Skip to main content

French’s Influence on the Modern Discussion of Corporate Criminal Liability: The Case of Corporate Citizenship and Corporate Compliance

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Reflections on Ethics and Responsibility
  • 390 Accesses

Abstract

Peter French’s writings on corporate responsibility have greatly influenced the discussion of corporate criminal liability. Though heavily criticized at the time for his views supporting that corporations were “full-fledged moral persons” and have whatever privileges, rights and duties as are, in the normal course of affairs, accorded to moral persons (French, Am Philos Q 16:207, 1979) recent developments in the area of corporate criminal liability have supported some of his visionary statements. This paper contends that the precursory contributions of French’s can be clearly observed in the modern discussion of corporate criminal liability. This is not to say, of course, that legislators around the world have tried to implement the normative concepts laid out by Peter French, but that he was able to capture, at a very early stage, some of the key concepts that, with time, have proven to be the nuts and bolts of corporate criminal liability.

In order to accomplish this task we pick to distinct features of French’s theory i.e., corporations as “full-fledged moral persons” and the “Corporate Internal Decision-making [CID] Structure”, and compare those with two key concepts in the modern discussion on corporate criminal liability: “corporate citizenship” and “compliance programs”. In this sense, corporate citizenship rights and the reciprocal duties are on the rise: corporations enjoy greater fundamental rights, and also face increasing duties, especially in the area of corporate criminal liability. Far from receding, corporate criminal liability is spreading worldwide and, in this context, corporate citizenship functions as a double-edged sword: for one, the more corporations are viewed as citizens of our society, the more they have the “right to be punished” in Hegelian terms; for another, such corporate punishment should be imposed on the basis of what the corporation has done or failed to do, and not on the grounds of what others, i.e., natural persons, have performed on their behalf.

It is here that corporate compliance developments play a key role: compliance programs are increasingly considered as a valid defense against corporate criminal liability. Correspondingly, corporate culpability is determined on the basis of such compliance programs. Peter French’s arguments on the CID Structure nicely dovetail with the modern approach to corporate compliance. As French acknowledged in 1996, corporate integrity – which would amount to a lack of corporate culpability – is based on a “… compliance system, and an active ethics officer plugged into the CID Structure in a significant way” (French, Am Business Law J 34:153, 1996). The recently issued ISO 19600 international standard on Compliance Managements Systems (Guidelines) reveals the importance of plugging into the CID structure compliance procedures that support the overall compliance culture within the corporation.

Finally, and leaving the legal arena, it is worth noting that, from a philosophical perspective, French’s position on corporate responsibility is consistent with operative constructivism as portrayed by Niklas Luhmann (Theories of distinction: Redescribing the descriptions of modernity. Stanford University Press, Stanford, 2002, 128), and developed for the corporate law world by Gunther Teubner (Am J Comp Law 36:130, 1988a, 43). Conceiving of corporations as self-producing and autonomous entities advances, from another perspective, French’s findings in this area.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a interesting comparative law perspective, see Dubber (2013).

  2. 2.

    Anonymous, 88 Eng. Rep. 1518 (K.B. 1701). However, almost a hundred years before that statement, in the case of Sutton’s Hospital [77 Eng. Rep. 960, 973 (K.B. 1612)] the following statement was noted: corporations “cannot commit treason, nor be outlawed, nor excommunicate, for they have no souls, neither can they appear in person, but by attorney”.

  3. 3.

    Interestingly enough, the actual quote seems to be “Corporations have neither bodies to be punished nor souls to be condemned; they therefore do as they like”. Therefore, if punishment is not equaled to bodily punishment or soul condemnation, the potential punishment of corporations could be argued.

  4. 4.

    For a recent account see the contributions in Pieth, Mark and Radha Ivory eds, (2011b) and Gobert and Pascal (2011).

  5. 5.

    See the contributions Pieth, Mark and Radha Ivory eds. (2011a). Gobert and Pascal (2011). See also Corporate Culture as a Basis for the Criminal Liability of Corporations (2008).

  6. 6.

    Persons with diminished capacity are what French et al. (1992), term as “moral patients”. “This category would include young children, the mentally impaired, animal, even trees and other parts of the natural environment.” The key here is to note how criminal law deals with such “moral patients” when “full-fledged members of the moral community” act on their behalf: the legal systems does not impose a criminal sanction on those moral patients, but on the full-fledged member of the moral community. Therefore, if criminal law imposes criminal sanctions on corporations, it is not treating corporations as moral patients, but as full-fledged members of the moral community.

  7. 7.

    As French himself acknowledged in French (1984), Preface, X: at the time “The burden of proof should fall on the revisionist, on those of us who would argue that corporations should be admitted to full-membership in the moral community.” However, given that most there has been an expansion of legislation introducing corporate criminal liability, it is fair to reverse the burden of proof: if corporate criminal liability is related to being considered a full-fledged member of the moral community, and corporate criminal liability is a world-wide phenomenon, the “contra-revisionists” should have the burden of proof and therefore explain why corporate criminal liability is a century-old mistake. See, consequently, Hasnas (2009).

  8. 8.

    Javier Cigüela has recently coined the term “Meta-Subject” to refer to French’s “conglomerates”. See Cigüela (forthcoming).

  9. 9.

    For a recent overall account of this connection see Pawlik (2012) and Pawlik (2004) (an interesting English review of this book is found in Kaiser 2006). Modern accounts noting various perspectives in Duff (2013), Dubber (2010), and Ramsay (2006). For a broader perspective see Farmer (2014).

  10. 10.

    See Dubber (2010).

  11. 11.

    Not surprisingly, some jurisdictions distinguish between citizens (in broad terms) and aliens in order to adequate the State’s response to their actions. For instance, certain jurisdictions contain rules substituting prison sanctions for deportation in case of crimes perpetrated by aliens. Other jurisdictions, such as the US, “diminish” the citizenship status of convicted felons by way of systematically depriving them of their voting rights, which leaves them in a “permanent state of second class citizenship” (Fletcher 2006).

  12. 12.

    For an overview, see Adler (2000).

  13. 13.

    Friedman (2000). See also Kahan (1998) and Buell (2006).

  14. 14.

    Explanatory: “A CID Structure subordinates and synthesizes the intentions and actions of various human persons (and even the behavior of machines) into a corporate action. What I mean by that is that the CID Structure not only organizes the various human beings in the system into a decision-making and acting entity, it makes it possible for us and those within the structure to describe what is happening as corporate. In the absence of the structure, the various activities of the humans and machines would be utterly unintelligible”.

  15. 15.

    US Sentencing Commission, US Sentencing Guidelines, Chapter 8 (1991). See Paula Desio, Deputy General Counsel, US Sentencing Commission, An Overview of the Organizational Guidelines, [available at: http://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf/training/organizational-guidelines/ORGOVERVIEW.pdf].

  16. 16.

    See Principles of Federal Prosecution of Business Organizations (June 1999). Attorney General Eric Holder.

  17. 17.

    See Gruner (2005) and Orland (2004).

  18. 18.

    See from various perspectives Bucy (1991), Laufer (1994), Lederman (2000), Quaid (1998), and Moore (1992). See generally Laufer (2006).

  19. 19.

    See Gruner and Brown (1996). “For purposes of corporate law compliance programs, high quality performance is performance that meets the stated or implied demands of various laws. A “quality system” aimed at maximizing law compliance is comprised of organizational structures, assigned responsibilities, procedures, processes, and resources that a corporation or other organization devotes to the pursuit of law compliance. These corporate resources should be applied to ensure that corporate employees act lawfully in carrying out tasks as corporate agents” (752).

  20. 20.

    http://www.iso.org/iso/home/store/catalogue_tc/catalogue_detail.htm?csnumber=62342. See generally Bleker and Hortensius (2014).

  21. 21.

    See generally Gómez-Jara (2011).

  22. 22.

    Podgor (2007) (noting the urgency for an affirmative defense based on corporate compliance programs); Weismann and Newman (2007) and Gruner and Brown (1996) (due diligence test for corporate criminal liability; Walsh and Pyrich (1995)).

  23. 23.

    See French (2011, 272–273).

  24. 24.

    See among others Bottke (1997, 1995), Heine (1995), Lampe (1994), Lütolf (1997), and Rotsch (1998); Schünemann has adopted as a “bedrock principle the theory of autopoietic systems” (Schünemann 1996, 132); Schünemann contends that “the only theory available to justify a true corporate criminal law is systems theory” (Schünemann 1999, 230).

  25. 25.

    See Luhmann (1996). For an outstanding introduction to this social theory, see Rasch (2000).

  26. 26.

    On operative constructivism, see Luhmann (2002).

  27. 27.

    See Luhmann (2008) and Teubner (1993a). For the specifics on organizations as autopoietic systems, see Luhmann (2000).

  28. 28.

    See in Bottke (1995, 48–63), Heine (1998, 217).

  29. 29.

    See Teubner (1993a, 28, b, 1988a, b).

  30. 30.

    Explaining that an autopoietic social system is “a system of actions/communications that reproduces itself by constantly producing from the network of its elements as new communications/actions” (Teubner 1988a).

  31. 31.

    See the explanatory graphic in Teubner (1988b, 115).

  32. 32.

    On corporate decision as a basis for organizational systems, see Teubner (1989).

  33. 33.

    See Teubner (1988a, 140).

References

  • Adler, Matthew D. 2000. Expressive theories of law: A skeptical overview. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 148: 1363–1501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleker, Sylvie, and Dirk Hortensius. 2014. ISO 19600: The development of a global standard on compliance management, Business Compliance 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottke, Wilfried. 1995. Assoziationsprävention: Zur heutigen Diskussion der Strafzwecke. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Standortvorteil Wirtschaftskriminalrecht: Müssen Unternehmen “strafmündig” werden? Bermerkungen zum Stand des Wirtschaftskriminalrechts in der Bundesrepublik Deutschland. Wistra: 241–253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bucy, Pamela. 1991. Corporate Ethos: A standard for imposing corporate criminal liability. Minnesota Law Review 75: 1095.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buell, Samuel W. 2006. The blaming function of entity criminal liability. Indiana Law Journal 81: 473–537.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cigüela, Javier. Collective organizations as meta-subjects. Zeitschrift für Internationale Strafrechtsdogmatik (forthcoming).

    Google Scholar 

  • De Maglie, Cristina. 2011. Italy. In European developments in corporate Criminal Liability, ed. James Gobert and Ana-Maria Pascal, 252. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubber, Markus D. 2010. Citizenship and penal law. New Criminal Law Review 13: 190–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. The comparative history and theory of corporate criminal liability. New Criminal Law Review 16: 203–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R.A. 2013. Responsibility, citizenship and criminal law. In Philosophical foundations of criminal law, ed. R.A. Duff and Stuart Green. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farmer, Lindsay. 2014. Making the modern criminal law: Criminalization and civil order. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feuerbach, Paul Anselm. 1818. Lehrbuch des gemeinen in Deuschtland gültigen peinlichen Rechts. 6th ed. Gießen: Heyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, George P. 2006. Political theory and criminal law. Criminal Justice Ethics 25: 18–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, Peter A. 1979. The corporation as a moral person. American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 207–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. Collective and corporate responsibility. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Principles of responsibility, shame and the corporation. In Shame, guilt and corporate responsibility, ed. Hugh Curtler. New York: Haven Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Integrity, intentions, and corporations. American Business Law Journal 34: 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. War and moral dissonance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, Peter A., Jeffrey Nesteruk, and David T. Risser. 1992. Corporations in the moral community. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Lawrence. 2000. In defense of corporate criminal liability. Harvard Journal for Law & Public Policy 12: 833.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gobert, James, and Ana-Maria Pascal, eds. 2011. European developments in corporate criminal liability. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gómez-Jara, Carlos. 2008. Corporations as victims of mismanagement: Beyond the shareholder vs. Directors Debate, PACE Law Review 28: 795–813.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Fundamentos modernos de la responsabilidad penal de las personas jurídicas. Madrid: BdF.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Corporate culpability as a limit to the overcriminalization of corporate criminal liability: The interplay between corporate compliance, self-regulation and corporate citizenship. New Criminal Law Review 14: 78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruner, Richard. 2005. Corporate criminal liability and prevention. New York: Law Journal Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruner, Richard S., and Louis M. Brown. 1996. Organizational justice: Recognizing and rewarding the good citizen corporation. Journal of Corporate Law 21: 731.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasnas, John. 2009. The centenary of a mistake: One hundred years of corporate criminal liability. American Criminal Law Review 46: 1329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heine, Günter. 1995. Die Strafrechtliche Verantwortlichkeit von Unternehmen. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heine, Gunter. 1998. New developments in corporate criminal liability in Europe: Can Europeans learn from the American experience – or Viceversa? Saint Louis-Warsaw Transatlantic Law Journal 4: 173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, Dan M. 1998. Social meaning and the economic analysis of crime. Journal of Legal Studies 27: 609–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser, Hanno F. 2006. The three dimensions of freedom, crime, and punishment. Buffalo Criminal Law Review 9: 691.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1996. Practical philosophy (ed. and trans. Mary J. Gregor). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, Jeffrey M., Joseph E. Murphy, and Winthrop Swenson. 1998. Compliance programs and the corporate sentencing guidelines: Preventing criminal and civil liability. New York: West Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lampe, Ernst J. 1994. Systemsunrecht und Unrechtssysteme. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft 106: 690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laufer, William S. 1994. Corporate bodies and guilty minds. Emory Law Journal 43: 648–730.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Corporate bodies and guilty minds. The failure of corporate criminal. Liability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lederman, Eli. 2000. Models for imposing corporate criminal liability: From adaptation and imitation toward aggregation and the search of self-identity. Buffalo Criminal Law Review 4: 641–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, Kurt. 1952. In Field theory in social science: Selected theoretical papers by Kurt Lewin, ed. Dorwin Cartwright. New York: Harper & Brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, Niklas. 1996. Social Systems. Trans. John Bednarz & Dirk Baecker. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Organisation und Entscheidung. Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Theories of distinction: Redescribing the descriptions of modernity. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Law as a social system. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lütolf, Sandra-Hilda. 1997. Strafbarkeit der juristischen Person. Zürich: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malblanc, Julius Friedrich. 1793. observationes quaedam ad delicta universitatum spectantes, Erlangen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Jennifer. 1992. Corporate culpability under the federal sentencing guidelines. Arizona Law Review 34: 743.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orland, Leonard. 2004. Corporate criminal liability. Regulation and compliance. New York: Aspen Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pawlik, Michael. 2004. Person, Subjekt, Bürger.: Zur Legitimation von Strafe. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pawlik, Michael. 2012. Das Unrecht des Bürgers: Grundlinien der Allgemeinen Verbrechenslehre. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrow, Charles. 1989. A society of organizations. In Kultur und Gesellschaft, ed. Max Haller, Hans Joachim Hofmann-Nowotny & Wolfgang Zapf. Frankfurt/New York: Campus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pieth, Mark, and Radha Ivory, eds. 2011a. Corporate criminal liability. Emergence, convergence, and risk. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pieth, Mark & Radha Ivory, 2011b. Emergence and convergence: Corporate criminal liability principles in overview. In Corporate criminal liability. Emergence, convergence, and risk, ed. Mark Pieth & Radha Ivory, p. 35. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Podgor, Ellen P. 2007. A new corporate world mandates a “Good Faith” affirmative defense. American Criminal Law Review 44: 1537.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quaid, Jennifer A. 1998. The assessment of corporate criminal liability on the basis of corporate identity: An analysis. McGill Law Journal 43: 67–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsay, P. 2006. The responsible subject as citizen: Democracy and the welfare state. Modern Law Review 69: 29–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rasch, William. 2000. Niklas Luhmann’s mdernity: The paradoxes of differentiation. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rotsch, Thomas. 1998. Individuelle Haftung in Großunternehmen. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salvo, Nelly. 2011. Principales aspectos de la Nueva Ley de Responsabilidad penal de las Personas Jurídicas en Chile (Ley N° 20.393). In Corporate criminal liability. Emergence, convergence, and risk, ed. Mark Pieth & Radha Ivory, p. 289. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schünemann, Bernd. 1996. Art. 4: Maßnahmen gengen Unternehmen. In Deutsche Wiedervereinigung III Unternehmenskriminalität. München: heymanns.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Criticising the notion of a genuine criminal law against legal entities. In Criminal responsibility of collective and legal entities. Freiburg: Iuscrim.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teubner, Gunther. 1988a. Enterprise corporatism. New industrial policy and the “Essence” of the legal person. American Journal of Comparative Law 36: 130–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1988b). Hypercycle in law and organization: The relationship between self-observation, self-constitution and autopoiesis. In European yearbook in the sociology of law, ed. Alberto Febrajjo. Milan: Giuffrè: 43–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. How the law thinks: Toward a constructivist epistemology of law. Law & Society Review 23: 727–758.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993a. Law as an autopoietic system. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993b. The many-headed hydra: Networks as higher-order collective actors. In Corporate control and accountability. Changing structures and the dynamics of regulation, ed. Joseph McCahery, Sol Piciotto, and Colin Scott. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, Charles J., and Alissa Pyrich. 1995. Corporate compliance programs as a shield to criminal liability: Can a corporation save its soul? Rutgers Law review 47: 605–689.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weismann, Andrew, and David Newman. 2007. Rethinking criminal corporate liability. Indiana Law Journal 82: 411–451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilberforce, William. Life of Thurlow, 1783.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carlos Gómez-Jara Díez .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Díez, C.GJ. (2017). French’s Influence on the Modern Discussion of Corporate Criminal Liability: The Case of Corporate Citizenship and Corporate Compliance. In: Goldberg, Z. (eds) Reflections on Ethics and Responsibility. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50359-2_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics