Skip to main content

Modified Fractions, Granularity and Scale Structure

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Semantics of Gradability, Vagueness, and Scale Structure

Part of the book series: Language, Cognition, and Mind ((LCAM,volume 4))

  • 428 Accesses

Abstract

Pragmatic enrichments arising from the use of modified fractions have been little studied, but offer interesting insights into the subtleties of scale structure and granularity. In this chapter I present some new experimental data on the interpretation of these expressions. I argue that these data suggest that modified fractions, like modified integers, give rise to pragmatic enrichments which are conditioned by scale granularity, but that we need to refine the notion of granularity somewhat to extend it to this domain. There is also evidence for enrichments that are not easily captured in classical quantity implicature terms, but which I suggest could be explained by appeal to typicality effects.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    As an anonymous reviewer pointed out, we can also use fractions to quantify over parts of things that are not obviously characterised as “wholes”—for instance, “half a kilogram of…”. The examples in this chapter all concern proportions of a finite quantity, and consequently involve proper fractions (those that lie between 0 and 1). Given that most uses of fractions for quantities above 1 also involve proper fractions, in combination with integers—we usually say “two and a quarter” rather than “nine quarters”—I would expect the observations here to apply to the broader class of fractional expressions of quantity.

  2. 2.

    The International Yard and Pound Agreement of 1959 defines the yard as exactly 0.9144 m, so in fact a mile is exactly 1609.344 m and 125 miles is thus 201,168 m. This latter distance is the first point at which the scale points for mile and metre coincide.

  3. 3.

    This assumption may not always be tenable: if we are talking predominantly about rare events, we might find it more useful to be able to distinguish events occurring with probability 0.001 and probability 0.01 than to be able to distinguish events with probability 0.5 and probability 0.6. However, a simple system of fractions with small denominators would perform very poorly according to this criterion too.

  4. 4.

    For instance, as pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, recipes can rely on thirds and quarters in combination, with quantities such as “1/3 cup” and “1/4 cup” being simultaneously salient.

  5. 5.

    An anonymous reviewer noted that this approach also still relies upon a high level of general numeracy on the part of the participants, with respect to their ability to interpret fractions. Given the relatively small number of outright errors with simple fractions in the following experiments, I would argue that this turned out not to constitute a major concern; however, caution is clearly necessary in interpreting the participants’ pragmatic behaviour with respect to fractions that did elicit a lot of errors (e.g. “more than 6/7” in experiment 1 below).

References

  • Breheny, R. (2008). A new look at the semantics and pragmatics of numerically quantified noun phrases. Journal of Semantics, 25(2), 93–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterworth, B. (1999). The mathematical brain. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1998). Informativeness, relevance, and scalar implicature. In R. Carston & S. Uchida (Eds.), Relevance theory: Applications and implications (pp. 179–236). Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, C. (2012). Modelling implicatures from modified numerals. Lingua, 132, 103–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, C., & Katsos, N. (2010). Comparative and superlative quantifiers: Pragmatic effects of comparison type. Journal of Semantics, 27(3), 271–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, C., Sauerland, U., & Solt, S. (2012). Granularity and scalar implicature in numerical expressions. Linguistics and Philosophy, 35(2), 135–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curtin, P. (1995). Prolegomena to a theory of granularity. MA thesis, University of Texas at Austin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S. (1997). The number sense. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, D., & Hackl, M. (2006). The universal density of measurement. Linguistics and Philosophy, 29(5), 537–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gazdar, G. (1979). Pragmatics: Implicature, presupposition and logical form. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B. (2006). Take ‘five’: The meaning and use of a number word. In S. Vogeleer & L. Tasmowski (Eds.), Non-definiteness and plurality (pp. 311–330). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B., Nouwen, R. (2007). ‘At least’ et al.: The semantics of scalar modifiers. Language, 83(3), 533–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B., & Van Tiel, B. (2013). Embedded scalars. Semantics and Pragmatics, 6(9), 1–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. (1989). A natural history of negation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, C. J. M., & Pollmann, M. M. W. (2001). On round numbers: Pragmatic aspects of numerical expressions. Journal of Quantitative Linguistics, 8(3), 187–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2002). Be brief and vague! And how Bidirectional Optimality Theory allows for verbosity and precision. In D. Restle & D. Zaefferer (Eds.), Sounds and systems: Studies in structure and change, a Festschrift for Theo Vennemann (pp. 439–458). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2009). Approximate interpretations of number words: A case for strategic communication. In E. Hinrichs & J. Nerbonne (Eds.), Theory and evidence in semantics (pp. 109–132). Stanford CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (1999). Pragmatic halos. Language, 75(3), 522–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nouwen, R. (2010). Two kinds of modified numerals. Semantics and Pragmatics, 3(3), 1–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sigurd, B. (1988). Round numbers. Language in Society, 17(2), 243–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solt, S. (2016). On quantification and measurement: The case of ‘most’ and ‘more than half’. Language, 92(1), 65–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chris Cummins .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Cummins, C. (2018). Modified Fractions, Granularity and Scale Structure. In: Castroviejo, E., McNally, L., Weidman Sassoon, G. (eds) The Semantics of Gradability, Vagueness, and Scale Structure. Language, Cognition, and Mind, vol 4. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77791-7_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-77791-7_9

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-77790-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-77791-7

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics