Skip to main content

Husserl’s Spatialization of Perceptual Consciousness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Perception, Affectivity, and Volition in Husserl’s Phenomenology

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 222))

  • 488 Accesses

Abstract

In this paper I show that, in Husserl’s phenomenology of perception, the consciousness of any perceiving subject can take up space. What Husserl calls “noema” just is some intentional object. Thus any noema of perception just is the object of some perceptual experience. According to Husserl, since the noema of perception is immanent to the consciousness of the perceiving subject, the object of perception must also be in some sense immanent. In order to avoid confrontation with Husserl’s anti-Brentanian claim that no intentional object can be immanent to any intentional act, I show that there are two different senses of immanence in Husserl: the “genuine”-sense and what Steven Crowell calls the “phenomenological”-sense. On this disambiguation, any perceptual object can be genuinely transcendent while remaining phenomenologically immanent. What is required for the second sense of immanence is a holistic conception of consciousness. However, Husserl is also a realist about the objects of perception: the object of perception is the actual object itself rather than some mental representation of anything like the Kantian thing in-itself. The objects of perception are spatial. Therefore, if any perceptual object is immanent to some consciousness then that consciousness must also be spatial; hence, my spatialist interpretation of Husserl’s phenomenology of perception.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As I make clear in Sect. 3.2, I take this phrase from Crowell (2008), although he uses it in a sense different than mine.

  2. 2.

    I add “typically” because in early onset glaucoma some patients see a black spot in their visual field. The black spot is an object of perception. It is not publicly accessible.

  3. 3.

    For example, Cartesian skepticism, mind-body problem, etc.

  4. 4.

    The most comprehensive defense of the standard object-interpretation of the noema remains Drummond (1990). To a large extent, the view that I develop about the noema is derived from Drummond’s. That is why I offer no positive arguments of my own that the noema is some kind of intentional object. Where I diverge from Drummond ’s view should be clear by the end of Sect. 3.3. For other object-interpretations, see: Gurwitsch (1964), Welton (1983), Sokolowski (1987), Bell (1990), Banchetti (1993), Ströker (1993), Brainard (2002), Zahavi (2003), Shim (2005).

  5. 5.

    Føllesdal (1969) is the origin of this view. Although a minority view within Husserl scholarship, this alternative interpretation of Husserl may be more influential on philosophers at large. For example, see Dreyfus (1982), Dummett (1993).

  6. 6.

    For a more recent discussion of this “noetic, or act-based” Husserlian view of token meanings that I do endorse, see: Hopp (2011, esp. 27–36). My agreement with Hopp—as opposed to Smith and McIntyre —rests on the fact that Hopp nowhere calls the conceptual “content” or aspect of an intentional act the “noema”; since, in general, Hopp takes no side at all in the noema debate (Hopp 2011, 176–177). For a contemporary view that conceives representational “contents” to be features or aspects of intentional or psychological states rather than being their truth-value, see: Pitt (2009).

  7. 7.

    Consequently, Smith and McIntyre are early advocates of conceptualism about perception.

  8. 8.

    Another exegetical reason in Smith and McIntyre is the following confusion between “reell” and “real.” As Husserl uses these terms, “reell” means “genuine” or “authentic;” by contrast, by “real” he means spatio-temporal, thus “actual” in a metaphysical sense. However, it appears Smith and McIntyre confuse these two distinct concepts and argue like this: since the noema is not a “reell”—i.e., not a genuine or authentic—component of the intentional act, it must be non-“real”—i.e., must be neither spatial nor temporal—and, therefore, the noema must be “ideal” or abstract (1982, 119–125). This is an obvious terminological error and, thus, fails to motivate their interpretation.

  9. 9.

    It should be noted that the later Brentano (1966) renounced this doctrine of “mental inexistence.” For details, see: Smith and McIntyre (1982, 47–54, 57–61).

  10. 10.

    All translations of Husserl’s work are my own.

  11. 11.

    As I will expand upon in Sect. 3.3, a sufficient condition for the transcendence of an intentional object is its numerical identity despite the diversity of intentional experiences about it (Hua III/1, 79, 84–86; Hua XI, 330–331).

  12. 12.

    Throughout this paper, experience is a translation of “Erlebnis”—which is more accurately, though more awkwardly, translated as living through or undergoing. Among many reasons why Husserl is not a representationalist is that not all Erlebnisse are intentional or representational. Moods, emotions, proprioceptive states like pain and hunger, are for Husserl Erlebnisse—but they do not represent.

  13. 13.

    In Ideas I, Husserl admits quite frankly “the one-sidedness of the noetic orientation” in the Logical Investigations (Hua III/1, 298; also, 217–218). That is, in the first edition of the Logical Investigations, Husserl dealt almost exclusively with features and properties of individual intentional acts—i.e., what is only genuinely immanent—as opposed to the objects at which such acts are directed. Smith and McIntyre ’s interpretation, therefore, turns out to be only germane to the noetic analysis of the first edition of Logical Investigations.

  14. 14.

    The rule seems to be this. Genuine immanence implies phenomenological immanence; but the converse is not the case. Perceptual objects can be phenomenologically immanent without being genuinely immanent. Phenomenological transcendence implies genuine transcendence. Nothing can be phenomenologically transcendent and genuinely immanent. However, the converse is not the case: genuine transcendence does not imply phenomenological immanence, for perceptual objects are genuinely transcendent yet phenomenologically immanent.

  15. 15.

    Of the numerically identical “pure ego” required by neo-Kantians like Paul Natorp, Husserl writes: “I must openly admit that I have not in any way been able to find such a primitive ego as the necessary center of relations” (Hua XIX, 374).

  16. 16.

    In the second edition of Logical Investigations, Husserl remarks in a footnote: “Since then, I have learned how to find [the pure ego]” (Hua XIX, 374).

References

  • Banchetti, Marina. 1993. Føllesdal on the Notion of the Noema: A Critique. Husserl Studies 10: 81–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, David. 1990. Husserl. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brainard, Marcus. 2002. Belief and its Neutralization: Husserl’s System of Phenomenology in Ideas I. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, Franz. 1995. Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. Trans. A. Rancurello, et al. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966. The True and the Evident. Trans. R. Chisholm, et al. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, Steven. 2008. Phenomenological Immanence, Normativity and Semantic Externalism. Synthese 160: 335–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert. 1982. The Perceptual Noema. In Husserl, Intentionality, and Cognitive Science, ed. H. Dreyfus and H. Hall, 97–123. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drummond, John. 1990. Husserlian Intentionality and Non-Foundational Realism: Noema and Object. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. The Transcendental and the Psychological. Husserl Studies 24: 193–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, Michael. 1993. Origins of Analytical Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Føllesdal, Dagfinn. 1969. Husserl’s Notion of Noema. Journal of Philosophy 66: 680–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, Aron. 1964. The Field of Consciousness. Pittsburgh: Duquesne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopp, Walter. 2011. Perception and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1950. Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge. Edited by S. Strasser. The Hague: Martinus-Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1954. Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. Edited by W. Biemel. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1958. Die Idee der Phänomenologie: Fünf Vorlesungen. Edited by W. Biemel. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966. Analysen zur passiven Synthesis. Edited by M. Fleischer. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1973. Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivitât: Zweiter Teil. Edited by I. Kern. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie: Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie. Edited by K. Schumann. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. Logische Untersuchungen: Zweiter Band. Edited by U. Panzer. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Transzendentaler Idealismus: Texte aus dem Nachlass (1908–1921). Edited by R. Hollinger and R. Stowa Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kojima, Hiroshi. 2000. Versuch einer vertieften Monadologie in der japanischen Phänomenologie. In Phänomenologie und Leibniz, ed. R. Cristin and K. Sakai, 183–210. Munich: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, David. 2009. Intentional psychologism. Philosophical Studies 146: 117–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John. 1982. Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shim, Michael. 2005. The Duality of Non-Conceptual Content in Husserl’s Phenomenology of Perception. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4: 209–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, David W., and Ronald McIntyre. 1982. Husserl and Intentionality: A Study of Mind, Meaning, and Language. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, Robert. 1987. Husserl and Frege. The Journal of Philosophy 84: 521–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ströker, Elisabeth. 1993. Husserl’s Transcendental Phenomenology. Trans. L. Hardy. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welton, Donn. 1983. The Origins of Meaning: A Critical Study of the Thresholds of Husserlian Phenomenology. The Hague: Martinus-Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, Dan. 2003. Husserl’s Phenomenology. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael K. Shim .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Shim, M.K. (2017). Husserl’s Spatialization of Perceptual Consciousness. In: Walton, R., Taguchi, S., Rubio, R. (eds) Perception, Affectivity, and Volition in Husserl’s Phenomenology. Phaenomenologica, vol 222. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55340-5_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics