholding is nevertheless the thing to do. We seem to be owed some explanation of why this should be so, especially since it would constitute a dramatic deviation from the effects of expert advice in other cases. Other things being equal, we think we should follow the experts’ advice when they recommend: believing, disbelieving, withholding, not believing, and not disbelieving. Why would not withholding be any different?” (2012, 363)

As a preliminary point we can now explain why we added to the story that the 100 have known epistemological expertise. We did so in order to have S know that their assertions about justification are well informed about both the math and the justification. So S has excellent reason to think that 100 people with ample relevant expertise assert that S’s withholding judgment on P is unjustified. As Turri observes, when experts make judgments within their expertise, our justified response defers to those judgments unless we have some special reason not to do so. Turri asks what the special reason is in this case.

Suppose that S does not have epistemic expertise. In particular, S does not have good reason to think that the experts are mistaken in this case. With this additional supposition of S’s having no independent epistemological evidence, S’s deferring to the 100 experts is quite justified. The justified deference concerns S’s attitude toward the contents of their testimony. That content is what their expertise supports. Their known expert testimony renders S justified in accepting what they tell S. S is justified in believing that S’s withholding judgment on P is not justified.

It does not follow that what the 100 tell S is true. Not only does this not follow, but also the story gives no reason to think that the 100 are right. Turri says that “the evidence directly indicates that withholding is not [justified]” (363). It is important to recognize who receives this indication. The expert testimony indicates to S that S’s withholding is not justified. But the story gives those who consider it no indication that this testimony is correct. The story simply stipulates that the relevantly knowledgeable 100 assert to S that S’s withholding is not justified, without giving any reason to think that these assertions are true. In the story the 100 do not identify anything about S’s withholding judgment that gives those who consider the story reason to think that S’s withholding is unjustified. Nor does the story give us any evidence that the 100 assertions that S’s withholding is unjustified are backed by some good evidence for that evaluation. The story does not provide any new information about what makes withholding justified or unjustified.

Evidentialism gives reason to think that S’s withholding on P is justified. Throughout the story S lacks evidence for or against P. Withholding is the sensible attitude for S, in light of all S has to go on about both the truth value of P and the justification of S’s attitude toward it. S’s evidence does not make any other attitude even a little bit reasonable. Either belief or disbelief would be quite unreasonable for S in light of the equal probability that the proposition has the other truth value and S’s lack of any higher order evidence in favor of either belief or disbelief in particular being justified. Withholding judgment on P is the noncommittal frame of mind that matches this lack of indication. It is fitting; it is justified. So in our view withholding judgment on P is the epistemically justified attitude for S.

Again, we think that in the story S is justified by the expert testimony in believing that the withholding is not justified. Thus our view has it that in this odd sort of case what someone is justified in believing to be the person’s justified attitude toward a proposition conflicts with what the person’s justified attitude actually is. This is unusual but not incoherent. S’s justification for the proposition that S’s withholding is unjustified is misleading expert testimony concerning which the epistemically uninformed S has no competing evidence. What makes it true that withholding judgment on P is justified for S is S’s lack of evidence for or against P. Misleading testimony can justify untrue epistemic beliefs in the presence of conflicting epistemic facts that are not apparent, just as misleading testimonial justification can justify untrue non-epistemic beliefs in the presence of conflicting non-epistemic facts that are not apparent. S does not see the epistemic facts. S’s having justification for believing that S’s withholding is not justified would be some excuse for S if S were to take some other doxastic attitude toward P in order to avoid what S has justification to think would be unjustified withholding. Nevertheless, S’s withholding would be justified.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Feldman, R., Conee, E. (2018). Between Belief and Disbelief. In: McCain, K. (eds) Believing in Accordance with the Evidence. Synthese Library, vol 398. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-95993-1_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics