Skip to main content

Knowledge, Time, and Paradox: Introducing Sequential Epistemic Logic

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Jaakko Hintikka on Knowledge and Game-Theoretical Semantics

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 12))

Abstract

Epistemic logic in the tradition of Hintikka provides, as one of its many applications, a toolkit for the precise analysis of certain epistemological problems. In recent years, dynamic epistemic logic has expanded this toolkit. Dynamic epistemic logic has been used in analyses of well-known epistemic “paradoxes”, such as the Paradox of the Surprise Examination and Fitch’s Paradox of Knowability, and related epistemic phenomena, such as what Hintikka called the “anti-performatory effect” of Moorean announcements. In this paper, we explore a variation on basic dynamic epistemic logic—what we call sequential epistemic logic—and argue that it allows more faithful and fine-grained analyses of those epistemological topics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a different variation on dynamic epistemic logic in a similar spirit, see [8, 9].

  2. 2.

    We will return to Hintikka’s point that “You may come to know that what I say was true” in Sect. 15.5.

  3. 3.

    An analogous statement is true for a third semantics for PAL based on arrow-elimination (as in [19, 32]), where the new relation \(R_{a \uparrow Q}\) is defined from the original relation \(R_a\) by: \(vR_{a \uparrow Q}u\) iff both \(vR_au\) and \(u\in Q\). Note, however, that non-trivial arrow-elimination will turn the reflexive \(R_a\) into a non-reflexive \(R_{a \uparrow Q}\), so the updated model will not be an epistemic model. For this reason, it is used to model the updating of belief rather than knowledge.

  4. 4.

    Also see [39, 47] on the role of time in knowability principles.

  5. 5.

    By contrast, the analysis in Sect. 3 of [18] involves syntactic derivations, as does the analysis in [24].

  6. 6.

    Also cf. [13], which uses an existential branching next-time operator, parametrized by epistemic actions, in connecting dynamic epistemic and epistemic temporal logic.

  7. 7.

    One way to see this is to note that the truth of our formulas without update operators is preserved under taking disjoint unions of models, defined in an obvious way, whereas \(\langle p\rangle \top \) concerns the model globally, not just what is reachable from the point of evaluation, so it is not preserved under taking disjoint unions of models. (If we had a universal modality, there would be more to say.).

  8. 8.

    The ‘\(\dots \)’ after \(S_{n-1}\) indicates that all coordinates of the new \(\omega \)-sequence are \(S_{n-1}\) thereafter, representing the supposition that “nothing else happens” after the update with \(\varphi _{n-1}\).

  9. 9.

    Even if \(\varphi \) does not contain futuristic operators, the fact that \(\langle !\rangle \) brings in a hypothetical future that may differ from the actual future means that we must be careful with the claim that \(Y\varphi \) expresses at \(t+1\) in the hypothetical sequence the “same proposition” that \(\varphi \) expresses at t in the actual sequence. This is correct if we mean that the set of worlds Q at which \(Y\varphi \) is true at \(t+1\) in the hypothetical sequence is the same as the set of worlds at which \(\varphi \) is true at t in the actual sequence. But the “worlds” in Q may have different futures—i.e., with respect to what epistemic relations these worlds will stand in—in the hypothetical sequence versus the actual sequence, so in a finer-grained sense, the set Q does not represent the same proposition relative to the hypothetical sequence and relative to the actual sequence. Still, the worlds in Q will have the same past up to t in both the hypothetical sequence and the actual sequence, so for a formula \(\varphi \) not containing futuristic operators, there is a reasonable sense in which the proposition expressed by \(Y\varphi \) at \(t+1\) in the hypothetical sequence is “the same” as the proposition expressed by \(\varphi \) at t in the actual sequence. This point deserves further discussion, but we do not have room for it here.

  10. 10.

    Cf. Hintikka on \(p\wedge \lnot Kp\) in Example 15.1: “You may come to know that what I say was true”.

  11. 11.

    This uses the fact that we are treating p as an eternal sentence, so \(KYp\rightarrow Kp\) is valid. If we were not treating p as eternal, then we would need to eternalize p with temporal operators: where \(S\varphi := P\varphi \vee \varphi \vee F\varphi \) (“sometime, \(\varphi \)”), the formula \(S p\wedge \lnot F K Sp\) is unascertainable.

  12. 12.

    See [24] for an analysis of the designated student paradox using static multi-agent epistemic logic. In that analysis, the assumptions about the initial epistemic states of the agents are not given by the model \(\mathscr {M}\), but rather by a weaker set of syntactically specified assumptions.

References

  1. Balbiani P, Baltag A, van Ditmarsch H, Herzig A, Hoshi T, de Lima T (2008) ‘Knowable’ as ‘known after an announcement’. Rev Symb Log 1(3):305–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Baltag A, Smets S (2010) Multi-agent belief dynamics. Lecture Slides from NASSLLI 2010, Indiana University. http://www.vub.ac.be/CLWF/nasslli2010lecture3.pdf

  3. van Benthem J (2004) What one may come to know. Analysis 64(2):95–105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. van Benthem J (2011) Logical dynamics of information and interaction. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  5. van Benthem J, Liu F (2007) Dynamic logic of preference upgrade. J Appl Non-Class Log 17(2):157–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. van Benthem J, Gerbrandy J, Hoshi T, Pacuit E (2009) Merging frameworks for interaction. J Philos Log 38(5):491–526

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Burgess J (2009) Can truth out? In: Salerno J (ed) New essays on the knowability paradox. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 147–162

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  8. Cohen M (2015a) A dynamic epistemic logic with a knowability principle. In: van der Hoek W, Holliday WH, Wang W (eds) Logic, rationality, and interaction: 5th international workshop, LORI 2015, Taipei, Taiwan, 28–30 Oct 2015. Proceedings, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, vol 9394. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cohen M (2015b) Dynamic knowability: the knowability paradox in dynamic epistemic logic. Master’s thesis, The Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München

    Google Scholar 

  10. van Ditmarsch H, Kooi B (2006) The secret of my success. Synthese 151(2):201–232

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. van Ditmarsch H, van der Hoek W, Kooi B (2008) Dynamic epistemic logic. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  12. van Ditmarsch H, van der Hoek W, Iliev P (2011) Everything is knowable—how to get to know whether a proposition is true. Theoria 78(2):93–114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. van Ditmarsch H, van der Hoek W, Ruan J (2013) Connecting dynamic epistemic and temporal epistemic logics. Log J IGPL 21(3):380–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. van Ditmarsch H, Halpern JY, van der Hoek W, Kooi B (2015) Handbook of epistemic logic. College Publications, London

    Google Scholar 

  15. Egré P (2011) Epistemic logic. In: Horsten L, Pettigrew R (eds) The continuum companion to philosophical logic. Continuum Companions, Continuum, New York, pp 503–542

    Google Scholar 

  16. Fitch FB (1963) A logical analysis of some value concepts. J Symb Log 28(2):135–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Gerbrandy J (1999) Bisimulations on planet Kripke. PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam, ILLC Dissertation Series DS-1999-01

    Google Scholar 

  18. Gerbrandy J (2007) The surprise examination in dynamic epistemic logic. Synthese 155(1):21–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Gerbrandy J, Groeneveld W (1997) Reasoning about information change. J Log Lang Inf 6(2):147–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Gierasimczuk N (2010) Knowing one’s limits. Logical analysis of inductive inference. PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam, ILLC Dissertation Series DS-2010-11

    Google Scholar 

  21. Herzig A, Lang J, Polacsek T (2000) A modal logic for epistemic tests. In: Horn W (ed) Proceedings of the 14th European conference on artificial intelligence (ECAI 2000). IOS Press, Amsterdam, pp 553–557

    Google Scholar 

  22. Hintikka J (1962) Knowledge and belief: an introduction to the logic of the two notions. Cornell University Press, Cornell

    Google Scholar 

  23. Holliday WH (2016a) On being in an undiscoverable position. Thought: A J Philos 5(1):33–40

    Google Scholar 

  24. Holliday WH (2016b) Simplifying the surprise exam. UC Berkeley Working Paper in Philosophy. http://escholarship.org/uc/item/82w2d085

  25. Holliday WH (Forthcoming) Epistemic logic and epistemology. In: Hansson S, Hendricks V (eds) Handbook of formal philosophy. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  26. Holliday WH, Icard TF (2010) Moorean phenomena in epistemic logic. In: Beklemishev L, Goranko V, Shehtman V (eds) Advances in modal logic, vol 8. College Publications, London, pp 178–199

    Google Scholar 

  27. Holliday WH, Hoshi T, Icard TF (2011) Schematic validity in dynamic epistemic logic: decidability. In: van Ditmarsch H, Lang J, Ju S (eds) Logic, rationality and interaction: third international workshop, LORI 2011, Guangzhou, China, 10–13 Oct 2011. Proceedings, Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, vol 6953. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 87–96

    Google Scholar 

  28. Holliday WH, Hoshi T, Icard TF (2012) A uniform logic of information dynamics. In: Bolander T, Braüner T, Ghilardi S, Moss L (eds) Advances in modal logic, vol 9. College Publications, London, pp 348–367

    Google Scholar 

  29. Holliday WH, Hoshi T, Icard TF (2013) Information dynamics and uniform substitution. Synthese 190(1):31–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Hoshi T (2008) Epistemic dynamics and protocol information. PhD thesis, Stanford University, ILLC Dissertation Series DS-2009-08

    Google Scholar 

  31. Hoshi T, Yap A (2009) Dynamic epistemic logic with branching temporal structures. Synthese 169(2):259–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Kooi B (2007) Expressivity and completeness for public update logics via reduction axioms. J Appl Non-Class Log 17(2):231–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Lewis D (1969) Convention: a philosophical study. Harvary University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  34. Lewis D (1996) Elusive knowledge. Australas J Philos 74(4):549–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. van Linder B, van der Hoek W, Meyer JJC (1994) Tests as epistemic updates: pursuit of knowledge. Technical report UU-CS-1994-08, Department of Computer Science, Utrecht University

    Google Scholar 

  36. Marcoci A (2010) The surprise examination paradox in dynamic epistemic logic. Master’s thesis, ILLC Master of Logic Thesis Series MoL-2010-18

    Google Scholar 

  37. Pacuit E (2013) Dynamic epistemic logic I and II. Philos Compass 8(9):798–833

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Plaza J (1989) Logics of public communications. In: Emrich M, Pfeifer M, Hadzikadic M, Ras Z (eds) Proceedings of the 4th international symposium on methodologies for intelligent systems: poster session program. Oak Ridge National Laboratory, ORNL/DSRD-24, pp 201–216

    Google Scholar 

  39. Proietti C, Sandu G (2010) Fitch’s paradox and ceteris paribus modalities. Synthese 173(1):75–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Quine WVO (1960) Word and object. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  41. Renne B, Sack J, Yap A (2009) Dynamic epistemic temporal logic. In: He X, Horty J, Pacuit E (eds) Logic, rationality, and interaction: second international workshop, LORI 2009, Chongqing, China, 8–11 Oct 2009. Proceedings, Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, vol 5834. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 263–277

    Google Scholar 

  42. Renne B, Sack J, Yap A (2016) Logics of temporal-epistemic actions. Synthese 193(3):813–849

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Sack J (2010) Logic for update products and steps into the past. Ann Pure Appl Log 161(12):1431–1461

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Sorensen R (1984) Recalcitrant variations of the prediction paradox. Australas J Philos 69(4):355–362

    Google Scholar 

  45. Sorensen R (1988) Blindspots. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  46. Stalnaker RC (1984) Inquiry. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  47. Wansing H (2015) Knowability remixed. In: Caret CR, Hjortland OT (eds) Foundations of logical consequence. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 322–328

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  48. Williamson T (2000) Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  49. Yap A (2011) Dynamic epistemic logic and temporal modality. In: Girard P, Roy O, Marion M (eds) Dynamic formal epistemology, synthese library, vol 351. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 33–50

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper is the written version of a talk with the same title that I gave at the LogiCIC mini-workshop on The Dynamics of Information States, organized by Ben Rodenhäuser in Amsterdam on June 19, 2014. I am grateful to Ben for the invitation to the workshop and to Alexandru Baltag and Sonja Smets for their encouraging feedback on the talk. I also benefited from the experience of co-teaching a course with Eric Pacuit on Ten Puzzles and Paradoxes of Knowledge and Belief at ESSLLI 2013 in Dusseldorf. It was during a sleepless jet-lagged night in Dusseldorf, before my lecture on dynamic epistemic logic, that ideas in this paper occurred to me. Finally, I appreciate having had the pleasure to meet Jaakko Hintikka at Stanford in March 2012, when he very kindly spent a lunch discussing epistemic logic with me. For helpful comments on this paper, I thank Johan van Benthem and Hans van Ditmarsch.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wesley H. Holliday .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Holliday, W.H. (2018). Knowledge, Time, and Paradox: Introducing Sequential Epistemic Logic. In: van Ditmarsch, H., Sandu, G. (eds) Jaakko Hintikka on Knowledge and Game-Theoretical Semantics. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 12. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-62864-6_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics