Skip to main content

What Do Proper Names Refer to?

The Simple Sentence Puzzle and Identity Statements

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence (JSAI-isAI 2015)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNAI,volume 10091))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 1235 Accesses

Abstract

The purpose of this paper is to solve the simple sentence puzzle about proper names. (1) Superman leaps more tall buildings than Clark Kent. (2) Superman = Clark Kent. (3) Superman leaps more tall buildings than Superman. Even when (1) and (2) are true, (3) is false. It will be shown that this is not a real puzzle, because (i) (1) and (3) do not express singular propositions, and (ii) the identity statement in (2) only concerns singular propositions. In (1) and (3), the proper names refer to aspects of an individual at the level of explicature, while identity statements of the form X = Y mean that Y can be substituted for X salva veritate, only in singular propositions about X /Y. Given this difference in reference between (1)/(3) and (2), the conjunction of (1) and (2) does not entail (3), in accordance with our intuition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Even if (i) and (ii) are true, (iii) can be false. (i) John believes that Cicero was a great orator. (ii) Cicero = Tully (iii) John believes that Tully was a great orator. Similarly, the truth of (ii) and (iv) does not entail that of (v). (iv) John wants to meet Cicero. (v) John wants to meet Tully.

  2. 2.

    “Aspects” are also called “(temporal) phases” or “modes of personification”.

  3. 3.

    This is consistent with Wittgenstein’s remark ([28]: 3.3): “Nur der Satz hat Sinn: nur im Zuzammenhange des Satzes hat ein Name Bedeutung.” (Only propositions have sense. Only in the nexus of a proposition does a name have sense.) This view sharply contrasts with descriptivism whereby the name Romulus, for example, is interpreted as a truncated description such as “a person who did such-and-such things, who killed Remus, and founded Rome” ([21]: 79).

  4. 4.

    This is an application of the Optionality Criterion given by Recanati (2004: 101): “Whenever a contextual ingredient of content is provided through a pragmatic process of the optional variety, we can imagine another possible context of utterance in which no such ingredient is provided yet the utterance expresses a complete proposition.”

  5. 5.

    The semantic approach we have seen in 3.1 above interprets Superman and Clark Kent in (15–16) as standard names, that is, as Superman (+) and Clark Kent (+).

  6. 6.

    Yoshiki Nishimura (University of Tokyo) and Sayaka Hasegawa (Seikei University) object to this observation by saying that (1) and (4) express different propositions depending on whether the interpreters are enlightened or not, to the extent that unenlightened people’s construal of Superman is different from enlightened people’s (p.c., 2015). Here the term ‘construal’ is taken from Cognitive Linguistics [12]. This view, however, is incompatible with the Millian view on proper names as assumed in this paper, because it forces us to consider that the truth-conditional meaning of a proper name consists of an individual as well as its construal. If, on the contrary, the construal is taken to be external to the truth-condition of the proposition in which the name occurs, enlightened and unenlightened speakers can, as against Nishimura and Hasegawa’s claim, fully entertain one and the same proposition, no matter how different their construal of the name may be.

  7. 7.

    Wittgenstein summarizes the nature of the puzzle raised by identity statements as follows ([28]: 5.5303, emphases in the original): “Beiläufig gesprochen: Von zwei Dingen zu sagen, sie seien identisch, ist ein Unsinn, und von Einem zu sagen, es sei identisch mit sich selbst, sagt gar nichts.” (Roughly speaking, to say of two things that they are identical is nonsense, and to say of one thing that it is identical with itself is to say nothing at all.) As will be shown below, the definition given in (17) enables us to solve the puzzle.

  8. 8.

    In the approach defended here, sentences of the form X is Y as in (2) and sentences of the form X is (not) X as in (21–22) receive different interpretations. While the latter present the speakers’ subjective view on extra-linguistic states of affairs, the former correspond to metalinguistic comments on the substitutivity of the terms X and Y as articulated in (17).

References

  1. Barbar, A.: A pragmatic treatment of simple sentences. Analysis 60, 300–308 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Bloom, P.: How Children Learn the Meanings of Words. The MIT Press, Cambridge (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Braun, D., Saul, J.: Simple sentences, substitutions, and mistaken evaluation. Philos. Stud. 111, 1–41 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Evans, G.: The Varieties of Reference. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Forbes, G.: How much substitutivity? Analysis 57, 109–113 (1997)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Forbes, G.: Enlightened semantics for simple sentences. Analysis 59, 86–91 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Frege, G.: Begriffsschrift. Nebert, Halle (1879)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Frege, G.: Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophische Kritik 100, 25–50 (1892)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Fujikawa, N.: Namae ni Nan no Imi ga Arunoka (What’s in a Name?: Philosophy of Proper Names). Keisoushobou (in Japanese) (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Grice, P.: Studies in the Way of Words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Koyama, T., Nakayama, Y.: The simple sentence puzzle and ambiguous co-referential names. Ann. Jpn. Assoc. Philos. Sci. 10(3), 127–138 (2001)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Langacker, R.W.: Cognitive Grammar. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. Locke, J.: An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Penguin Classics (1997 [1689])

    Google Scholar 

  14. Lycan, W.G.: Philosophy of Language: A Contemporary Introduction, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Mill, J.S.: A System of Logic. Longmans, London (1843)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Moore, J.: Saving substitutivity in simple sentences. Analysis 59, 91–105 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Moore, J.: Did clinton lie? Analysis 60, 250–254 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Noya, S.: Katarienu Mono Wo Kataru (Speaking the Unspeakable). Koudansha (in Japanese) (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Recanati, F.: Direct Reference: From Language to Thought. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Recanati, F.: Literal Meaning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Russell, B.: The Philosophy of Logical Atomism and Other Essays 1914-19 (The collected papers of Bertrand Russell 8). Allen & Unwin Ltd, London (1956)

    Google Scholar 

  22. Sakai, T.: L’énigme des énoncés d’identité de type « a = b » : Une solution grammaticale. Langue et littérature françaises 101, 23–37 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Sakai, T.: Contextualizing tautologies: from radical pragmatics to meaning eliminativism. Engl. Linguist. 29–1, 38–68 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Sato, N.: Retorikku No Kigouron (Semiotics of Rhetoric). Koudansha (in Japanese) (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Saul, J.: Substitutions and simple sentences. Analysis 57, 102–108 (1997)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Saul, J.: Substitution, simple sentence, and sex scandals. Analysis 59, 106–112 (1999)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Saul, J.: Simple Sentences, Substitution, and Intuitions. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2007)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  28. Wittgenstein, L.: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Routledge & Kegan Paul, Side-by-side-by side edition at https://people.umass.edu/klement/tlp/ (1922)

  29. Wittgenstein, L.: Philosophische Untersuchungen. In: Anscombe, G.E.M. (ed.) Philosophical Investigations. Basil Blackwell, Oxford (1953)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Daisuke Bekki (Ochanomizu University/JST CREST/National Institute of Informatics), who kindly gave me the opportunity to present this paper at LENLS 12, held at Keio University, Yokohama, Japan, on November 15–17 2015. This work was supported by JSPS KAKENHI Grant Number 25370437.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tomohiro Sakai .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this paper

Cite this paper

Sakai, T. (2017). What Do Proper Names Refer to?. In: Otake, M., Kurahashi, S., Ota, Y., Satoh, K., Bekki, D. (eds) New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence. JSAI-isAI 2015. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 10091. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50953-2_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50953-2_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-50952-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-50953-2

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics