Skip to main content

Aristotle’s Political Friendship (politike philia) as Solidarity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Aristotle on Emotions in Law and Politics

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 121))

Abstract

Aristotle’s concept of friendship (philia), in particular the friendship between citizens, has had a significant impact on modern political philosophy. In a just state, citizens experience friendship with each other in that they wish each other well for their own sake and do things for each other even though they do not know each other. An important idea that runs throughout Aristotle’s ethical and political works is that citizens aim at promoting the common good. Aristotle defines political friendship as a concord (homonoia) which is a friendship of utility that comprises legal friendship and moral friendship. Political friendship is elaborated in the different constitutions (EN VIII.10, Pol. III.5, IV.2) and can concern different relationships—between citizens, between cities, and among human beings (EN VIII and IX). Political friendship creates concord in society and prevents violence and strife. Aristotle’s concept of political friendship could thus serve as model for contemporary communities, satisfying a growing need for social and global unity beyond liberty or justice. Aristotle insists that friendship (philia) is virtue, and concerns emotion and noble actions aimed at living well together. Therefore, political friendship is the greatest of blessings for the state, since it is the best safeguard against revolution and preserves the unity of the state (Pol. 1262b7–8).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Edition used: Aristotle, The complete works of Aristotle: the Revised Oxford Translation. Edited by Jonathan Barnes. Three works are especially relevant for Aristotle’s political theory: Nicomachean Ethics, Eudemian Ethics, and Politics.

  2. 2.

    Editions used: Nicomachean Ethics, edited by Terence Irwin and Nicomachean Ethics, Clarendon Aristotle Series.

  3. 3.

    Especially, see Nussbaum (1986, 2001, 2013).

  4. 4.

    Mulgan (1977).

  5. 5.

    Other scholars, especially Michael Sandel, Michael Walzer, and Amitai Etzioni are often faulted for undermining community feeling (or political affection or friendship), even though they insist they inherit Aristotle’s viewpoints, especially justice as a virtue.

  6. 6.

    Durkheim (2014).

  7. 7.

    For the history of solidarity, see Wilde (2013).

  8. 8.

    Derrida (1997).

  9. 9.

    Humans find fulfilment and happiness only in relatedness and solidarity’ with their fellow humans. Humanistic ethics affirms life through the unfolding of human powers, provided that this empowerment is not at the expense of others, for this would be tantamount to evil. In this conception, virtue is regarded as self-responsibility and vice as irresponsibility. See Fromm (2003).

  10. 10.

    Frank (2005), pp. 150–151 and 161–163.

  11. 11.

    Bryan (2009), pp. 758–759.

  12. 12.

    Edition used: The Complete Works of Aristotle: the Revised Oxford Translation. Edited by Jonathan Barnes.

  13. 13.

    Cooper (1980, p. 300) explains that philia is (1) mutual awareness and liking, (2) a reciprocal wishing the other well for the other’s sake, and (3) a reciprocal, practical “doing” of things for that other may be considered the denominators common to all friendships throughout Aristotle’s works. Here we must notice friendship is not merely an emotion; it requires “actual social interaction,” active engagement in one another’s lives (EN 1157b, 1171b–1172a, and Pol. 1280b). But Price (1989), chapter 5 who is another expert of Aristotle’s philia disagrees with Cooper. For more explanation, see Schwarzenbach (1996), p. 100.

  14. 14.

    Aristotle emphasizes friendship as ‘feeling’ in the friendship of pleasure between young people. He says “for their lives are guided by their feelings, and they pursue above all what is pleasant for themselves and what is at hand…Young people are prone to erotic passion, since this mostly accords with feelings, and is caused by pleasure; that is why they love and quickly stop, often changing in a single day” (EN 1156a32–1156b4). I think that Aristotle believes the love for feeling is the main characteristic aspect for erotic love (eros) as the one of kinds of the friendship of pleasure, instead of philia.

  15. 15.

    Aristotle (1998).

  16. 16.

    Kalimtzis (2000), pp. 51–52.

  17. 17.

    Edition used: The Complete Works of Aristotle: the Revised Oxford Translation. Edited by Jonathan Barnes.

  18. 18.

    Here Aristotle mentions that “homonoia is the friendship of fellow citizens” (EE 1241a33).

  19. 19.

    Here Aristotle mentions that “homonoia also appears to be a features of friendship” (EN 1167a22) and “homonoia, then, is apparently political friendship” (EN 1167b3).

  20. 20.

    Antiphon (2002).

  21. 21.

    Xenophon (2013).

  22. 22.

    Plato (1997).

  23. 23.

    Cicero (1887).

  24. 24.

    Recitation in Stern-Gillet (1995), p. 149.

  25. 25.

    This idea is also mentioned in 1162a20–22: “For the other animals, the community goes only as far as childbearing, but also for the benefits in their life.”

  26. 26.

    Kouloumbaritses (1981), pp. 198–199.

  27. 27.

    Recitation in Kalimtzis (2000), pp. 63–64.

  28. 28.

    Barker (1959).

  29. 29.

    Kronman (1979).

  30. 30.

    Yack (1993), p. 105.

  31. 31.

    Cartland says that Yack does not consider the question of whether political pluralism (i.e., differences of opinion regarding moral dilemmas) is compatible with prudence and, therefore, whether the polity can achieve eudaimonia. Cartland (2011), p. 40.

  32. 32.

    But Yack (1985) insisted that political friendship has the double meanings, both friendship for utility and for virtue in his older article, “Community and Conflict in Aristotle’s Political Philosophy”.

  33. 33.

    Cooper (1980), p. 305.

  34. 34.

    Stern-Gillet (1995), p. 149 confirms the rational meaning of political friendship, saying that “concord (homonoia) or friendship inevitably prevails between those who obey reason and recognize the irrelevance of such contingent factors as custom, ethnicity, and geography.”

  35. 35.

    “But civic friendship is that resting on equality; it is based on utility; and just as cities are friends to one another, so in the like way are citizen.” (EE 1242b24, trans. J. Solomon).

  36. 36.

    Editions used for Physics and Poetics: The Complete Works of Aristotle: the Revised Oxford Translation. Edited by Jonathan Barnes.

  37. 37.

    “There are six parts consequently of every tragedy, that make it the sort of tragedy it is, viz. a plot, characters, diction, thought, spectacle, and melody; two of them arising from the means, one from the manner, and three from the objects of the dramatic imitation, and there is nothing else besides these six…” (Poet. 1450a7–15 Trans. I. Bywater).

  38. 38.

    See more in Heater (2002), pp. 22–30 and Kalimtzis (2000), p. 66.

  39. 39.

    Recitation Wilde (2013), pp. 3–6.

  40. 40.

    Hutter (1978), p. 110.

  41. 41.

    Schwarzenbach regards political friendship as ‘care’; Aristotle repeatedly urges a “common care” (koinon epimeleian) when advising his statesmen in the EN 1180a2, and he uses the term ‘care’ (epimeleia) in a political context throughout his Politics (1261b27, 1263a27, 1293b13, 1299a20, 1300a5, 1325a7, 1328b12, 1335a7, 1395b20).

  42. 42.

    Fraser and Honneth (2003).

References

  • Antiphon. 2002. In The Fragments, ed. Gerard J. Pendrick. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. 1984a. Eudemian Ethics. In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes and trans. J. Solomon. Princeton, NJ and Guildford, UK: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984b. Physics. In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes and trans. R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye. Princeton, NJ and Guildford, UK: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984c. Poetics. In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes and trans. I. Bywater. Princeton, NJ and Guildford, UK: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984d. Politics. In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes and trans. B. Jowett. Princeton, NJ and Guildford, UK: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984e. Rhetoric. In The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes and trans. W. Rhys Roberts. Princeton, NJ and Guildford, UK: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Nicomachean Ethics. Books VIII and IX Books VIII and IX. Translated by Michael Pakaluk. Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press and Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Terence Irwin. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, Ernest. 1959. The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bryan, Bradley. 2009. Approaching Others: Aristotle on Friendship’s Possibility. Political Theory, September 25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartland, Jenifer. 2011. Aristotle’s Liberalism of Virtue: Unity, Disorder and Friendship. Saarbrücken: LAP LAMBERT Academic Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero, Marcus Tullius. 1887. In Ethical Writings of Cicero: Cicero De Officiis, Cicero De Senectute, Cicero De Amicitia, Scipio’s Dream, ed. Andrew P. Peabody. Boston, MA: Little, Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, John M. 1980. Aristotle on Friendship. In Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, ed. Amélie Rorty. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1997. Politics of Friendship. London and New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, Émile. 2014. The Division of Labor in Society. Edited by Steven Lukes and Translated by W. D. Halls. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Jill. 2005. A Democracy of Distinction: Aristotle and the Work of Politics. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, Nancy, and Axel Honneth. 2003. Redistribution or Recognition?: A Political-Philosophical Exchange. London and New York: Verso.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fromm, Erich. 2003. Man for Himself: An Inquiry into the Psychology of Ethics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heater, Derek. 2002. World Citizenship: Cosmopolitan Thinking and Its Opponents. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutter, Horst. 1978. Politics as Friendship: The Origins of Classical Notions of Politics in the Theory and Practice of Friendship. Waterloo, ON: Wilfrid Laurier University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalimtzis, Kostas. 2000. Aristotle on Political Enmity and Disease: An Inquiry into Stasis. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kouloumbaritses, L. 1981. Political Friendship in Aristotle. In Aristotle and Politics, ed. P. Demake, 198–199. Athens: Panteios School of Political Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kronman, Anthony. 1979. Aristotle’s Idea of Political Fraternity. American Journal of Jurisprudence 24 (1): 114–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mulgan, R.G. 1977. Aristotle’s Political Theory: An Introduction for Students of Political Theory. Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha Craven. 1986. The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for Justice. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato. 1997. Complete Works. Edited by John M. Cooper. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzenbach, Sibyl A. 1996. On Civic Friendship. Ethics 107 (1): 97–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern-Gillet, Suzanne. 1995. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Friendship. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilde, Lawrence. 2013. Global Solidarity. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xenophon. 2013. Memorabilia; Oeconomicus. Edited by Jeffrey Henderson and Translated by E. C. Marchant and O. J. Todd. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yack, Bernard. 1985. Community and Conflict in Aristotle’s Political Philosophy. Review of Politics 47: 92–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. The Problems of a Political Animal: Community, Justice, and Conflict in Aristotelian Political Thought. Berkeley: University of California press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Misung Jang .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Jang, M. (2018). Aristotle’s Political Friendship (politike philia) as Solidarity. In: Huppes-Cluysenaer, L., Coelho, N. (eds) Aristotle on Emotions in Law and Politics. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 121. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66703-4_20

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-66703-4_20

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-66702-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-66703-4

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics