Skip to main content

On the Alleged Simplicity of Impure Proof

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Simplicity: Ideals of Practice in Mathematics and the Arts

Part of the book series: Mathematics, Culture, and the Arts ((MACUAR))

Abstract

Roughly, a proof of a theorem, is “pure” if it draws only on what is “close” or “intrinsic” to that theorem. Mathematicians employ a variety of terms to identify pure proofs, saying that a pure proof is one that avoids what is “extrinsic,” “extraneous,” “distant,” “remote,” “alien,” or “foreign” to the problem or theorem under investigation. In the background of these attributions is the view that there is a distance measure (or a variety of such measures) between mathematical statements and proofs. Mathematicians have paid little attention to specifying such distance measures precisely because in practice certain methods of proof have seemed self-evidently impure by design: think for instance of analytic geometry and analytic number theory. By contrast, mathematicians have paid considerable attention to whether such impurities are a good thing or to be avoided, and some have claimed that they are valuable because generally impure proofs are simpler than pure proofs. This article is an investigation of this claim, formulated more precisely by proof-theoretic means. After assembling evidence from proof theory that may be thought to support this claim, we will argue that on the contrary this evidence does not support the claim.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 19.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 29.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 29.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. [14, p. 351], though statements of this sort are found throughout La géométrie. For more on the simplicity of the Cartesian method in geometry [3, Sect. 2], [41].

  2. 2.

    Cf. [39, p. 271]. For a detailed historical investigation of Lagrange’s views on purity in his algebraic work.

  3. 3.

    The prize question is described in [51, p. 4]. Otto Hölder showed in 1892 that there is no exact solution in finite terms to cubics in the casus irreducibilis that avoids imaginary numbers [32]. For a more thorough discussion of the casus irreducibilis in relation to purity [1].

  4. 4.

    More precisely, the prime number theorem states that \(\frac{\pi (x)} {x/\log (x)}\) approaches 1 in the limit, where π(x) is the number of primes less than or equal to x.

  5. 5.

    Cf. [24, p. 338]. For more on purity in arithmetic [2, 4].

  6. 6.

    Note that in [8] Avigad draws on work from automated reasoning, which is closely allied with proof theory; thus these approaches are not exclusive.

  7. 7.

    In [54], Simpson defines RCA0 (on p. 24) in a slightly different but equivalent way, using Σ 1 0-induction (with set parameters) but not primitive recursion. As he notes on p. 73, Friedman originally defined RCA0 in the way we have done here [23, pp. 557–558].

  8. 8.

    A significant remaining question is whether IΣ 1 is especially significant, as an arithmetical extension of PRA, for the thesis that impurity generally offers gains of efficiency; or whether a study of IΣ 2, for instance, would offer key additional insights. Toward this, Ignjatović has conjectured that further inductive strengthenings of PRA with respect to the quantifier-free theorems of PRA will yield a significant gain of efficiency, but to the best of our knowledge this is still open.

  9. 9.

    Polynomial speed-up may be more carefully defined as follows [10, pp. 4–5]. Let the length ℓ(π) of a proof π be the number of symbol occurrences in π. For any formula φ, let \(\pi _{T_{i}}^{<}(\varphi )\) be the shortest proof (in terms of number of symbol occurrences) of φ in T i . We say that T 1 is at most a polynomial speed-up of T 2 with respect to Φ if there is a polynomial p(x) with natural number coefficients such that for every φ provable in T 2

    $$\displaystyle{ \ell(\pi _{T_{2}}^{<}(\varphi )) <p(\ell(\pi _{ T_{1}}^{<}(\varphi ))). }$$
  10. 10.

    This can be defined precisely as follows. Firstly, a function f(x) eventually dominates a function g(x) if there is an m such that for all n > m, f(n) ≥ g(n). Secondly, let 2 m x be the function defined by: \(2_{0}^{n} = n, 2_{m+1}^{n} = 2^{2_{m}^{n}}\). For example, \(2_{1}^{n} = 2^{2_{0}^{n}} = 2^{n}\), \(2_{2}^{n} = 2^{2_{1}^{n}} = 2^{2^{n}}\), \(2_{3}^{n} = 2^{2_{2}^{n}} = 2^{2^{2^{n} }}\), and so on. A function f(x) has Kalmar elementary growth rate if there is an m such that 2 m x eventually dominates f(x). It turns out that 2 x x is the first function that dominates all Kalmar elementary functions. A function f(x) has roughly super-exponential growth rate if and only if (i) it does not have Kalmar elementary growth rate, but (ii) there is a polynomial p(x) with natural number coefficients such that p(2 x x) eventually dominates it.

  11. 11.

    Roughly super-exponential speed-up may be more carefully defined as follows [10, pp. 4–5]. T 1 has roughly super-exponential speed-up over T 2 if and only if

    1. 1.

      there is no function f(x) with Kalmar elementary growth rate such that for every φ provable in T 2, \(\ell(\pi _{T_{2}}^{<}(\varphi )) <f(\ell(\pi _{T_{1}}^{<}(\varphi )))\); and

    2. 2.

      there is a function g(x) with roughly super-exponential growth rate such that for every φ provable in T 2, \(\ell(\pi _{T_{2}}^{<}(\varphi )) <g(\ell(\pi _{T_{1}}^{<}(\varphi )))\).

    For Φ a set of formulas provable in T 2, T 1 has roughly super-exponential speed-up over T 2 with respect to Φ if and only if there is a sequence {φ i : iω} of formulas from Φ such that

    1. 1.

      there is no function f(x) with Kalmar elementary growth rate such that for every φ n Φ, \(\ell(\pi _{T_{2}}^{<}(\varphi _{n})) <f(\ell(\pi _{T_{1}}^{<}(\varphi _{n})))\); and

    2. 2.

      there is a function g(x) with roughly super-exponential growth rate such that for every φ n Φ, \(\ell(\pi _{T_{2}}^{<}(\varphi _{n})) <g(\ell(\pi _{T_{1}}^{<}(\varphi _{n})))\).

  12. 12.

    He suggests as a possibility WKL0 + + COH, where COH asserts the existence of a cohesive set, having shown that WKL0 + + COH is a Π 2 1-axiomatizable Π 1 1-conservative extension of RCA0 (Corollary 2.5).

  13. 13.

    That WKL0 and WKL0 + are Π 2 1-axiomatizable can be seen by inspecting the logical form of their axioms. That they are not Π 1 1-axiomatizable follows, respectively, from Harrington’s result that WKL0 is Π 1 1-conservative over RCA0 and from Brown and Simpson’s result that WKL0 + is Π 1 1-conservative over RCA0. To see why for the case of WKL0, note that we can write WKL0 as RCA0 + φ. If WKL0 were Π 1 1-axiomatizable, then there would be a Π 1 1 theory T such that T is equivalent to WKL0. Since RCA0 is finitely axiomatizable, RCA0 + φ is equivalent to a single sentence that, by compactness, is provable in a finite subtheory of T that can be conjoined into a single sentence ψ. Hence RCA0 proves the equivalence of ψ and φ. Since WKL0 proves ψ, it follows by Harrington’s conservation result that RCA0 proves ψ, and thus that RCA0 proves φ, contradicting the fact that WKL0 is properly stronger than RCA0. For WKL0 + the argument is similar, using Brown and Simpson’s result instead.

References

  1. Arana, Andrew. “Logical and semantic purity.” Protosociology, 25 (2008): 36–48. Reprinted in Philosophy of Mathematics: Set Theory, Measuring Theories, and Nominalism. Edited by Gerhard Preyer and Georg Peter. Frankfurt: Ontos, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  2. ———. “Purity in arithmetic: Some formal and informal issues.” In Formalism and Beyond. On the Nature of Mathematical Discourse, edited by Godehard Link, 315–335. Boston: de Gryuter, 2014.

    Google Scholar 

  3. ———. “Imagination in mathematics.” In The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination, edited by Amy Kind, chapter 34, pages 463–477. London: Routledge, 2016.

    Google Scholar 

  4. ———. “Elementarity and purity.” In Analytic Philosophy and the Foundations of Mathematics. Edited by Andrew Arana and Carlos Alvarez. Palgrave/Macmillan, Forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Arana, Andrew, and Paolo Mancosu. “On the relationship between plane and solid geometry.” Review of Symbolic Logic 5, no. 2 (2012): 294–353.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Jeremy Avigad. “Formalizing forcing arguments in subsystems of second-order arithmetic.” Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 82 (1996): 165–191.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. ———. “Number theory and elementary arithmetic.” Philosophia Mathematica 11 (2003): 257–284.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. ———. “Mathematical method and proof.” Synthese 153, no. 1 (2006): 105–159.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Brown, Douglas K. and Stephen G. Simpson. “The Baire category theorem in weak subsystems of second-order arithmetic.” Journal of Symbolic Logic 58, no. 2 (1993): 557–578.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Caldon, Patrick, and Aleksandar Ignjatovic. “On mathematical instrumentalism.” Journal of Symbolic Logic 70, no. 3 (2005): 778–794.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Cornaros, Charalampos, and Costas Dimitracopoulos. “The prime number theorem and fragments of PA.” Archive for Mathematical Logic 33, no. 4 (1994): 265–281.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. d’Alembert, Jean Le Rond. “Application de l’algebre ou de l’analyse à la géométrie.” In editors, Encyclopédie ou Dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, volume 1. Edited by Denis Diderot and Jean Le Rond d’Alembert. Paris: Briasson, David, Le Breton, and Durand, 1751.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Dean, Walter. “Computational Complexity Theory.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by Edward N. Zalta. Fall 2015 edition, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Descartes, René. “La géométrie.” In Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison et chercher la vérité dans les sciences, 297–413. Leiden: Jan Maire, 1637.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Detlefsen, Michael. “On an alleged refutation of Hilbert’s program using Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 19, no. 4 (1990): 343–377.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. ———. “Philosophy of mathematics in the twentieth century.” In Philosophy of Science, Logic, and Mathematics, volume 9 of Routledge History of Philosophy, 50–123. Edited by Stuart G. Shanker. London: Routledge, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Detlefsen, Michael, and Andrew Arana. “Purity of methods.” Philosophers’ Imprint 11, no. 2 (2011): 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  18. de la Vallée Poussin, Charles. “Recherches analytiques sur la théorie des nombres premiers.” Annales de la Socièté Scientifique de Bruxelles 20 (1896): 183–256. Reprinted in Collected Works Volume 1. Edited by P. Butzer, J. Mawhin, and P. Vetro, Académie Royale de Belgique and Circolo Matematico di Palermo, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Edmonds, Jack. “Paths, trees, and flowers.” Canadian Journal of Mathematics 17 (1965): 449–467.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Erdős, Paul. “On a new method in elementary number theory which leads to an elementary proof of the prime number theorem.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA 35 (1949): 374–384.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Fortnow, Lance, and Steve Homer. “A short history of computational complexity.” Bulletin of the European Association for Theoretical Computer Science 80 (2003): 95–133.

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Ferraro, Giovanni, and Marco Panza. “Lagrange’s theory of analytical functions and his ideal of purity of method.” Archive for History of Exact Sciences 66, no. 2 (2011): 95–197.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  23. Friedman, Harvey M. “Systems of second order arithmetic with restricted induction. I.” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 41, no. 2 (1976): 557–8.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Granville, Andrew. “Analytic Number Theory.” In The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Edited by Timothy Gowers, June Barrow-Green, and Imre Leader. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Guicciardini, Niccolò. Isaac Newton on Mathematical Certainty and Method. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Hadamard, Jacques. “Sur la distribution des zéros de la fonction ζ(s) et ses conséquences arithmétiques.” Bulletin de la Société Mathématique de France. 24 (1896):199–220.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. ———. The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field. Princeton: Princeton University Press,1945.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  28. Hájek, Petr. “Interpretability and fragments of arithmetic.” In Arithmetic, proof theory, and computational complexity. Edited by Peter Clote and Jan Krajícek. 185–196. New York: Oxford University Press, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Hallett, Michael. “Reflections on the purity of method in Hilbert’s Grundlagen der Geometrie.” In The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Edited by Paolo Mancosu. 198–255. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Hilbert, David. Grundlagen der Geometrie. Leipzig: B.G. Teubner, 1899.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  31. ———. “On the infinite.” In From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Edited by Jean van Heijenoort. 367–392. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Hölder, Otto. “Über den Casus Irreducibilis bei der Gleichung dritten Grades.” Mathematische Annalen 38 (1892): 307–312.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  33. Hale, Bob, and Crispin Wright. The Reason’s Proper Study: Essays towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Ignjatovic, Aleksandar. “Fragments of First and Second Order Arithmetic and Length of Proofs.” PhD diss., University of California, Berkeley, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Jorgensen, Palle. “Source of Jacques Hadamard quote.” http://www.cs.uiowa.edu/~jorgen/hadamardquotesource.html, December 2015.

  36. Kaye, Richard. Models of Peano Arithmetic. New York: Oxford University Press, 1991.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  37. Klein, Felix. Elementary Mathematics from an Advanced Standpoint. Geometry. New York: Dover, 1953. Translated from the third German edition by E. R. Hedrick and C. A. Noble, New York: Macmillan, 1939.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  38. Kreisel, Georg. “Kurt Gödel.” Biographical Memoirs of Fellows of the Royal Society 26 (1980): 149–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Lagrange, Joseph-Louis. “Leçons sur mathematiques elementaires.” In Oeuvres de Lagrange, volume VII. Edited by Joseph-Alfred Serret. Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1876.

    Google Scholar 

  40. MacLaurin, Colin. A Treatise of Fluxions. Edinburgh: Ruddimans, 1742.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Maronne, Sébastien. “Pascal versus Descartes on geometrical problem solving and the Sluse-Pascal correspondence.” Early Science and Medicine 15 (2010): 537–565.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  42. Mathias, A. R. D. “A term of length 4,523,659,424,929. Synthese 133, no. 1–2 (2002): 75–86.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  43. McLarty, Colin. “What Does It Take To Prove Fermat’s Last Theorem? Grothendieck and the Logic of Number Theory.” The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16, no. 3 (2010): 359–377.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  44. Newton, Isaac. Universal arithmetick. London: J. Senex, W. Taylor, T. Warner, and J. Osborn, London, 1720. Reprinted in The mathematical works of Isaac Newton, Vol. II, edited by Derek T. Whiteside, Johnson, New York: Reprint Corp., 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Mathias, A. R. D.. “Geometria curvilinea.” In The Mathematical Papers of Isaac Newton. Vol. IV: 1664–1666, edited by D.T. Whiteside, 420–484. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Painlevé, Paul. “Analyse des travaux scientifiques.” In Oeuvres de Paul Painlevé, volume 1. Paris: CNRS, 1972. Originally published by Gauthier-Villars, 1900.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Parsons, Charles. “On a number-theoretic choice scheme and its relation to induction.” In Intuitionism and Proof Theory, edited by A. Kino, John Myhill, and Richard Eugene Vesley, 459–473. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Parikh, Rohit. “Existence and feasibility in arithmetic.” Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (1971): 494–508.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  49. Michael Potter, Michael. Set theory and its philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Pycior, Helena M. Symbols, impossible numbers, and geometric entanglements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  51. Rider Robin E. A Bibliography of Early Modern Algebra, 1500–1800, volume VII of Berkeley Papers in History of Science. Berkeley: Office for History of Science and Technology, University of California, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Selberg, Atle. “An elementary proof of the prime-number theorem.” Annals of Mathematics 50 (1949): 305–313.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  53. Simpson, Stephen G. “Partial realizations of Hilbert’s Program.” The Journal of Symbolic Logic 53, no. 2 (1988): 349–363.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Rider Robin E.. Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Berlin: Springer, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Sudac, Olivier. “The prime number theorem is PRA-provable.” Theoretical Computer Science 257 (2001): 185–239.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  56. Tait, William W. “Finitism.” The Journal of Philosophy 78, no. 9 (1981): 524–546.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Wright, Crispin. “Is Hume’s Principle Analytic?” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40, no. 1 (1999): 6–30.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  58. Yokoyama, Keita. “On Π 1 1 conservativity for Π 2 1 theories in second order arithmetic.” In Proceedings of the 10th Asian logic conference, Kobe, Japan, September 1–6, 2008, edited by Toshiyasu Arai et. al., 375–386. Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Walter Dean, Michael Detlefsen, Sébastien Maronne, Mitsuhiro Okada, Marco Panza, and Sean Walsh for helpful discussions on these subjects.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew Arana .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Arana, A. (2017). On the Alleged Simplicity of Impure Proof. In: Kossak, R., Ording, P. (eds) Simplicity: Ideals of Practice in Mathematics and the Arts. Mathematics, Culture, and the Arts. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53385-8_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics