Skip to main content

How Husserl’s and Searle’s Contextual Model Reformulates the Discussion About the Conceptual Content of Perception

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Perception, Affectivity, and Volition in Husserl’s Phenomenology

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 222))

Abstract

I argue that Husserl’s notion of horizon and Searle’s notion of background offer a contextual model of perception that significantly reformulates the debate about the conceptual vs. nonconceptual content of perception. I illustrate the model by using a test case: the perception of an ancient Roman milestone—an example given by Husserl—which both Husserl and Searle consider to be a direct and immediate perception without inferences involved. I further differentiate Husserl’s and Searle’s views, arguing that Husserl’s model has the advantage of accounting for the diachronic aspect of perception.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On this see Dretske (2003), Hopp (2011), McDowell (2003), Peacocke (2001), Stalnaker (2003), as well as the essays in Schear (2013).

  2. 2.

    In this regard, I agree with Mulligan when he writes: “It is often suggested that Searle ’s analysis of intentionality was anticipated by Husserl’s Logical Investigations … This is not the case” (2003, 266–67).

  3. 3.

    Husserl also gives the example of his wife: “I see an object. It is Malvine; she enters the room. Or I recognize her without a word – her first name – playing a role. This is the ‘wordless recognition’ of an individual object” (Hua XX/2, 263).

  4. 4.

    On the first-person see Davidson 1984, Searle 1987, Shoemaker 1996.

  5. 5.

    This givenness does not de-realize objects, but remarkably grants them a persona; the object is something that “cries out to us” (Hua XXXVI, 86–87) or “knocks at the door of consciousness” (1989, 231).

  6. 6.

    On the notion of horizon, see among many others: Christensen 1993, 749–779; Hilmy 1981–1982, 21–48; Kwan 1990, 361–399; Taylor 1990, 19–23; Walton 1988, 55–71, 2010, 132–151.

  7. 7.

    Husserl writes: “The factual world is experienced according to types. The things are experienced as tree, shrub, animal, snake, bird … The table is characterized as something we recognize and yet something new. What is experienced as individually new is, at first, known through what is actually perceived; it reminds us of something identical (or similar). What is grasped as typical also has a horizon of possible experiences with corresponding indications of what is known, thus a type of properties not yet experienced, but expected. If we see a dog, we immediately anticipate further behaviors, its typical manner of eating, playing, running, jumping, etc.” (1973a, 331; 1985, 398–99).

  8. 8.

    On the role of sensations, see Moran 2005, 152f.

  9. 9.

    He opposes signitiv to intuitiv (Hua XIX/2, 567).

  10. 10.

    As Husserl further explains: “Countless signitive intentions lack either a fixed or a passing tie with expressions, though their essential character puts them in a class with meaning-intentions. I here recur to the perceptual and imaginative course of a melody, or of some familiar type of event, and to the definite or indefinite intentions and fulfillments which arise in such a course. I refer likewise to the empirical arrangement and connection of things in their phenomenal coexistence, in regard to whatever gives the things appearing in this order, and especially the parts in each unified individual thing, the character of a unity involving precisely this order and this form” (2001, 224).

    However, in the reworkings of this work of 1913, Husserl criticizes his broad use of signitive intention. There was, Husserl says, an extension of the signitive intentions to all intentions that point beyond the sensory given but it was, he continues “a terminology about which we have misgivings and have therefore abandoned” (XX/1, 91).

  11. 11.

    See also: “The essence of thinghood, with respect to all its moments, includes a stream of limitless continuity, a limitless realm of open possibilities a parte ante, which a parte post can ever be more precisely determined, delimited, and enriched, but which always have to await infinity” (1997, 114).

  12. 12.

    This quotation makes explicit what can also be found in the Crisis where we read that the thing is nothing more than “a unity for consciousness of the openly endless multiplicity of changing experiences and experienced things, one’s own and those of others” (1970, 164). This is also confirmed by Dorion Cairns who reports in his conversations with Husserl that “today he [Husserl] sees that the object itself is, in its being and determinations, correlate of the horizon … Being is always and only given as correlate of a horizon; it is never self-given in originality” (1976, 97).

  13. 13.

    Searle uses the expression of “mind/brain” in, among other places, Intentionality (1983, vii) as naming his own alternative to dualism. As he explains his view, “consciousness consists of inner, qualitative, subjective states and processes. It has therefore a first-person ontology” and “consciousness is, above all, a biological phenomenon. Conscious processes are biological processes” (1998, 53).

  14. 14.

    I am very grateful to Peter Burgess and Zachary Hugo for their careful editing.

References

  • Cairns, Dorion. 1976. Conversations with Husserl and Fink. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, Carleton. 1993. Sense, Subject and Horizon. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53: 749–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, Donald. 1984. First Person Authority. Dialectica 38: 101–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred. 2003. The Intentionality of Perception. In John Searle, ed. B. Smith, 154–168. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert. 2013. The Myth of the Pervasiveness of the Mental. In Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-world: the McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, ed. J. Schear, 14–40. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilmy, Stephen. 1981. The Scope of Husserl’s Notion of Horizon. The Modern Schoolman 59: 21–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopp, Walter. 2011. Perception and Knowledge: A Phenomenological Account. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1952. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Zweites Buch, Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution. Edited by M. Biemel. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1970. The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Philosophy. Trans. D. Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1973a. Experience and Judgment: Investigations in a Genealogy of Logic. Trans. J. Churchill. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1973b. Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Zweiter Teil: 1921–1928. Edited by I. Kern. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1976. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch, Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie. Edited by K. Schuhmann. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis, Zweiter Teil. Edited by U. Panzer. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985. Erfahrung und Urteil. Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik. Edited by L. Landgrebe. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy, Second Book. Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution. Trans. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Thing and Space. Lectures of 1907. Trans. R. Rojcewicz. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy First Book General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology. Trans. F. Kersten. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Logical Investigations, vol. 2. Trans. J.N. Findlay. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Logische Untersuchungen, Ergzänzungsband, Erster Teil. Entwürfe zur Umarbeitung der VI. Untersuchung and zur Vorrede für die Neuauflage der Logischen Untersuchungen (Sommer 1913). Edited by U. Melle. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Transzendentaler Idealismus. Texte aus dem Nachlass (1908–1921). Edited by R. Rollinger and R. Sowa. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Logische Untersuchungen, Ergzänzungsband, Zweiter Teil. Texte für die Neufassung der VI. Untersuchung. Zur Phänomenologie des Ausdrucks und der Erkenntnis (1893/94–1921). Edited by U. Melle. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kwan, Tze-Wan. 1990. Husserl’s Concept of Horizon. An Attempt at Reappraisal. In The Moral Sense and its Foundational Significance: Self, Person, Historicity, Community. Phenomenological Praxeology and Psychiatry, ed. A.-Th. Tymieniecka, 361–399. Boston: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Nonconceptual Content (1994). In Essays on Nonconceptual Content, ed. Y. Gunther, 75–90. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, John Stuart. 1884. An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy and of The Principal Philosophical Questions Discussed In His Writings. New York: Henry Holt and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, Dermot. 2005. Edmund Husserl: Founder of Phenomenology. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, Kevin. 2003. Searle, Derrida, and the Ends of Phenomenology. In John Searle, ed. B. Smith, 261–286. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, Christopher. 2001. Does Perception Have a Nonconceptual Content? Journal of Philosophy 98 (5): 239–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schear, Joseph, ed. 2013. Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-world: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John. 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. Intentionality, Empiricism, and the First Person. Journal of Philosophy 84: 123–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991. Response: Perception and the Satisfactions of Intentionality. In Searle and His Critics, ed. E. Lepore and R. Van Gulick, 181–192. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. The Rediscovery of the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Mind, Language and Society: Philosophy in the Real World. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Mind. A Brief Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, Sydney. 1996. The First-person Perspective and Other Essays. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, Robert. 2003. What Might Nonconceptual Content Be? (1998). In Essays on Nonconceptual Content, ed. Y. Gunther, 95–106. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Larry G. 1990. The Centrality of the ‘Horizon’ in Husserl and Heidegger. Contemporary Philosophy 13: 19–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Roberto J. 1988. Nature and the ‘Primal Horizon,’. Phenomenological Inquiry 12: 55–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. The Constitutive and Reconstructive Building-up of Horizons. In Epistemology, Archaeology, Ethics: Current Investigations of Husserl’s Corpus, ed. P. Vandevelde and S. Luft, 132–151. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, Dan. 2003. Husserl’s Phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pol Vandevelde .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Vandevelde, P. (2017). How Husserl’s and Searle’s Contextual Model Reformulates the Discussion About the Conceptual Content of Perception. In: Walton, R., Taguchi, S., Rubio, R. (eds) Perception, Affectivity, and Volition in Husserl’s Phenomenology. Phaenomenologica, vol 222. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55340-5_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics