Skip to main content

Coordination and Measurement: What We Get Wrong About What Reichenbach Got Right

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
EPSA15 Selected Papers

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 5))

Abstract

In his Scientific Representation (2008), van Fraassen argues that measuring is a form of representation. In fact, every measurement pinpoints its target in accordance with specific operational rules within an already-constructed theoretical space, in which certain conceptual interconnections can be represented. Reichenbach’s 1920 account of coordination is particularly interesting in this connection. Even though recent reassessments of this account do not do full justice to some important elements lying behind it, they do have the merit of focusing on a different aspect of his early work that traditional interpretations of relativized a priori principles have unfortunately neglected in favour of a more “structural” role for coordination. In Reichenbach’s early work, however, the idea of coordination was employed not only to indicate theory-specific fundamental principles such as the ones suggested in the literature on conventional principles in science, but also to refer to more “basic” assumptions. In Reichenbach, these principles are preconditions both of the individuation of physical magnitudes and of their measurement, and, as such, they are necessary to approach the world in the first instance. This paper aims to reassess Reichenbach’s approach to coordination and to the representation of physical quantities in light of recent literature on measurement and scientific representation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The “invention” of temperature, as Chang (2004) put it, has now become a classic example of this.

  2. 2.

    I tend to interpret it as a weak defence of the a priori, rather than as a “weak rejection” of it, as Parrini has instead suggested already in the early 1980s. Cf. his (2002), chap. 1.

  3. 3.

    See Friedman (2001) and literature therein.

  4. 4.

    In chapters II and III of his (1920/1965) Reichenbach’s approach is indeed to show how contradictions can emerge when considering the whole set of fundamental principles presupposed by a theory with respect to some other whole set of principles accepted by the previous theory.

  5. 5.

    In (1916/2008) the justification, presented in proto-Kantian terms, goes along the lines of a “transcendental deduction”. On this particular approach, see Padovani (2011) and literature therein.

  6. 6.

    To my knowledge, the only text in which he outlines how this procedure is supposed to work, albeit without referring to the term “mutuality of coordination”, is Reichenbach (1923/1932), an interesting paper dealing with scientific inference and theory testing. Cf. Padovani (2015b).

  7. 7.

    In this respect, van Fraassen misses this point in Reichenbach’s work both in his (2007, 412) as well as in his (2008, 137), when he writes that “there is no presuppositionless starting point for coordination” – pace Reichenbach.

  8. 8.

    On the origin and importance of this principle in Reichenbach’s work, see Padovani (2013).

  9. 9.

    See in particular his (2008, chap. 5).

  10. 10.

    Reichenbach describes the passage from one system of principles to the other in terms of inclusion of the oldest into the new one. An extension or generalization of a system moving beyond the previous one can be obtained within the system itself, by virtue of what he names “procedure of the continuous expansion” (Verfahren der stetigen Erweiterung), that the English edition translates as “method of the successive approximations”. As he writes: “The contradiction that arises if experiences are made with the old coordinating principle by means of which a new coordinating principle is to be proved disappears on one condition: if the old principle can be regarded as an approximation [Näherung] for certain simple cases. Since all experiences are merely approximate laws [Näherungsgesetze], they may be established by means of the old principles; this method does not exclude the possibility that the totality of experiences inductively confirms a more general principle. It is logically admissible and technically possible to discover inductively new coordinating principles that represent a successive approximation of the principles used until now. We can call such a generalization “successive” [stetig] because for certain approximately realized cases the new principle is to converge toward the old principle with an exactness corresponding to the approximation of these cases. We shall call this inductive procedure the method of successive approximations [Verfahren der stetigen Erweiterung].” Reichenbach (1920/1965), 68–69.

  11. 11.

    Cf. van Fraassen (2008), 166 ff.

  12. 12.

    Interestingly, an analysis of these issues had already been carried out by Reichenbach, mutatis mutandis, in his doctoral dissertation (1916/2008), together with his first extensive discussion of the notion of approximation. As I have emphasized in my (2011), it was this kind of analysis that first implicitly lead to the idea of a “relativized a priori” and so it was not the Einsteinian revolution that was in the background of this idea, contrary to what Friedman (2001) has claimed.

  13. 13.

    This theoretical space is a mathematical construct that is used to represent certain conceptual interconnections in the act of measuring. Some of van Fraassen’s favourite illustrations of what he means by “logical space”, and how this theoretical space is supposed to work, are time and colour. On these issues, see however Belot (2010).

  14. 14.

    I’ve insisted on these issues especially in Padovani (2015b).

  15. 15.

    Cf. Padovani (2015a).

Bibliography

  • Belot, G. 2010. Transcendental idealism among the Jersey metaphysicians. Philosophical Studies 150: 429–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. 2004. Inventing temperature. Measurement and scientific progress. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 2001. Dynamics of reason. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Reconsidering the dynamics of reason. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43: 47–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krantz, H., R. Luce, P. Suppes, and A. Tversky. 1971–1990. Foundations of measurement, vol. I–III. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Padovani, F. 2011. Relativizing the relativized a priori. Synthese 181 (1): 41–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Genidentity and topology of time: Kurt Lewin and Hans Reichenbach. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 273: 97–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015a. Measurement, coordination, and the relativized a priori. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 52: 123–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015b. Reichenbach on causality in 1923: Scientific inference, coordination, and confirmation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 53: 3–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parrini, P. 2002. L’empirismo logico. Aspetti storici e prospettive teoriche. Roma: Carocci.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. 1916/2008. The concept of probability in the mathematical representation of reality, ed. F. Eberhardt and C. Glymour. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1920/1965. The theory of relativity and a priori knowledge. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1923/1932. Die Kausalbehauptung und die Möglichkeit ihrer empirischen Nachprüfung. Erkenntnis 3 (1): 32–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stump, D. 2015. Conceptual change and the philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tal, E. 2013. Old and new problems in philosophy of measurement. Philosophy Compass 8 (12): 1159–1173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Making time: A study in the epistemology of measurement. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 67: 297–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B.C. (2007). Relativity reign O’er Me. Symposium on Thomas Ryckman’s The Reign of Relativity. Metascience 16(3): 407–419.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Scientific representation. Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Modeling and measurement: The criterion of empirical grounding. Philosophy of Science 79: 773–784.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Besides the EPSA 2015 meeting in Düsseldorf, early versions of this paper were also presented at the BSPS conference in Manchester (2015) and at the GWP conference in Düsseldorf (2016). On all those occasions, I have greatly benefitted from the remarks made by the audience. I also wish to thank Giovanni Valente and Erik Curiel as well as two anonymous referees for valuable comments on a previous draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Flavia Padovani .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this paper

Cite this paper

Padovani, F. (2017). Coordination and Measurement: What We Get Wrong About What Reichenbach Got Right. In: Massimi, M., Romeijn, JW., Schurz, G. (eds) EPSA15 Selected Papers. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53730-6_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics