Skip to main content

Richer Than Reduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Building Theories

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 41))

Abstract

There are numerous routes for scientific discovery, many of which involve the use of information from other scientific theories. In particular, searching for possible reductions is widely recognized as one guiding principle for scientific discovery or innovation. However, reduction is only one kind of intertheoretic relation; scientific theories, claims, and proposals can be related in more, and more complex, ways. This chapter proposes that much scientific discovery proceeds through the use of constraints implied by those intertheoretic relationships. The resulting framework is significantly more general than the common reduction-centric focus. As a result, it can explain more prosaic, everyday cases of scientific discovery, as well as scientists’ opportunistic use of many different kinds of scientific information. I illustrate the framework using three case studies from cognitive science, and conclude by exploring the potential limits of analyses of scientific discovery via constraints.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Readers who are skeptical about notions of ‘truth’ with regards to scientific theories should instead substitute ‘accurate’ or ‘approximately true’ or whatever notion they prefer.

  2. 2.

    For space reasons, I only summarize my account of intertheoretic constraints here. More details and discussion can be found in Danks 2013 or Chap. 2 of Danks 2014.

  3. 3.

    As an aside, notice that this alternative-dependence implies that the particular constraints that scientists entertain can depend on contingent historical facts about the science (that influence the set of alternatives considered), even though the existence and nature of those constraints are not history-dependent.

  4. 4.

    Again, readers should freely substitute their preferred term for ‘truth’, such as ‘accuracy’ or ‘approximate truth’.

  5. 5.

    This goal-dependence does not necessarily imply some sort of goal-dependent pragmatism or perspectivism (though I do also endorse that; see, e.g., Danks 2015). Rather, this dependence is just a generalization of the old reductionist observation that two theories could stand in a reduction relation without thereby constraining one another’s explanations in any interesting or informative way (e.g., Putnam 1975).

  6. 6.

    As a matter of historical interest, these were the three main types of theories of causal structure representation being proposed in cognitive science in the early 2000s.

  7. 7.

    One might object that they could be tunable, if we understood “environment” in an appropriately broad and rich way. The problem is that this move makes the mappings essentially unlearnable, as every experience now involves a unique, never-before-seen environment.

  8. 8.

    A framework for characterizing and modeling this dynamics represents another extension of the constraint-inclusion model of Laudan, Nickles, and others.

  9. 9.

    Thanks to Donald Gillies for encouraging me to consider this possibility, even after I had initially dismissed it.

  10. 10.

    That being said, creativity could perhaps be modeled as discovery via constraints in the following way: suppose creativity results, as some have suggested (e.g., Simonton 1999), from profligate, unguided idea generation, followed by thoughtful pruning of the outputs. This pruning process could potentially be based on the use of constraints, and so we have the beginnings of a picture in which all discovery is based on constraints. Of course, this proposal does not explain the “idea generator,” and much more work would need to be done before we have a full story in terms of constraints. Nonetheless, it is suggestive that even the “singular creative act” might be captured by this framework.

References

  • Barsalou, L. W. (2008). Grounded cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 617–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (2000). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1985). Reduction, qualia, and the direct introspection of brain states. Journal of Philosophy, 82, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danks, D. (2013). Moving from levels & reduction to dimensions & constraints. In M. Knauff, M. Pauen, N. Sebanz, & I. Wachsmuth (Eds.), Proceedings of the 35th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 2124–2129). Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danks, D. (2014). Unifying the mind: Cognitive representations as graphical models. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danks, D. (2015). Goal-dependence in (scientific) ontology. Synthese, 192, 3601–3616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2002). Strategies for discovering mechanisms: Schema instantiation, modular subassembly, forward/backward chaining. Philosophy of Science, 69(S3), S354–S365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2002). Strategies in the interfield discovery of the mechanism of protein synthesis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33(1), 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeSchepper, B., & Treisman, A. (1996). Visual memory for novel shapes: Implicit coding without attention. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 22, 27–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Desimone, R., & Duncan, J. (1995). Neural mechanisms of selective visual attention. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 18, 193–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dizadji-Bahmani, F., Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2010). Who’s afraid of Nagelian reduction? Erkenntnis, 73, 393–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences: Or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis. Synthese, 28, 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1997). Special sciences: Still autonomous after all these years. Nous, 31, 149–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, T. L., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2005). Structure and strength in causal induction. Cognitive Psychology, 51(4), 334–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hadjichristidis, C., Sloman, S., Stevenson, R., & Over, D. (2004). Feature centrality and property induction. Cognitive Science, 28, 45–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagmayer, Y., & Sloman, S. A. (2009). Decision makers conceive of their choices as interventions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 138, 22–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagmayer, Y., Meder, B., Osman, M., Mangold, S., & Lagnado, D. A. (2010). Spontaneous causal learning while controlling a dynamic system. The Open Psychology Journal, 3, 145–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M. (1998). Causal asymmetries. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, C. A. (1981a). Towards a general theory of reduction, part I: Historical and scientific setting. Dialogue, 20, 38–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, C. A. (1981b). Towards a general theory of reduction, part II: Identity in reduction. Dialogue, 20, 201–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, L., & Pashler, H. (2007). Working memory and the guidance of visual attention: Consonance-driven orienting. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 14, 148–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C. (1989). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A problem solving approach to scientific progress. In I. Hacking (Ed.), Scientific revolutions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2009). Doing without concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maruff, P., Danckert, J., Camplin, G., & Currie, J. (1999). Behavioural goals constrain the selection of visual information. Psychological Science, 10, 522–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, G. L. (2004). The big book of concepts. Cambridge, MA: Bradford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science: Problems in the logic of scientific explanation. New York: Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1978). Scientific problems and constraints. In PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (pp. 134–148). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1981). What is a problem that we may solve it? Synthese, 47, 85–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickles, T. (1988). Questioning and problems in philosophy of science: Problem-solving versus directly truth-seeking epistemologies. In M. Meyer (Ed.), Questions and questioning (pp. 43–67). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, J. M. (1987). A model for stimulus generalization in Pavlovian conditioning. Psychological Review, 94(1), 61–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophy and our mental life. In Mind, language, and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 291–303). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rehder, B. (2003a). A causal-model theory of conceptual representation and categorization. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, & Cognition, 29, 1141–1159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rehder, B. (2003b). Categorization as causal reasoning. Cognitive Science, 27, 709–748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rehder, B. (2009). Causal-based property generalization. Cognitive Science, 33, 301–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rehder, B., & Kim, S. (2010). Causal status and coherence in causal-based categorization. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, & Cognition, 36(5), 1171–1206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla, R. A., & Wagner, A. R. (1972). A theory of Pavlovian conditioning: Variations in the effectiveness of reinforcement and nonreinforcement. In A. H. Black & W. F. Prokasy (Eds.), Classical conditioning II: Current research and theory (pp. 64–99). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rovee, C. K., & Rovee, D. T. (1969). Conjugate reinforcement of infant exploratory behavior. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 8, 33–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schouten, M. K. D., & de Jong, H. L. (Eds.). (2012). The matter of the mind: Philosophical essays on psychology, neuroscience and reduction. London: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, D. R. (1995). Is human learning rational? The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 48A, 257–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simonton, D. K. (1999). Origins of genius: Darwinian perspectives on creativity. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloman, S. A. (2005). Causal models: How people think about the world and its alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Timberlake, W. (2001). Integrating niche-related and general process approaches in the study of learning. Behavioural Processes, 54, 79–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tipper, S. P., Weaver, B., & Houghton, G. (1994). Behavioural goals determine inhibitory mechanisms of selective attention. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Experimental Psychology, 47, 809–840.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellen, S., & Danks, D. (2014). Learning with a purpose: The influence of goals. In P. Bello, M. Guarini, M. McShane, & B. Scassellati (Eds.), Proceedings of the 36th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1766–1771). Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1980). Reductionistic research strategies and their biases in the units of selection controversy. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Scientific discovery: Case studies (pp. 213–259). D. Reidel Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The ideas in this paper were initially presented at the “Building Theories: Hypotheses & Heuristics in Science” conference at Sapienza University. Thanks to the audience at the conference for their comments and criticisms, particular Emiliano Ippoliti, Lindley Darden, Donald Gillies, and Margie Morrison. Thanks also to two anonymous reviewers for valuable feedback on an earlier draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Danks .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Danks, D. (2018). Richer Than Reduction. In: Danks, D., Ippoliti, E. (eds) Building Theories. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 41. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72787-5_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics