Skip to main content

The “Ought”-Dimension in Value Theory: The Concept of the Desirable in John Dewey’s Definition of Value and Its Significance for the Social Sciences

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 9))

Abstract

The concept of “value” is widely used in various fields, and it has recently become the subject of empirical research. However, there is no common understanding of what it is. From the very start, the scope of value has been part of the opposition of what “is” to what “ought to be,” and the fact that value judgments contained a normative element seemed to make the exclusion of value from the area of scientific analysis inevitable. John Dewey offers a different way of reasoning about values, which would allow scientists to keep the normativity in a way of saving the specificity of the concept. In order to do this, Dewey links the source of value with the evaluation process and introduces the concept of the “desirable” drawing the line between the “desirable” and the “desired”. Clyde Kluckhohn later borrowed this concept from Dewey, while formulating the concept of values within Parsons’ theory of action. Thanks to him, the “desirable” has become a favorite part of value definition among different researchers. As a result of this development, the concept of “desirability” has been transformed: for example, in social psychology, the “desirable” has moved closer to the “important”, and the significance of the normative aspect has diminished, evolving to a more descriptive understanding, while the social dimension, though present already in Dewey, has greatly increased.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    One of the most famous attempts was made by John Searle; see (Searle 1964).

  2. 2.

    A close connection between value and norm can also be proved by their inclusion in one and the same encyclopedia article: (Marini 2000, pp. 2828–2840). The correlation of the evaluative and normative is a separate topic; although both have the meaning of should, they are of dramatically different characters (e.g. see: Marini 2000, 2829–2830; Habermas 1992).

  3. 3.

    See C. Ehrenfels’s understanding of value as “being desired” (Begehrbarkeit) (Ehrenfels 1897, 53) or R.B Perry’s view on value as “any object of any interest” (Perry 1950, 115).

  4. 4.

    Dewey has several works on values (Dewey 1929, 1949, 1972); in this article I will stick to the latest one (Theory of valuation, 1939).

  5. 5.

    Including social conditions (Dewey 1972, 32).

  6. 6.

    Meaning the ten purposes realized in the ten types of values which serve to handle “three universal requirements of human existence”, namely, “needs of individuals as biological organisms, requisites of coordinated social interaction, and survival and welfare needs of groups” (Schwartz 2012, 4).

  7. 7.

    See the categories of hedonism and power (Schwartz 2012, 56–60): here we can hardly imagine a conflict between the desired and the desirable in the form of “I do not want to, but I will”.

  8. 8.

    Or vice versa: “I ought not to do X” can be interpreted as “I probably want X. But if I do X, Y will happen, and I do not want Y”.

  9. 9.

    One can say, “this position is highly desirable” (i.e. “Everyone wants this position”), and “it is desirable to distinguish between these concepts” (i.e. “one needs/ought to/should distinguish between these concepts”).

  10. 10.

    E.g. the dictionary definition of desirable refers to worth, while the latter is defined through value (see e.g. Oxford English Dictionary).

  11. 11.

    “At any given time an adult person in a social group has certain ends which are so standardized by custom that they are taken for granted without examination, so that the only problems arising concern the best means for attaining them” (Dewey 1972, 43).

  12. 12.

    “By institutionalization value is part of the situation” (Kluckhohn 1962, 410).

  13. 13.

    Actually, John Searle’s criticism of the fact-value opposition is also based upon the existence of social institutions.

References

  • Ayer, A.J. 1983. Language, truth and logic. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, M.W. 1956, September. An expansion of Dewey’s groundwork for a general theory of value. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 15 (1): 100–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darity, W.A., ed. 2008. International encyclopedia of the social sciences. Vol. 8. 2nd ed. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. 1929. Experience and nature. The Paul Carus lectures. London: Geroge Allen & Unwin, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1949. The field of value. In Value: A cooperative inquiry, ed. R. Lepley. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1972. Theory of valuation. In International encyclopedia of unified science: Foundations of the unity of science, 2, 4. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrenfels, Ch. von. 1897. System der Werttheorie. Vol. 1. Leipzig: O.R. Reisland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 1992. Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitlin, S., and J.A. Piliavin. 2004, August. Values: Reviving a dormant concept. Annual Review of Sociology 30: 359–393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hügli, A. 2004. Wert. In Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, Völlig neubearb. Ausg. des “Wörterbuchs der philosophischen Begriffe” von Rudolf Eisler., 12: W-Z:1556. Basel: Schwabe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joas, H. 2000. The genesis of values. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kilby, R.W. 1993. The study of human values. Lanham/New York/London: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kluckhohn, C. 1962. Values and value-orientations in the theory of action: An exploration in definition and classification. In Toward a general theory of action, ed. T. Parsons and E. Shils, 388–433. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krobath, H.T. 2009. Werte: Ein Streifzug durch Philosophie und Wissenschaft. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lautmann, R. 1969. Wert und Norm: Begriffsanalysen für die Soziologie. Köln und Opladen: Westdeitscher Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marini, M.M. 2000. Social values and norms. In Encyclopedia of sociology. 2nd ed. 4: 2828–2840. New York: Macmillan Reference USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T., and E. Shils, eds. 1962. Toward a general theory of action. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, R.B. 1950. General theory of value: Its meaning and basic principles construed in terms of interest. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1981. Reason, truth, and history. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. The collapse of the fact/value dichotomy and other essays: [Including the Rosenthal Lectures]/Hilary Putnam. 3. Print. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rickert, H. 1915. Der Gegenstand der Erkenntnis. Einführung in die Transzendentalphilosophie. Tübingen: JCB Mohr (Paul Siebeck).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohan, M.J. 2000. A rose by any name? The values construct. Personality and Social Psychology Review 4 (3): 255–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. 1982. Consequences of pragmatism: Essays, 1972–1980. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, S.H. 1992, December 1. Universals in the content and structure of values: Theoretical advances and empirical tests in 20 countries. In Advances in experimental social psychology 25: 1–65. Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999, January. A theory of cultural values and some implications for work. Applied Psychology 48 (1): 23–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012, December 1. An overview of the Schwartz theory of basic values. Online Readings in Psychology and Culture 2 (1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1964, January. How to derive ‘ought’ from ‘is’. The Philosophical Review 73 (1): 43–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spates, J.L. 1983. The sociology of values. Annual Review of Sociology 9: 27–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elizaveta Kostrova .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Kostrova, E. (2018). The “Ought”-Dimension in Value Theory: The Concept of the Desirable in John Dewey’s Definition of Value and Its Significance for the Social Sciences. In: Christian, A., Hommen, D., Retzlaff, N., Schurz, G. (eds) Philosophy of Science. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72577-2_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics