Skip to main content

Is Economics a Moral Science?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Economic Objects and the Objects of Economics

Part of the book series: Virtues and Economics ((VIEC,volume 3))

Abstract

Economics is a multifaceted inquiry into the social relationship among humans in society. This mutifacetedness creates a lack of communication between critics of economics (which includes a large proportion of philosophers and professors with a religious bent) and defenders of what, for lack of a better term, I will call mainstream economics. The problem is that when critics attack economics, their attack generally focuses on the one-dimensional vision of the social relationship of individuals that is conveyed by the principal texts rather than on a much more sophisticated vision of humans and of social relationships held by good economists. The author fully agrees that morals and science are intertwined in a Putnam sense—the questions one asks and the framework one chooses reflects moral choices. But the paper argues that that as a pragmatic way to move forward, that deeper intertwinement can be usefully separated from less deep, entanglements that are more easily understood and recognized.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I discuss Robbins ’ work in detail in Colander (2009).

  2. 2.

    Whether that sub branch is a science or not depends on the definition of science one is using, and early economists had many different definitions of science. They distinguished pure science from realistic science, and there were many shades of both. Alfred Marshall felt that all economics blended together and chose to call all of economics a science. Others distinguished a science which dealt primarily with logical truisms from broader economic inquiry which they chose to call an art and craft, not a science. I discuss these issues in Colander (1992).

  3. 3.

    Economist’s resolution of these issues goes back to the 1930s when Gunnar Myrdal (1929 Swedish edition; 1932 German edition) pointed out the difficulty of moving from theory to policy. His work was only translated into English in 1952 but it was well known in its German translation. Abram Bergson (1938, 1954) also pointed out that economic analysis needed an externally determined social welfare function to have any possibility of moving from theory to policy implications. Later, Amartya Sen (1970) extended the analysis with social choice theory. It is that work, and the work of their students, to which I refer when I argue that the economics profession has accepted that morals must be integrated into policy analysis. The work of RDG Little (1950) and van Graff (1957) pointed out the difficulties with applying economist’s theoretical model to practice, but that did not affect the belief of economists that they had theoretically solved the problem. The acceptance of the Walrasian general equilibrium model as the basic model for policy pushed all such considerations out of practical economic policy analysis, and the work is hardly discussed in the principles course.

  4. 4.

    An example of what I mean can be found in the debate between Hillary Putnam and Partha DasGupta which I discuss in Su and Colander (2013).

  5. 5.

    Mill (1863) put it this way “The utility standard may be hard to apply, but it is better than having no standard.”

  6. 6.

    This philosophical concept of utility was not something that was designed to be measurable, as some economists later attempted to do with it. It was simply a constructed concept meant to provide moral guidance—to remind policy makers to look at policy from the position of an impartial spectator, not from the point of view of one side or another. That’s why there were two different concepts of utility—one the philosophical concept, utility, utilitarian issues had to be dealt with using a different moral philosophical methodology, not a scientific methodology. (2007)

  7. 7.

    This is a heuristic, not a definitive rule. It accepts that scientific analysis reflects some inseparable moral judgments, but it does the best it can to reduce these as much as it can.

  8. 8.

    For a discussion of how the art of economics was lost, see Colander (1992). See also Colander and Su (2015).

  9. 9.

    I am not arguing that most economists have seriously thought about them about them. Welfare economics and methodology is hardly taught in graduate economic programs and thus most economists have little introduction to it. Like most individuals, economist do what they do, and spend little time thinking about broad questions of methodology.

  10. 10.

    One theoretical economist, Ariel Rubinstein, a well known game theorist, and author of a standard text in graduate microeconomics has been very clear about the need to distinguish the moral dimension to economic policy analysis. He writes: “I would like to start with what I believe every academic should do when appearing in public, especially when speaking about political and controversial issues—to clarify the extent to which he is incorporating his professional knowledge in his remarks, when he is expressing views with the authority supported by academic findings, and what part of his comments are nothing more than his personal thoughts and opinions….to the best of my understanding, economic theory has nothing to say about the heart of the issue under discussion here…Because as an economic theorist, I would like to state that economic theory is exploited in discussion about current economic issues, and I don’t like it…, to put it mildly. Everything that I say here, even in an academic context (and I intentionally use the word “academic” since I do not think that the word “scientific” is appropriate for economics) is completely subjective, controversial and therefore perhaps describes me no less than it describes economic theory” (Rubinstein 2012: 13–14).

  11. 11.

    One specific example of economic pedagogy failing is in its failure to deal with the possibility of endogenous tastes. If tastes are endogenous individual’s utility functions are influenced by the operation of the system. In this case, one cannot take preferences as givens. Without some moral input about what tastes are preferable, one cannot say what policy is desirable. With semi-endogenous tastes the entire textbook economic policy foundation is undermined. This would seem to be an important policy issue. Yet, one sees no discussion of that possibility in the economic principles texts.

References

  • Bentham, J. 1780/1907. An Introduction to Principles of Morals and Legislation. Oxford: Claredon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, A. 1938. A reformulation of certain aspects of welfare economics. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 52 (2): 310–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1954. On the concept of social welfare. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 68 (2): 233–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boulding, K. 1969. Economics as a Moral Science. The American Economic Review 59 (1): 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colander, D. 1992. The lost art of economics. Journal of Economic Perspectives 6 (3).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Edgeworth’s hedonimeter and the quest to measure utility. Journal of Economic Perspectives 21 (2 Spring): 215–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. What was it that Robbins was defining? Journal of the History of Economic Thought 31 (04): 437–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colander, D., and H.-C. Su. 2015. Making sense of Economist’s positive normative distinction. Journal of Economic Methodology 22 (2): 157170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graff, J. de V. 1957. Theoretical Welfare Economics. Cambridge: Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.N. 1891. The scope and method of political economy. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, I.A.M. 1950. A critique of welfare economics. Oxford: Claredon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, A. 1890. Principles of economics. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1848a. On the principles of political economy. London: Longmans Green and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J.S. 1848b. The Principles of Political Economy (1947). Oxford: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1859. On Liberty. London: Longman, Roberts and Green Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1863. Utilitarianism. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2013.

    Google Scholar 

  • Myrdal, G. 1929/1932/1953. The Political Element in Development of Economic Theory, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 2002. The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricardo, D. 1817. On the principles of political economy and taxation. London: John Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, L. 1932. An essay on the nature and significance of economic science. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1938. Live and dead issues in the methodology of economics. Economica, August 5 342–352,

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. Economics and political economy. American Economic Review. May: 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, A. 2012. Economic Fables. Cambridge: Open Book Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 1970. Collective choice and social welfare. Cambridge: Harvard U. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Senior, N.W. 1951/1836. An outline of the science of political economy. New York: Augustus M. Kelly.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidgwick, H. 1883. Principles of political economy. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. 1759. Theory of Moral Sentiments. New york: A.M Kelley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Su, H., and D. Colander. 2013. A failure to communicate: The fact/value divide and the Putnam/Dasgupta debate. Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 6 (2): 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Colander .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Colander, D. (2018). Is Economics a Moral Science?. In: Róna, P., Zsolnai, L. (eds) Economic Objects and the Objects of Economics. Virtues and Economics, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-94529-3_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics