Skip to main content

Antinomies of Measure. Phenomenology and Spatial Continuity (Husserl, Becker, Weyl)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Changing Faces of Space

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 39))

  • 356 Accesses

Abstract

What is the role and the significance of the continuity in the phenomenology of spatiality? And what is the function of spatial continuity in a phenomenological epistemology? Under the title of continuity falls one of the greatest apories of phenomenology and one of the greatest achievements of the phenomenological epistemology (metric continuum formulated by Hermann Weyl) . Moving from these premises, the essay will face up to the following issues:

  1. 1.

    The determination of geometrical subjectivity, that is the definition of the 0-point of consciousness and the corresponding modal (dimensions) and relational (distances) field;

  2. 2.

    The definition of metric space as:

    1. 2.1.

      the elementary operation of the proportioning between 0 (consciousness) and counter-0 (mode and spatial relations);

    2. 2.2.

      the middle-level between the composition of sensible fields and the formalization of geometrical-physical space;

    3. 2.3.

      the result of the nullification of egoity and the constant of correlation between the electromagnetic field and gravitational field ;

  3. 3.

    The definition of contingent a priori as:

    1. 3.1.

      the character of incomplete formalization of Euclidian geometry;

    2. 3.2.

      the occasional nature of the elements (e.g.: extension and color) between which there is material-apriorical relationship (e.g.: non-independence);

    3. 3.3.

      the projection, through continuum or sequence of integers, of the actually given upon the background of a priori possible;

  4. 4.

    The definition of limes as:

    1. 4.1.

      the empirical-ideal determination of magnitude, interval or correlation;

    2. 4.2.

      the feature, first topological and then metrical, of the sensible spatial fields;

      1. 4.2.1.

        then the essential element for the overlay and the coincidence of the sensible fields;

    3. 4.3.

      the reflexive presupposition of measurement.

Once it has been so proven that the same metrics is the contingent a priori of spatiality, and of its possible continuization, the final objective of the essay is to prepare the ground for the analysis of the central and most problematic point of natural phenomenology, the theme that has sanctioned its failure and irrelevance, that is: the relationship between space and matter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On the oscillation which in this respect is present in Kantian readings see at least Scaravelli (1973: 3–189), Cohen (1883: 56–63, 164–198), Friedmann (1985: 467 ff).

  2. 2.

    Cfr. Riemann (1868: 653–654, 71–123), Pettoello (1986).

  3. 3.

    Cfr. Putnam (1995), Zalamea (2012).

  4. 4.

    Cfr. Hirsch (1982), Sider (1997), Casati and Varzi (1999).

  5. 5.

    Husserl defines the transcendence in immanence in this manner also in Husserl (1973a: 170).

  6. 6.

    Cfr. Becker (1923: 544).

  7. 7.

    Cfr. Kerszberg (1986), Kerszberg (2007).

  8. 8.

    The second side of the pair evidently refers to the solution formulated by Weierstrass, regarding the exclusion of infinitesimals in determining the continuum, which constitutes for Husserl not so much a decisive acquisition of his formation, as one of aspects of the mathematical heritage that is most present in his philosophical reflection. In formal terms, in the first case one obtains the limit of a sequence, such that n1, n2, n3… tends infinitarily to (→) nn, in the second the limit of a function, f(x), which can be formulated as follows: “if, given an ε, there is an η0, such that, for 0 < η < η0, the difference f(x0 ± η) − L is less in absolute value than η, then L is the limit of f(x), for x = x0” (Heine 1872: 184); or in an extremely simplified manner: “the number 1/3 is not the limit of the series 3/10 + 3/100 + 3/1000··· +3/+ 10n +···; but it is the sequence associated with this series” (Boyer 1968: 606).

  9. 9.

    That the understanding of the limit is phenomenologically exposed to this dual possibility is amply demonstrated by the divarication that separates the treatments conducted in that regard by two of the students of Husserl who most contributed to the maturing of Phänomenologie der Wahrnehmung, that is, Schapp (1910: 149–157), on the ideality of the limit, and Hofman (1912: esp. 60), on the concept-limit of the “visual perceivable thing”, (1912: 62–67), on the measure of a visual magnitude, and (1912: 101–103), on spatial limits.

  10. 10.

    Cfr. Husserl (1983: LXVII); on the subsequent exchange of letters between Becker-Mahnke-Weyl, see Mancosu (2010: esp. 256–357). On the main lines of Husserl’s phenomenology of nature, see Rang (1990).

  11. 11.

    Conrad-Martius (1923: 204–225). Cfr. Conrad-Martius (1958: 75 and 191).

  12. 12.

    Bergson (1889: 111, 112), Bergson (1922: 53), cfr. Ingarden (1922: esp. 291–295, 300, 354–365). Cfr. Zanfi (2013: 183–192).

  13. 13.

    It does not seem rash to grasp even in this use of apeiron—in which culminates Koyré’s regression to the Zenonian paradoxes more than ten years after Husserl’s rejection of his project for the doctoral dissertation (Koyré 1999)—a testimony of his by now mature separation from his Gottingen master; in this regard, see Zambelli (1999). Husserl’s interest in resolving the link between Mengenlehre and apeiron—demonstrated by the manuscripts Ms. A I 35 (Menge. Die Paradoxien. Die Insolubilia. Insbesondere auch die Paradoxien der Mengenlehre, 1912), pp. 4 et seq., and Ms. A III 12 (Morphologische Realität gegenüber der physikalischen. Das organische Individuum. (1) Die formale Logik des Apeiron, der Apophantik. (2) Formal Logik der Kontinuität, 1926)—is widely reflected in the pages of the Jahrbuch; see esp. volume VI, in which appear London (1923) and Lipps (1923). Cfr. Peckhaus (1990).

  14. 14.

    On the return of apeiron in the history of phenomenology, see Heidegger (1946), Heidegger (1991: esp. 109–113), Fink (19571960), Levinas (1961: esp. 163 f.), Derrida (1962: 48 and 151), Derrida (1967: esp. 142), which, betraying as much the archaic Anaximandrean meaning as the later Platonic one, makes of the non-limit the unity that saves from the limit—Plato, Philebus, 24 a3: “tò àpeiron pollà esti”.

  15. 15.

    On the issue of the tode ti, first addressed in Husserl (1913: 33–34), see also Husserl (2001b: 299–309), and Husserl (2012: 147. Text n. 11, 1918).

  16. 16.

    Husserl (1966: in particular 319–324). Cfr. Costa (1999: 86 ff.), Lohmar (1998: 171 ff.).

  17. 17.

    Husserl (2005a: 183). Cfr. Husserl (1973c: 265–266, 267–268, 269–272).

  18. 18.

    On Meinong (1903), Wittgenstein (1976: § 80) and Wittgenstein (1991: I, § 66; II, § 86), see Mulligan (1991). See also, on metrics, Meinong (1896: esp. 5–23, 59–77). As to the position of the Graz School on the definition of continua, see Brentano (1976), Marty (1916). Cfr. Albertazzi (1992).

  19. 19.

    Husserl (1974a : 32–34). The contingent a priori renders the essential orientation of occasional expressions already, first in the deictic and then in the adverbial determination of the place and then in scientific praxis, cfr. Husserl (1922: 86, 87). On the link between the contingent a priori of the science of space and the facticity of nature, cfr. Husserl (1973c: 287–290). On the phenomenological notion of contingency, see Pöggeler (1986: esp. 17).

  20. 20.

    On the relationship between metric and contingent a priori, see, for the geometric side, Volkert (1994: 271), and for the linguistic-ontological side, see Kripke (1980: esp. 55 ff.) For an acute analysis of the measure-measurement plexus see, beyond the classic (Helmholtz 1887; Nagel 1931; Kuhn 1961; Sokolowski 1987).

  21. 21.

    It is precisely Becker’s taking up (1927: 317), of the apeiron and its omnitemporal character as aei, that leads us from the analysis of the symbolic-transcendent transfinity to a metaphysics of contingency, to a metaphysics of that transcendent “(relatively) close to us and therefore accessible to a ‘divining interpretation’ (“Deutung”)”, that is, nature (Becker 1927: 328). Cfr. Peckhaus (2005).

  22. 22.

    Husserl (1974a, b: 93–102). Cfr. Ortiz Hill (1997: 145–170).

  23. 23.

    On Cantor’s role in Husserl’s formation, and particularly in the decision of harking back in ideal-realistic fashion to Platonism as capable of throwing light precisely on the relationship between “sense and type of mathematical knowledge,” cfr. Schuhmann (1977: 19 and 26). A much broader question, to which we shall only make passing reference, is that of Cantor’s influence on Husserl’s philosophical vocabulary, which is documented, besides in the rigorous distinction between stetig and kontinuerlich (Cantor 1883: 903, 919) and the use of immanent-transient (Cantor 1883: 895–896; Husserl 1966: 291, 300), above all in the reversal of the coupling reel and real in Husserl (1922: 411, 632, 633), compared to Cantor (1883: 882).

Abbreviations

Hua::

Husserliana Gesammelte Werke, Den Haag/Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster, M. Nijhoff, and, from vol. XXVII, Dordrecht/Boston/London, Kluwer.

References

  • Albertazzi, L. (Ed.). (1992). Unfolding perceptual continua. Amsterdam-Philadelphia, John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, O. (1923). Bemerkungen zur phänomenologischen Begründung der Geometrie und ihre physikalischen Anwendungen. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, VI, 385–560.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, O. (1927). Mathematische Existenz. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, VIII, 441–809.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1889). Time and free will. An essay on the immediate data of consciousness (Engl. ed. by F. L. Pogson). New York: Dover Publications (2001).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1922). Duration and simultaneity (Engl. ed. by L. Jacobson). The Bobbs-Merrill Company (1965).

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, C. B. (1968). A history of mathematics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1976). Raum, Zeit, Kontinuum. hrsg. von S. Kröner- R. M. Chisholm. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantor, G. (1883). Foundations of a general theory of manifolds: A mathematico-philosophical investigation into the theory of infinite (Engl. ed. by W. Ewald), in Id., From Kant to Hilbert, II. Oxford: Clarendon Press (pp. 878–920) (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1923). Realontologie. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, VI, 159–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. (1958). Der Raum. München: Kösel-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casati, R., & Varzi, A. (1999). Parts and places. The structures of spatial representation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, H. (1883). Das Princip der Infinitesimal-Methode und seine Geschichte. Berlin: Dümmler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Costa, V. (1999). Estetica trascendentale fenomenologica. Sensibilità e razionalità nella filosofia di Edmund Husserl. Milan: Vita e Pensiero.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1962). Edmund Husserl’s origin of geometry: An introduction (Engl. ed. by J. P. Leavey). Lincoln and London: University of Nebraska Press (1989).

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1967). Violence and metaphysics: An essay on the thought of E. Levinas. In Id., Writing and difference (Engl. ed. by. A. Bass). Routledge, London-New York (pp. 97–192) (2001).

    Google Scholar 

  • Duval, R. (1990). Durée ou discontinuité de l’apparaître: le choix phénoménologique. In S. Ijsselin1g (Ed.), Husserl-Ausgabe und Husserl-Forschung (pp. 81–106). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fink, E. (1957). Nachdenkliches zur ontologischen Frühgeschichte von Raum – Zeit – Bewegung. Den Haag, M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fink, E. (1960): Nietzsche’s philosophy (Engl. ed. by G. Richter). London-New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1985). Kant’s theory of geometry. The Philosophical Review, 44(4), 455–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1946). Der Spruch des Anaximander. In Id., Holzwege (1950), GA, Bd. 5, hrsg. von F.-W. von Herrmann, Frankfurt a. M: Klostermann, pp. 321–373 (1977).

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1991). Grundbegriffe (1941), GA, Bd. 51, hrsg. von P. Jaeger. Frankfurt a. M.: Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heine, E. (1872). Die Elemente der Functionenlehre. Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 74, 172–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. (1887). Numbering and measuring from epistemological viewpoint (Engl. ed. by W. Ewald). In Id., From Kant to Hilbert, II (pp. 727–752). Oxford: Clarendon Press (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  • Herbart, J. F. (1829). Allgemeine Metaphysik nebst den Anfängen der philosophischen Naturlehre. In Id., Sämtliche Werke (Ed.), vol. VIII, hrsg. von K. Kehrbach-O. Flügel, Neudruck der Ausgabe, Legensalza 1893, Scientia, Aalen 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. (1982). The concept of identity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann, H. (1912). Untersuchungen über Empfindungsbegriff. Archiv für Psychologie, XXVI, 1–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1911). Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft. In Id., Aufsätze und Vorträge (1911–1921), Hua XXV (pp. 3–62).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1913): Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie, Hua III/1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1922). Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band, Hua XIX/1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1966). Zur Auflösung des Schemas Auffasungsinhalt-Auffasung. In Id., Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins, Hua X (pp. 269–334).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973a). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Zweiter Teil (1921–1928). Hua XIV.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973b). Der Widersinn des transzendentalen Realismus. Gegen den Einwand des Solipsismus (1924), Text nr. 17, in Hua XIV (pp. 341–356).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973c). Ding und Raum. Vorlesungen 1907, Hua XVI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1974a). Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft (1929), Hua XVII.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1974b). Das ideale Erkenntnissubjekt der formalen Logik und die formale Apriorität rein rationaler Gegenstände. Kontingent-Materiales und formales Apriori (1920/21), Ergänzender Text V, in Hua XVII, pp. 379–393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1983). Versuch über der Raum, in Hua XXI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1984a). Einleitung in die Logik und Erkenntnistheorie. Vorlesungen 1906/07, Hua XXIV.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1984b). Fours letters from Edmund Husserl to Hermann Weyl (ed. by D. van Dalen). Husserl Studies, 1, 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1986). Aufsätze und Vorträge (1911–1921), Hua XXV.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001a). Natur und Geist. Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1927, Hua XXXI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001b). Die Bernauer Manuskripte über das Zeitbewusstsein (1917/18), Hua XXXII.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2003). Der formal allgemeine Beweis des transzendentalen Idealismus und die Undenkbarkeit von realem Sein ohne leibliche Subjektivität. Wesentliche Beziehung der Weltkonstitution zu einer offenen Vielheit von Subjekten. Geburt und Tod jedes Subjekts als apriorische Notwendigkeiten (1914–15), Text nr. 7, in Hua XXXVI (pp. 132–145).

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2005a). Einführung in die Phänomenologie der Erkenntnis (1909), Hua, Materialen, VII.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2005b). Logische Untersuchungen. Ergänzungsband. Zweiter Teil. Texte für Neufassung der VI. Untersuchung. Zur Phänomenologie des Ausdrucks und der Erkenntnis (1893/94–1921), Hua XX/2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2009). Untersuchungen über Urteilstheorie (1893–1918), Hua XL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2009a). Uneigentliche Affirmationen (1893/94), in Hua XL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2009b). Urteile verschiedener Art aufgrund der blosse Vorstellung (1908), Text nr. 17, in Hua XL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2009c). Empirische und apriorische Aussagen über das erscheinende Ding (1908), Text nr. 19, in Hua XL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2012). Zur Lehre vom Wesen und zur Methode der eidetischen Variation (1891–1935). Hua XLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1922). Intuition und Intellekt bei Henri Bergson. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, V, 286–461.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1787). Kritik der reinen Vernunft, hrsg. von J. Timmermann-H. Klemme. Hamburg: Meiner (1956).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerszberg, P. (1986). Le principe de Weyl et l’invention d’una cosmologie non-statique. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 35(1), pp. 1–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerzsberg, P. (2007). Perseverance and adjustment: On Weyl’s phenomenological philosophy of nature. In L. Boi, P. Kerszberg, & F. Patras (Eds.), Rediscovering Phenomenology. Phenomenological essays on mathematical beings, physical reality, perception and consciousness (pp. 173–194). Dordrecht: Spinger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré, A. (1922). Bemerkungen zu den zenonischen Paradoxen. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, V, 603–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyré, A. (1999). Insolubilia. Eine logische Studie über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre, hrsg. von P. Zambelli. Giornale critico della filosofia italiana, VI/18, 303–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1961). The function of measurement in modern physical science. Isis, 52(2), 61–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1961). Totality and infinity. An essay on exteriority (Engl. ed. by A. Lingis). Pittsburgh : Duquesne University Press (1969, 200720).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipps, H. (1923). Die Paradoxien der Mengenlehre. Jahrbuch für Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Forschung, VI, 561–571.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lohmar, D. (1998). Erfahrung und kategoriales Denken. Hume, Kant und Husserl über vorprädikative Erfahrung und prädikative Erkenntnis. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • London, F. (1923). Über die Bedingungen der Möglichkeit einer deduktiven Theorie. Jahrbuch für Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Forschung, VI, 335–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (2010). The adventure of reason. Interplay between philosophy of mathematics and mathematical logic, 1900–1940. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marty, A. (1916). Raum und Zeit, hrsg. von J. Eisenmeier, A. Kastil, O. Kraus, Halle, Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1896). Über die Bedeutung des Weber’schen Gesetzes. Beiträge zur Psychologie der Vergleichens und Messens. Leopold Voss: Hamburg-Leipzig.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1903). Bemerkungen über den Farbenkörper und das Mischungsgesetz. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, 33, 1–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, K. (1991). Colors, corners and complexity; Mejnong & Wittgenstein on some internal relations. In B. C. van Fraassen et alii (Eds.), Existence and explanation: Essays in Honor of Karel Lambert (pp. 77–101). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1931). Measurement. Erkenntnis, 2, 313–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ortiz Hill, C. (1997). Did Georg Cantor influence Edmund Husserl? Synthese, 113(1), 145–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peckhaus, V. (1990). Hilbertprogramm und Kritische Philosophie. Das Göttinger Modell interdisziplinär Zusammenarbeit zwischen Mathematik und Philosophie. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peckhaus V. (Ed.). (2005). Oskar Becker und die Philosophie der Mathematik. München: Wilhelm Fink Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1898). The logic of continuity. In Id., K. L. Ketner (Ed.), Reasoning and the logic of things. The Cambridge Conferences Lectures of 1898 (pp. 242–268). Harvard University Press, Cambridge-London (1992).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettoello, R. (1986). Idealismo e Realismo. La formazione filosofica di J. F. Herbart. Florence: La Nuova Italia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pöggeler, O. (1986). Kontingenz und Rationalität in der phänomenologischen Wissenschaftstheorie. In Aa. Vv., Vernunft und Kontingenz. Rationalität und Ethos in der Phänomenologie (Phänomenologische Forschungen, 19) (pp. 10–37).

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1995). Peirce’s Continuum. In K. L. Ketner (Ed.), Peirce and contemporary thought: Philosophical inquiries (pp. 356–365). New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rang, B. (1990). Phänomenologie der materiellen Natur. Klostermann: Frankfurt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. (1921). Über das Wesen der Bewegung (1914). In Id., Gesammelte Schriften, hrsg. von E. Stein, Halle, Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riemann, B. (1868). On the hypotheses which lie at the foundation of geometry (Engl. ed. by W. Ewald). In Id., From Kant to Hilbert, II (pp. 652–661). Oxford : Clarendon Press (1996).

    Google Scholar 

  • Scaravelli, E. (1973). Scritti kantiani. La Nuova Italia: Florence.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schapp W. (1910). Beiträge zur Phänomenologie der Wahrnehmung, hrsg. von C. F. Graumann, Wiesbaden, B. Heymann 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schuhmann, K. (1977). Husserl-Chronik. Denk- und Lebensweg Edmund Husserls, Den Haag, M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (1997). Four-dimensionalism. The Philosophical Review, 106(2), 197–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski R. (1987). Measurement. American Philosophical Quarterly, 24(1), 71–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Volkert K. (1994), Anschauliche Unmöglichkeit versus logische Unmöglichkeit zur erkenntnistheoretischen Diskussion über die nichteuklidische Geometrie. In G. Meggle, V. Wessels (Ed.), Analyomen, 1 (Proceedings of 1st Conference Perspectives in Analytical Philosophy). De Gruyter: Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1918). The continuum: A critical examination of the foundation of analysis (Engl. ed. by S. Pollard, T. Bole). New York : Dover Publications (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1919). Raum, Zeit, Materie. Vorlesungen über allgemeine Relativitätstheorie (3rd ed.). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1975). Philosophical remarks (R. Rhees (Ed.), Engl. trans. by R. Hargreaves, R. White).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1991). Remarks on color (1950–51) (G. E. M. Anscombe (Ed.), Engl. trans. by L.L. McAlister-M. Schättle). New Jersey: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalamea, F. (2012). Peirce’s logic of continuity: A conceptual and mathematical approach. Chesnut Hill: Docent Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zambelli, P. (1999). Alexandre Koyré im “Mekka der Mathematik”. Koyrés Göttinger Dissertationsentwurf. N. T. M., n. s., 7, 208–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zanfi, C. (2013). Bergson e la filosofia tedesca 1907–1932. Quodlibet: Macerata.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Felice Masi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Masi, F. (2017). Antinomies of Measure. Phenomenology and Spatial Continuity (Husserl, Becker, Weyl). In: Catena, M., Masi, F. (eds) The Changing Faces of Space. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 39. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66911-3_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics