Skip to main content

Feigl, Sellars, and the Idea of a “Pure Pragmatics”

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Logical Empiricism and Pragmatism

Part of the book series: Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook ((VCIY,volume 19))

Abstract

In the “Personal Postscript” to his seminal essay “Existential Hypothesis”, Herbert Feigl declares:

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For an extended discussion of Feigl ’s attempt at a reconciliation of realism and empiricism, see Neuber 2011.

  2. 2.

    There is little doubt that someone like Otto Neurath (himself a self-declared defender of the logical empiricist idea) would not have accepted this purely formalist point of view; but this would be a discussion for another day.

  3. 3.

    Or, as Sellars writes at another place: “‘[T]oken’ is a meta-linguistic predicate, and is used properly when it is said that the state of affairs designated by one expression in a language is a token of another (perhaps the same) expression in the language.” (Sellars [1948] 1949, p. 440).

  4. 4.

    At one place, he explicitly declares: “Not that coherence is the definition of truth. The point is rather that the Idealistic conception of coherence has its contribution to make to the theory of meaning, confirmation, and truth.” (Sellars [1948] 1949, p. 443).

  5. 5.

    Thus in “Pure Pragmatics and Epistemology,” Sellars writes: “[W]hat can be clarified is the notion of one item in a world being in a formal sense about another item in the same world, which in turn has some direct or indirect relation to the same world. It is a matter of the same world as, and not of the world tout court.” (Sellars 1947a, p. 201). Moreover, in “Realism and the New Way of Words,” Sellars introduces the fictional character of an omniscient being (called ‘Jones’) that has, by definition, knowledge of THE (one and only) world, but which according to Sellars serves only as an illustrative contrast to the – only relevant – common empirical language user.

  6. 6.

    Let it be noted, though, that Sellars ’s conception of a ‘world story’ bears strong similarities with Kasimir Ajdukiewicz’s notion of a “world-perspective.” Ajdukiewicz had introduced this notion in an article for the journal Erkenntnis in 1939 and Sellars had translated that article for the volume Readings in Philosophical Analysis, which he and Feigl published in 1949 (see Ajdukiewicz 1949).

  7. 7.

    It is pretty clear that Sellars takes his bearings here from the logical empiricist agenda in its post-verificationist (liberalized) stage. See, in this connection, Carnap (1936/37) and especially Hempel (1950). See further the reconstruction in Uebel 2007, ch. 10.

  8. 8.

    It might be objected that there are many cases in which indexicals do not occur. Take, for example, the measurement statement ‘The temperature rises from 24, 37 °C to 29, 53 °C in the bomb calorimeter’. Here, we find no explicit use of indexicals. However, implicitly it is this specific bomb calorimeter in which at a specific point of time now at a specific place here the temperature rises from 25, 37 °C to 29, 53 °C.

  9. 9.

    In his seminal Space and Time in Contemporary Physics, Schlick characterized this method as follows: “In order to fix a point in space, one must somehow, directly or indirectly, point to it […], that is, one establishes a spatio-temporal coincidence of two otherwise separate elements. And it now turns out that these coincidences always occur in agreement for all intuitive spaces of different senses and all individuals; precisely so is an objective ‘point,’ independent of individual experiences and valid for all, thereby defined.” (Schlick [1917] 1979, pp. 262–63) For an excellent discussion of Schlick ’s method of coincidences (and its – Einsteinian – scientific context), see Howard 1999.

  10. 10.

    See Schlick [1918] 1974, p. 275: “[A]ll measurement, from the most primitive to the most sophisticated, rests on the observation of spatio-temporal coincidences.”

  11. 11.

    Thanks to Thomas Uebel for a very helpful comment concerning the main idea of this paper.

References

  • Ajdukiewicz, Kasimir. 1949. The Scientific World-Perspective. In Readings in Philosophical Analysis, ed. H. Feigl and W. Sellars, 182–188. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, Rudolf. 1928. Der Logische aufbau der Welt. Berlin: Bernary.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1936/37. Testability and Meaning. In Philosophy of Science 3: 419–471 and 4: 1–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1942. Introduction to Semantics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carus, André. 2004. Carnap and Twntieth-Century Thought: Explication as Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, Herbert. [1943] 1949. Logical Empiricism. In Readings in Philosophical Analysis, ed. H. Feigl and W. Sellars, 3–26. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1950a. Existential Hypotheses. Philosophy of Science 17: 35–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1950b. Logical Reconstruction, Realism and Pure Semiotics. Philosophy of Science 17: 186–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. [1954] 1981. Scientific Method Without Metaphysical Presuppositions. In Inquiries and Provocations: Selected Writings, 1929–1974, ed. R.S. Cohen, 95–106. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1967. The “Mental” and the “Physical”: The Essay and a Postscript. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. [1971] 1981. Some Crucial Issues on Mind-Body Monism. In Inquiries and Provocations: Selected Writings, 1929–1974, ed. R.S. Cohen, 351–365. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Nelson. 1978. Ways of Worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidelberger, Michael. 2003. The Mind-Body Problem in the Origin of Logical Empiricism: Herbert Feigl and Psychophysical Parallelism. In Logical Empiricism: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives, ed. P. Parrini, W.S. Salmon, and M.H. Salmon, 232–262. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl G. 1950. Problems and Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of Meaning. Revue International de Philosophie 4: 41–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, Don. 1999. Point Coincidences and Pointer Coincidences: Einstein on Invariant Structure in Spacetime Theories. In The History of General Relativity IV: The Expanding Worlds of General Relativity, ed. H. Goenner, J. Renn, J. Ritter, and T. Sauer, 463–500. Boston: Birkhäuser.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, David. 1989. Demonstratives. In Themes from Kaplan, ed. J. Almog, J. Perry, and H. Wettstein, 481–563. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Ernest (1948). Review: Wilfrid Sellars, Epistemology and the New Way of Words, Realism and the New Way of Words. Journal of Symbolic Logic 13: 222–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1950. Science and Semantic Realism. Philosophy of Science 17: 174–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neuber, Matthias. 2011. Feigl’s ‘Scientific Realism’. Philosophy of Science 78: 165–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014a. Is Logical Empiricism Compatible with Scientific Realism? In European Philosophy of Science: Philosophy of Science in Europe and the Viennese Heritage, ed. M.C. Galavotti, E. Nemeth, and F. Stadler, 249–262. Dordrecht/Heidelberg/New York/London: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014b. Herbert Feigl. In ed. E. Zalta, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/feigl.

  • Putnam, Hilary. 1977. Realism and Reason. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 50: 483–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, Hans. 1938. Experience and Prediction: An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz. [1917] 1979. Space and Time in Contemporary Physics. In Philosophical Papers vol. 1 (1909–1922), ed. H.L. Mulder and B. van de Velde-Schlick, 207269, Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. [1918] 1974. General Theory of Knowledge. Trans. A.E. Blumberg. Wien/New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, Wilfrid. 1947a. Pure Pragmatics and Epistemology. Philosophy of Science 14: 181–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1947b. Epistemology and the new way of Words. The Journal of Philosophy 44: 645–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. [1948] 1949. Realism and the new way of Words. In Readings in Philosophical Analysis, ed. H. Feigl and W. Sellars, 424–456. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1963. Empiricism and Abstract Entities. In The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, ed. P.A. Schilpp, 431–468. La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1975. Autobiographical Reflections. In Action, Knowledge, and Reality: Critical Studies in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars, ed. W. Sellars and H.-N. Castañeda, 273–299. Indianapolis: Bobb-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stubenberg, Leopold. 1997. Austria vs. Australia: Two Versions of the Identity Theory. In Austrian Philosophy: Past and Present, ed. K. Lehrer and J.C. Marek, 125–146. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, Alfred. 1944. The Semantic Conception of Truth: And the Foundations of Semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 4: 341–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, Thomas. 2007. Empiricism at the Crossroads: The Vienna Circle’s Protocol-Sentence Debate. Chicago/La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, Bas C. 1980. The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthias Neuber .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Neuber, M. (2017). Feigl, Sellars, and the Idea of a “Pure Pragmatics”. In: Pihlström, S., Stadler, F., Weidtmann, N. (eds) Logical Empiricism and Pragmatism. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, vol 19. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50730-9_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics